메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 111, Issue 1, 2000, Pages 79-101

Was Aristotle an "Aristotelian social democrat"?

(1)  Mulgan, Richard a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0039626318     PISSN: 00141704     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1086/233420     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (38)

References (122)
  • 1
    • 61449450600 scopus 로고
    • Nature, function, and capability: Aristotle on political distribution
    • The main sources for a discussion of social democracy are Martha Nussbaum, "Nature, Function, and Capability: Aristotle on Political Distribution," Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, suppl. vol. (1988), pp. 145-84, and "Aristotelian Social Democracy," in Liberalism and the Good, ed. R. Bruce Douglass et al. (New York: Routledge, 1990), pp. 203-52. Nussbaum also canvasses Aristotle's support for liberal democracy in "Shame, Separateness, and Political Unity: Aristotle's Criticism of Plato," in Essays on Aristotle's Ethics, ed. Amelie O. Rorty (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1980), The Fragility of Goodness (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986), and Love's Knowledge: Essays in Philosophy and Literature (New York: Oxford University Press, 1990).
    • (1988) Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy , Issue.SUPPL. VOL. , pp. 145-184
    • Nussbaum, M.1
  • 2
    • 0003352586 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotelian social democracy
    • ed. R. Bruce Douglass et al. New York: Routledge
    • The main sources for a discussion of social democracy are Martha Nussbaum, "Nature, Function, and Capability: Aristotle on Political Distribution," Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, suppl. vol. (1988), pp. 145-84, and "Aristotelian Social Democracy," in Liberalism and the Good, ed. R. Bruce Douglass et al. (New York: Routledge, 1990), pp. 203-52. Nussbaum also canvasses Aristotle's support for liberal democracy in "Shame, Separateness, and Political Unity: Aristotle's Criticism of Plato," in Essays on Aristotle's Ethics, ed. Amelie O. Rorty (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1980), The Fragility of Goodness (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986), and Love's Knowledge: Essays in Philosophy and Literature (New York: Oxford University Press, 1990).
    • (1990) Liberalism and the Good , pp. 203-252
  • 3
    • 0011679017 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Shame, separateness, and political unity: Aristotle's criticism of Plato
    • ed. Amelie O. Rorty Berkeley: University of California Press
    • The main sources for a discussion of social democracy are Martha Nussbaum, "Nature, Function, and Capability: Aristotle on Political Distribution," Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, suppl. vol. (1988), pp. 145-84, and "Aristotelian Social Democracy," in Liberalism and the Good, ed. R. Bruce Douglass et al. (New York: Routledge, 1990), pp. 203-52. Nussbaum also canvasses Aristotle's support for liberal democracy in "Shame, Separateness, and Political Unity: Aristotle's Criticism of Plato," in Essays on Aristotle's Ethics, ed. Amelie O. Rorty (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1980), The Fragility of Goodness (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986), and Love's Knowledge: Essays in Philosophy and Literature (New York: Oxford University Press, 1990).
    • (1980) Essays on Aristotle's Ethics
  • 4
    • 0004275697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • The main sources for a discussion of social democracy are Martha Nussbaum, "Nature, Function, and Capability: Aristotle on Political Distribution," Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, suppl. vol. (1988), pp. 145-84, and "Aristotelian Social Democracy," in Liberalism and the Good, ed. R. Bruce Douglass et al. (New York: Routledge, 1990), pp. 203-52. Nussbaum also canvasses Aristotle's support for liberal democracy in "Shame, Separateness, and Political Unity: Aristotle's Criticism of Plato," in Essays on Aristotle's Ethics, ed. Amelie O. Rorty (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1980), The Fragility of Goodness (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986), and Love's Knowledge: Essays in Philosophy and Literature (New York: Oxford University Press, 1990).
    • (1986) The Fragility of Goodness
  • 5
    • 0004062648 scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • The main sources for a discussion of social democracy are Martha Nussbaum, "Nature, Function, and Capability: Aristotle on Political Distribution," Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, suppl. vol. (1988), pp. 145-84, and "Aristotelian Social Democracy," in Liberalism and the Good, ed. R. Bruce Douglass et al. (New York: Routledge, 1990), pp. 203-52. Nussbaum also canvasses Aristotle's support for liberal democracy in "Shame, Separateness, and Political Unity: Aristotle's Criticism of Plato," in Essays on Aristotle's Ethics, ed. Amelie O. Rorty (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1980), The Fragility of Goodness (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986), and Love's Knowledge: Essays in Philosophy and Literature (New York: Oxford University Press, 1990).
    • (1990) Love's Knowledge: Essays in Philosophy and Literature
  • 6
    • 0003905669 scopus 로고
    • Berkeley: University of California Press
    • For example, Bernard Yack, The Problems of a Political Animal (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993); Jeremy Waldron, "The Wisdom of the Multitude: Some Reflections on Book 3, Chapter 11 of Aristotle's Politics," Political Theory 23 (1995): 563-84; Susan Bickford, The Dissonance of Democracy (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1996); Arlene Saxonhouse, Athenian Democracy: Modern Mythmakers and Ancient Theories (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1996); John Uhr, Deliberative Democracy in Australia (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988).
    • (1993) The Problems of a Political Animal
    • Yack, B.1
  • 7
    • 84970763608 scopus 로고
    • The wisdom of the multitude: Some reflections on book 3, chapter 11 of Aristotle's politics
    • For example, Bernard Yack, The Problems of a Political Animal (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993); Jeremy Waldron, "The Wisdom of the Multitude: Some Reflections on Book 3, Chapter 11 of Aristotle's Politics," Political Theory 23 (1995): 563-84; Susan Bickford, The Dissonance of Democracy (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1996); Arlene Saxonhouse, Athenian Democracy: Modern Mythmakers and Ancient Theories (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1996); John Uhr, Deliberative Democracy in Australia (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988).
    • (1995) Political Theory , vol.23 , pp. 563-584
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 8
    • 0003671288 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press
    • For example, Bernard Yack, The Problems of a Political Animal (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993); Jeremy Waldron, "The Wisdom of the Multitude: Some Reflections on Book 3, Chapter 11 of Aristotle's Politics," Political Theory 23 (1995): 563-84; Susan Bickford, The Dissonance of Democracy (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1996); Arlene Saxonhouse, Athenian Democracy: Modern Mythmakers and Ancient Theories (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1996); John Uhr, Deliberative Democracy in Australia (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988).
    • (1996) The Dissonance of Democracy
    • Bickford, S.1
  • 9
    • 0004092585 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press
    • For example, Bernard Yack, The Problems of a Political Animal (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993); Jeremy Waldron, "The Wisdom of the Multitude: Some Reflections on Book 3, Chapter 11 of Aristotle's Politics," Political Theory 23 (1995): 563-84; Susan Bickford, The Dissonance of Democracy (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1996); Arlene Saxonhouse, Athenian Democracy: Modern Mythmakers and Ancient Theories (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1996); John Uhr, Deliberative Democracy in Australia (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988).
    • (1996) Athenian Democracy: Modern Mythmakers and Ancient Theories
    • Saxonhouse, A.1
  • 10
    • 0003683169 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • For example, Bernard Yack, The Problems of a Political Animal (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993); Jeremy Waldron, "The Wisdom of the Multitude: Some Reflections on Book 3, Chapter 11 of Aristotle's Politics," Political Theory 23 (1995): 563-84; Susan Bickford, The Dissonance of Democracy (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1996); Arlene Saxonhouse, Athenian Democracy: Modern Mythmakers and Ancient Theories (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1996); John Uhr, Deliberative Democracy in Australia (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988).
    • (1988) Deliberative Democracy in Australia
    • Uhr, J.1
  • 11
    • 0005901359 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Harvard University Press
    • Martha Nussbaum, Cultivating Humanity (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1997), pp. 118-20.
    • (1997) Cultivating Humanity , pp. 118-120
    • Nussbaum, M.1
  • 12
    • 0003750065 scopus 로고
    • New York: Simon & Schuster
    • Alan Bloom, The Closing of the American Mind (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1987); I. F. Stone, The Trial of Socrates (Boston: Little Brown, 1988).
    • (1987) The Closing of the American Mind
    • Bloom, A.1
  • 13
    • 0039426211 scopus 로고
    • Boston: Little Brown
    • Alan Bloom, The Closing of the American Mind (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1987); I. F. Stone, The Trial of Socrates (Boston: Little Brown, 1988).
    • (1988) The Trial of Socrates
    • Stone, I.F.1
  • 14
    • 84893234643 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 3.6.1278b32-37, (hereafter EN), 8.11.1161a32-b8
    • For slaves, the main discussion is 1.4-7, 13 (all Aristotle references are to the Politics unless otherwise indicated). See also 3.6.1278b32-37, Ethica Nicomachea (hereafter EN), 8.11.1161a32-b8; Richard Mulgan, Aristotle's Political Theory (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977), pp. 40-44; Nicholas Smith, "Aristotle's Theory of Natural Slavery," Phoenix 37 (1983): 109-22. For women, see Aristode, 1.12-13, 2.5; see also Mulgan, Aristotle's Political Theory, pp. 44-47.
    • Ethica Nicomachea
  • 15
    • 0004031434 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • For slaves, the main discussion is 1.4-7, 13 (all Aristotle references are to the Politics unless otherwise indicated). See also 3.6.1278b32-37, Ethica Nicomachea (hereafter EN), 8.11.1161a32-b8; Richard Mulgan, Aristotle's Political Theory (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977), pp. 40-44; Nicholas Smith, "Aristotle's Theory of Natural Slavery," Phoenix 37 (1983): 109-22. For women, see Aristode, 1.12-13, 2.5; see also Mulgan, Aristotle's Political Theory, pp. 44-47.
    • (1977) Aristotle's Political Theory , pp. 40-44
    • Mulgan, R.1
  • 16
    • 0040018493 scopus 로고
    • Aristotle's theory of natural slavery
    • For women, see Aristode, 1.12-13, 2.5
    • For slaves, the main discussion is 1.4-7, 13 (all Aristotle references are to the Politics unless otherwise indicated). See also 3.6.1278b32-37, Ethica Nicomachea (hereafter EN), 8.11.1161a32-b8; Richard Mulgan, Aristotle's Political Theory (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977), pp. 40-44; Nicholas Smith, "Aristotle's Theory of Natural Slavery," Phoenix 37 (1983): 109-22. For women, see Aristode, 1.12-13, 2.5; see also Mulgan, Aristotle's Political Theory, pp. 44-47.
    • (1983) Phoenix , vol.37 , pp. 109-122
    • Smith, N.1
  • 17
    • 0004031434 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For slaves, the main discussion is 1.4-7, 13 (all Aristotle references are to the Politics unless otherwise indicated). See also 3.6.1278b32-37, Ethica Nicomachea (hereafter EN), 8.11.1161a32-b8; Richard Mulgan, Aristotle's Political Theory (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977), pp. 40-44; Nicholas Smith, "Aristotle's Theory of Natural Slavery," Phoenix 37 (1983): 109-22. For women, see Aristode, 1.12-13, 2.5; see also Mulgan, Aristotle's Political Theory, pp. 44-47.
    • Aristotle's Political Theory , pp. 44-47
    • Mulgan1
  • 18
    • 0003664584 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press
    • For example, Susan Moller Okin, Women in Western Political Thought (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1979); Jean Bethke Elshtain, Public Man, Private Woman (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1982), in the case of women. Followers of the cryptographic method of Leo Strauss have interpreted Aristotle's logically flawed accounts of slavery and of the subjection of women as deliberately intended to raise doubts about the justification of these institutions: e.g., Wayne Ambler, "Aristotle on Nature and Politics: The Case of Slavery," Political Theory 15 (1987): 390-410; on slavery, Arlene Saxonhouse, "Family, Polity and Unity: Aristotle on Socrates' Community of Wives," Polity 15 (1982): 202-19; and Harold Levy, "Does Aristotle Exclude Women from Politics?" Review of Politics 52 (1990): 397-416, on women. This approach is implausible; see Richard Mulgan, "Aristotle and the Political Role of Women," History of Political Thought 15 (1994) : 179-202, "The Straussian Influence in the Interpretation of Aristotle's Politics," in History of Philosophy Yearbook, ed. Paul Thom and Udo Thiel (Canberra: Australasian Society for the History of Philosophy, 1994), pp. 219-35.
    • (1979) Women in Western Political Thought
    • Okin, S.M.1
  • 19
    • 0003850824 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press
    • For example, Susan Moller Okin, Women in Western Political Thought (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1979); Jean Bethke Elshtain, Public Man, Private Woman (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1982), in the case of women. Followers of the cryptographic method of Leo Strauss have interpreted Aristotle's logically flawed accounts of slavery and of the subjection of women as deliberately intended to raise doubts about the justification of these institutions: e.g., Wayne Ambler, "Aristotle on Nature and Politics: The Case of Slavery," Political Theory 15 (1987): 390-410; on slavery, Arlene Saxonhouse, "Family, Polity and Unity: Aristotle on Socrates' Community of Wives," Polity 15 (1982): 202-19; and Harold Levy, "Does Aristotle Exclude Women from Politics?" Review of Politics 52 (1990): 397-416, on women. This approach is implausible; see Richard Mulgan, "Aristotle and the Political Role of Women," History of Political Thought 15 (1994) : 179-202, "The Straussian Influence in the Interpretation of Aristotle's Politics," in History of Philosophy Yearbook, ed. Paul Thom and Udo Thiel (Canberra: Australasian Society for the History of Philosophy, 1994), pp. 219-35.
    • (1982) Public Man, Private Woman
    • Elshtain, J.B.1
  • 20
    • 84972685305 scopus 로고
    • Aristotle on nature and politics: The case of slavery
    • For example, Susan Moller Okin, Women in Western Political Thought (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1979); Jean Bethke Elshtain, Public Man, Private Woman (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1982), in the case of women. Followers of the cryptographic method of Leo Strauss have interpreted Aristotle's logically flawed accounts of slavery and of the subjection of women as deliberately intended to raise doubts about the justification of these institutions: e.g., Wayne Ambler, "Aristotle on Nature and Politics: The Case of Slavery," Political Theory 15 (1987): 390-410; on slavery, Arlene Saxonhouse, "Family, Polity and Unity: Aristotle on Socrates' Community of Wives," Polity 15 (1982): 202-19; and Harold Levy, "Does Aristotle Exclude Women from Politics?" Review of Politics 52 (1990): 397-416, on women. This approach is implausible; see Richard Mulgan, "Aristotle and the Political Role of Women," History of Political Thought 15 (1994) : 179-202, "The Straussian Influence in the Interpretation of Aristotle's Politics," in History of Philosophy Yearbook, ed. Paul Thom and Udo Thiel (Canberra: Australasian Society for the History of Philosophy, 1994), pp. 219-35.
    • (1987) Political Theory , vol.15 , pp. 390-410
    • Ambler, W.1
  • 21
    • 0001381824 scopus 로고
    • Family, polity and unity: Aristotle on Socrates' community of wives
    • For example, Susan Moller Okin, Women in Western Political Thought (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1979); Jean Bethke Elshtain, Public Man, Private Woman (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1982), in the case of women. Followers of the cryptographic method of Leo Strauss have interpreted Aristotle's logically flawed accounts of slavery and of the subjection of women as deliberately intended to raise doubts about the justification of these institutions: e.g., Wayne Ambler, "Aristotle on Nature and Politics: The Case of Slavery," Political Theory 15 (1987): 390-410; on slavery, Arlene Saxonhouse, "Family, Polity and Unity: Aristotle on Socrates' Community of Wives," Polity 15 (1982): 202-19; and Harold Levy, "Does Aristotle Exclude Women from Politics?" Review of Politics 52 (1990): 397-416, on women. This approach is implausible; see Richard Mulgan, "Aristotle and the Political Role of Women," History of Political Thought 15 (1994) : 179-202, "The Straussian Influence in the Interpretation of Aristotle's Politics," in History of Philosophy Yearbook, ed. Paul Thom and Udo Thiel (Canberra: Australasian Society for the History of Philosophy, 1994), pp. 219-35.
    • (1982) Polity , vol.15 , pp. 202-219
    • Saxonhouse, A.1
  • 22
    • 84976189179 scopus 로고
    • Does Aristotle exclude women from politics?
    • For example, Susan Moller Okin, Women in Western Political Thought (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1979); Jean Bethke Elshtain, Public Man, Private Woman (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1982), in the case of women. Followers of the cryptographic method of Leo Strauss have interpreted Aristotle's logically flawed accounts of slavery and of the subjection of women as deliberately intended to raise doubts about the justification of these institutions: e.g., Wayne Ambler, "Aristotle on Nature and Politics: The Case of Slavery," Political Theory 15 (1987): 390-410; on slavery, Arlene Saxonhouse, "Family, Polity and Unity: Aristotle on Socrates' Community of Wives," Polity 15 (1982): 202-19; and Harold Levy, "Does Aristotle Exclude Women from Politics?" Review of Politics 52 (1990): 397-416, on women. This approach is implausible; see Richard Mulgan, "Aristotle and the Political Role of Women," History of Political Thought 15 (1994) : 179-202, "The Straussian Influence in the Interpretation of Aristotle's Politics," in History of Philosophy Yearbook, ed. Paul Thom and Udo Thiel (Canberra: Australasian Society for the History of Philosophy, 1994), pp. 219-35.
    • (1990) Review of Politics , vol.52 , pp. 397-416
    • Levy, H.1
  • 23
    • 84937310454 scopus 로고
    • Aristotle and the political role of women
    • For example, Susan Moller Okin, Women in Western Political Thought (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1979); Jean Bethke Elshtain, Public Man, Private Woman (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1982), in the case of women. Followers of the cryptographic method of Leo Strauss have interpreted Aristotle's logically flawed accounts of slavery and of the subjection of women as deliberately intended to raise doubts about the justification of these institutions: e.g., Wayne Ambler, "Aristotle on Nature and Politics: The Case of Slavery," Political Theory 15 (1987): 390-410; on slavery, Arlene Saxonhouse, "Family, Polity and Unity: Aristotle on Socrates' Community of Wives," Polity 15 (1982): 202-19; and Harold Levy, "Does Aristotle Exclude Women from Politics?" Review of Politics 52 (1990): 397-416, on women. This approach is implausible; see Richard Mulgan, "Aristotle and the Political Role of Women," History of Political Thought 15 (1994) : 179-202, "The Straussian Influence in the Interpretation of Aristotle's Politics," in History of Philosophy Yearbook, ed. Paul Thom and Udo Thiel (Canberra: Australasian Society for the History of Philosophy, 1994), pp. 219-35.
    • (1994) History of Political Thought , vol.15 , pp. 179-202
    • Mulgan, R.1
  • 24
    • 85037767948 scopus 로고
    • The Straussian influence in the interpretation of Aristotle's politics
    • ed. Paul Thom and Udo Thiel Canberra: Australasian Society for the History of Philosophy
    • For example, Susan Moller Okin, Women in Western Political Thought (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1979); Jean Bethke Elshtain, Public Man, Private Woman (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1982), in the case of women. Followers of the cryptographic method of Leo Strauss have interpreted Aristotle's logically flawed accounts of slavery and of the subjection of women as deliberately intended to raise doubts about the justification of these institutions: e.g., Wayne Ambler, "Aristotle on Nature and Politics: The Case of Slavery," Political Theory 15 (1987): 390-410; on slavery, Arlene Saxonhouse, "Family, Polity and Unity: Aristotle on Socrates' Community of Wives," Polity 15 (1982): 202-19; and Harold Levy, "Does Aristotle Exclude Women from Politics?" Review of Politics 52 (1990): 397-416, on women. This approach is implausible; see Richard Mulgan, "Aristotle and the Political Role of Women," History of Political Thought 15 (1994) : 179-202, "The Straussian Influence in the Interpretation of Aristotle's Politics," in History of Philosophy Yearbook, ed. Paul Thom and Udo Thiel (Canberra: Australasian Society for the History of Philosophy, 1994), pp. 219-35.
    • (1994) History of Philosophy Yearbook , pp. 219-235
  • 25
    • 85037768520 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle, 2.2-5
    • Aristotle, 2.2-5.
  • 26
    • 85037767948 scopus 로고
    • The Straussian influence in the interpretation of Aristotle's politics
    • 3.12, 4.11.1296a13-18
    • Ibid., 3.12, 4.11.1296a13-18.
    • (1994) History of Philosophy Yearbook , pp. 219-235
  • 27
    • 0004056394 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, chap. 6
    • For example, Josiah Ober, Political Dissent in Classical Athens (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1998), chap. 6.
    • (1998) Political Dissent in Classical Athens
    • Ober, J.1
  • 29
    • 85037756197 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle, 3.13.1284a3-14, 7.14.1332b22-27
    • Aristotle, 3.13.1284a3-14, 7.14.1332b22-27.
  • 31
    • 0039673205 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2.9.12, 5.1.1301b29, 6.2.1317b4
    • Ibid., 2.9.12, 5.1.1301b29, 6.2.1317b4; EN 5.3.1131a27-29.
    • Areopagiticus
    • Isocrates1
  • 32
    • 85037762151 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 5.3.1131a27-29
    • Ibid., 2.9.12, 5.1.1301b29, 6.2.1317b4; EN 5.3.1131a27-29.
    • EN
    • Isocrates1
  • 34
    • 85037774971 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle, 3.12, 4.11.1296a13-18, 5.10.1310a25-36
    • Aristotle, 3.12, 4.11.1296a13-18, 5.10.1310a25-36.
  • 35
    • 0004275697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, Nussbaum, Fragility of Goodness, p. 353, "Aristotelian Social Democracy," p. 239; Aristotle, 6.4.1318b6-1319a18.
    • Fragility of Goodness , pp. 353
    • Nussbaum1
  • 36
    • 0003352586 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle, 6.4.1318b6-1319a18
    • For example, Nussbaum, Fragility of Goodness, p. 353, "Aristotelian Social Democracy," p. 239; Aristotle, 6.4.1318b6-1319a18.
    • Aristotelian Social Democracy , pp. 239
  • 37
    • 85037767756 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ober, p. 306
    • Ober, p. 306.
  • 38
    • 85037763090 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle, 1.2.1252b28-30, 3.6.1278b20-30, 7.14.1333a11-16
    • For example, Aristotle, 1.2.1252b28-30, 3.6.1278b20-30, 7.14.1333a11-16.
  • 39
    • 84875356328 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1.8.1099a31-b8, 10.8.1178b33-35
    • Aristotle, EN 1.8.1099a31-b8, 10.8.1178b33-35.
    • EN
    • Aristotle1
  • 40
    • 85037776986 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle, 2.9.1271a29-37, 2.10.1272a12-27
    • Aristotle, 2.9.1271a29-37, 2.10.1272a12-27.
  • 41
    • 84875356328 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2.1.1103a32-b6, 10.9.1179b20-21, 7.13.1332a39-40
    • Aristotle, EN 2.1.1103a32-b6, 10.9.1179b20-21, 7.13.1332a39-40.
    • EN
    • Aristotle1
  • 42
    • 85037750357 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 2.6.1106b3; Aristotle, 7.16.1335b12
    • Ibid., EN 2.6.1106b3; Aristotle, 7.16.1335b12.
    • EN
  • 43
    • 85037783450 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle, 7.7, cf. 7.10.1330a25-30
    • For example, Aristotle, 7.7, cf. 7.10.1330a25-30.
  • 44
    • 0011679017 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, Nussbaum, "Shame, Separateness, and Political Unity," pp. 420-21, Fragility of Goodness, pp. 347-49, "Nature, Function, and Capability," pp. 156-57, 171-72, "Aristotelian Social Democracy," p. 248, n. 80.
    • Shame, Separateness, and Political Unity , pp. 420-421
    • Nussbaum1
  • 45
    • 85019556277 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, Nussbaum, "Shame, Separateness, and Political Unity," pp. 420-21, Fragility of Goodness, pp. 347-49, "Nature, Function, and Capability," pp. 156-57, 171-72, "Aristotelian Social Democracy," p. 248, n. 80.
    • Fragility of Goodness , pp. 347-349
  • 46
    • 0038833643 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, Nussbaum, "Shame, Separateness, and Political Unity," pp. 420-21, Fragility of Goodness, pp. 347-49, "Nature, Function, and Capability," pp. 156-57, 171-72, "Aristotelian Social Democracy," p. 248, n. 80.
    • Nature, Function, and Capability , pp. 156-157
  • 47
    • 85037755698 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, Nussbaum, "Shame, Separateness, and Political Unity," pp. 420-21, Fragility of Goodness, pp. 347-49, "Nature, Function, and Capability," pp. 156-57, 171-72, "Aristotelian Social Democracy," p. 248, n. 80.
    • Aristotelian Social Democracy , vol.80 , pp. 248
  • 48
    • 85037763448 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle, 3.5.1278a20-21, 7.9.1329a39-41
    • Aristotle, 3.5.1278a20-21, 7.9.1329a39-41.
  • 51
    • 85037755698 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 7.9.1328b41-1329a2
    • Ibid., 7.9.1328b41-1329a2; see Fred D. Miller, Nature, Justice and Rights in Aristotle's Politics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995), pp. 161, 244.
    • Aristotelian Social Democracy , vol.80 , pp. 248
  • 53
    • 0039356642 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1.117
    • Some commentators, e.g., W. L. Newman, The Politics of Aristotle (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1887-1902), 1.117, have inferred, on the analogy of his theory of natural slavery, that Aristotle believed in the existence of a naturally inferior laboring class of Greeks. However, there is no clear evidence for such an interpretation. Among Greek males, there are only natural slaves and natural free men, all of whom are potentially virtuous (Aristotle, 1.13.1260b1-3).
    • (1887) The Politics of Aristotle
    • Newman, W.L.1
  • 54
    • 85037784038 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, Aristotle, 1.13.1260a10-12; see also n. 6 above
    • For example, Aristotle, 1.13.1260a10-12; see also n. 6 above.
  • 55
    • 85037776415 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle, 7.9.1328b36-1329a2
    • Aristotle, 7.9.1328b36-1329a2.
  • 56
    • 0039356642 scopus 로고
    • 1.9.1257b23-1258a14. See Ober, pp. 340-41 and n. 87
    • Merchants are too concerned with acquisition and bodily desires (ibid., 1.9.1257b23-1258a14). See Ober, pp. 340-41 and n. 87.
    • (1887) The Politics of Aristotle
    • Newman, W.L.1
  • 57
    • 85037775020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle, 7.9.1329a24-26, 7.10.1330a25-33
    • Aristotle, 7.9.1329a24-26, 7.10.1330a25-33.
  • 58
    • 0039949051 scopus 로고
    • Aristotle's theory of distributive justice
    • ed. David Keyt and Fred D. Miller Oxford: Blackwell, Ober, pp. 340-41 and n. 87
    • Aristotle does not explicitly say that no free Greeks are noncitizens. However, his preference for slaves and foreigners in the menial roles, as well as his theory of distributive justice, suggest that no free Greeks were excluded. See David Keyt, "Aristotle's Theory of Distributive Justice," in A Companion to Aristotle's Politics, ed. David Keyt and Fred D. Miller (Oxford: Blackwell, 1991), pp. 238-78; Ober, pp. 340-41 and n. 87.
    • (1991) A Companion to Aristotle's Politics , pp. 238-278
    • Keyt, D.1
  • 59
    • 0038833643 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nussbaum, "Nature, Function, and Capability," pp. 146-48, 156-57, interprets Aristotle's remark (7.2.1324a23-25) that the best constitution allows "anyone whatsoever" to live well as implying that the ideal state should provide a good life for everyone who is capable of it. However, the extension of "anyone whatsoever" may be confined to a preselected citizen body and need not carry any implication about how widely that citizen body is selected in the first place. See David Charles, "Perfectionism in Aristotle's Political Theory: Reply to Martha Nussbaum," Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, suppl. vol. (1988), pp. 185-206, 194-97; Miller, p. 214 and n. 65.
    • Nature, Function, and Capability , pp. 146-148
    • Nussbaum1
  • 60
    • 0040611702 scopus 로고
    • Perfectionism in Aristotle's political theory: Reply to Martha Nussbaum
    • Miller, p. 214 and n. 65
    • Nussbaum, "Nature, Function, and Capability," pp. 146-48, 156-57, interprets Aristotle's remark (7.2.1324a23-25) that the best constitution allows "anyone whatsoever" to live well as implying that the ideal state should provide a good life for everyone who is capable of it. However, the extension of "anyone whatsoever" may be confined to a preselected citizen body and need not carry any implication about how widely that citizen body is selected in the first place. See David Charles, "Perfectionism in Aristotle's Political Theory: Reply to Martha Nussbaum," Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, suppl. vol. (1988), pp. 185-206, 194-97; Miller, p. 214 and n. 65.
    • (1988) Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy , Issue.SUPPL. VOL. , pp. 185-206
    • Charles, D.1
  • 61
    • 85037750361 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle, 7.4
    • Aristotle, 7.4.
  • 62
    • 0040611702 scopus 로고
    • Perfectionism in Aristotle's political theory: Reply to Martha Nussbaum
    • 3.5.1278a15-20
    • Democracies may include laborers who ideally should be excluded (ibid., 3.5.1278a15-20). Farmers, who are excluded from the ideal state, form the citizen body of the best (least bad) form of democracy (4.6.1292b25-29). Oligarchies, too, with their emphasis on wealth, may include as citizens rich merchants whose concern for trade and profit making would make them unsuitable citizens for the ideal state. See n. 32 above.
    • (1988) Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy , Issue.SUPPL. VOL. , pp. 185-206
    • Charles, D.1
  • 64
    • 85037755698 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nussbaum, "Nature, Function, and Capability," p. 172, "Aristotelian Social Democracy," p. 248, n. 80.
    • Aristotelian Social Democracy , vol.80 , pp. 248
  • 68
    • 85037763181 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See n. 12 above
    • See n. 12 above.
  • 69
    • 85037763730 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Seen. 13 above
    • Seen. 13 above.
  • 70
    • 85037754173 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle, 2.9.1270a30-b7
    • Aristotle, 2.9.1270a30-b7.
  • 75
    • 0004275697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • esp. chaps. 1, 11
    • Nussbaum, Fragility of Goodness, esp. chaps. 1, 11; Bernard Williams, Shame and Necessity (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993).
    • Fragility of Goodness
    • Nussbaum1
  • 76
    • 0004141126 scopus 로고
    • Berkeley: University of California Press
    • Nussbaum, Fragility of Goodness, esp. chaps. 1, 11; Bernard Williams, Shame and Necessity (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993).
    • (1993) Shame and Necessity
    • Williams, B.1
  • 78
    • 85037753878 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See nn. 5, 6 above
    • See nn. 5, 6 above.
  • 79
    • 85037766127 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle, 3.9.1280a9-11, 5.1.1301a25-28, 5.2.1302a24-31
    • Aristotle, 3.9.1280a9-11, 5.1.1301a25-28, 5.2.1302a24-31.
  • 80
    • 0004275697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 3.12.1283a15-20
    • Ibid., 3.12.1283a15-20. Wealth (oligarchy) and freedom (democracy) are necessary for the state's existence, but virtue is necessary for living well.
    • Fragility of Goodness
    • Nussbaum1
  • 83
    • 85037774671 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Charles, p. 195
    • Charles, p. 195.
  • 90
    • 84872334687 scopus 로고
    • Aristotle and political liberty
    • Ibid., ed. Gunther Patzig Gottingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht
    • Ibid., quoting Jonathan Barnes, "Aristotle and Political Liberty," in Aristoteles' "Politik": Akten des XI Symposium Aristotelicum, ed. Gunther Patzig (Gottingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1990), pp. 249-63.
    • (1990) Aristoteles' "Politik": Akten des XI Symposium Aristotelicum , pp. 249-263
    • Nussbaum1
  • 91
    • 85037766504 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Barnes
    • Barnes.
  • 92
    • 85037770521 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Miller, pp. 248-49
    • See Miller, pp. 248-49.
  • 93
    • 84875356328 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 10.9.1180a1-4
    • Aristotle, EN 10.9.1180a1-4.
    • EN
    • Aristotle1
  • 95
    • 84875356328 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 10.9.1180b3-13
    • For example, Aristotle, EN 10.9.1180b3-13.
    • EN
    • Aristotle1
  • 96
    • 84875356328 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 10.9.1180b1; Aristotle, 6.5.1319b40
    • Ibid., EN 10.9.1180b1; Aristotle, 6.5.1319b40. That the word normally used for law (nomos) could also refer to social norms or conventions shows the difficulty in Greek of clearly distinguishing between law and morality or of seeking to limit the law's concern with morality.
    • EN
    • Aristotle1
  • 97
    • 85037762351 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Patzig, ed.
    • Richard Sorabji, "Comments on Barnes," in Patzig, ed., pp. 264-76. Sorabji, though less inclined than Barnes to find a totalitarian impulse in Aristotle (referring particularly to Aristotle's vindication of the family), nonetheless rejects the view of Donald Allan that Aristotle held a minimalist view of the role of the state. See Allan's "Individual and State in the Ethics and Politics," in La Politique d'Aristote, ed. Rudolf Stark et al. (Geneva: Fondation Hardt, 1964).
    • Comments on Barnes , pp. 264-276
    • Sorabji, R.1
  • 98
    • 84921968545 scopus 로고
    • Individual and state in the ethics and politics
    • ed. Rudolf Stark et al. Geneva: Fondation Hardt
    • Richard Sorabji, "Comments on Barnes," in Patzig, ed., pp. 264-76. Sorabji, though less inclined than Barnes to find a totalitarian impulse in Aristotle (referring particularly to Aristotle's vindication of the family), nonetheless rejects the view of Donald Allan that Aristotle held a minimalist view of the role of the state. See Allan's "Individual and State in the Ethics and Politics," in La Politique d'Aristote, ed. Rudolf Stark et al. (Geneva: Fondation Hardt, 1964).
    • (1964) La Politique d'Aristote
    • Allan1
  • 99
    • 85037751630 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle, 2.9.1271a41-b10, 7.14.1333b10-1334a11, 8.4.1338b10-16; 10.9.1180a25-29
    • Aristotle, 2.9.1271a41-b10, 7.14.1333b10-1334a11, 8.4.1338b10-16; and EN 10.9.1180a25-29.
    • EN
  • 100
  • 101
    • 84872421184 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1.9.1367a33
    • Aristotle, Metaphysics, A.2.982b25, Rhetoric, 1.9.1367a33.
    • Rhetoric
  • 103
    • 84875356328 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2.5.1105a30-34
    • Aristotle, EN 2.5.1105a30-34.
    • EN
    • Aristotle1
  • 104
    • 0003659604 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, chap. 1
    • See, e.g., John M. Cooper, Reason and Human Good in Aristotle (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1975), chap. 1; W. F. R. Hardie, Aristotle's Ethical Theory, 2d ed. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980), chap. 11; Terence Irwin, Aristotle's First Principles (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990), chap. 7.
    • (1975) Reason and Human Good in Aristotle
    • Cooper, J.M.1
  • 105
    • 0004132123 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press, chap. 11
    • See, e.g., John M. Cooper, Reason and Human Good in Aristotle (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1975), chap. 1; W. F. R. Hardie, Aristotle's Ethical Theory, 2d ed. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980), chap. 11; Terence Irwin, Aristotle's First Principles (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990), chap. 7.
    • (1980) Aristotle's Ethical Theory, 2d Ed.
    • Hardie, W.F.R.1
  • 106
    • 0040598810 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press, chap. 7
    • See, e.g., John M. Cooper, Reason and Human Good in Aristotle (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1975), chap. 1; W. F. R. Hardie, Aristotle's Ethical Theory, 2d ed. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980), chap. 11; Terence Irwin, Aristotle's First Principles (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990), chap. 7.
    • (1990) Aristotle's First Principles
    • Irwin, T.1
  • 107
    • 85037779452 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle, EN 6.5; David Wiggins, "Deliberation and Practical Wisdom," in Essays on Aristotle's Ethics, ed. Amelie O. Rorty (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1980), pp. 221-40; Sherman, pp. 79-94; Irwin, p. 336.
    • EN 6.5
    • Aristotle1
  • 108
    • 85163428913 scopus 로고
    • Deliberation and practical wisdom
    • ed. Amelie O. Rorty Berkeley: University of California Press, Sherman, pp. 79-94; Irwin, p. 336
    • Aristotle, EN 6.5; David Wiggins, "Deliberation and Practical Wisdom," in Essays on Aristotle's Ethics, ed. Amelie O. Rorty (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1980), pp. 221-40; Sherman, pp. 79-94; Irwin, p. 336.
    • (1980) Essays on Aristotle's Ethics , pp. 221-240
    • Wiggins, D.1
  • 109
    • 0345778648 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle, ethical diversity and political argument
    • Such a pluralist view of Aristotle, advanced, e.g., by Yack and Waldron, is rebutted in Richard Mulgan, "Aristotle, Ethical Diversity and Political Argument," Journal of Political Philosophy 7 (1999): 191-207.
    • (1999) Journal of Political Philosophy , vol.7 , pp. 191-207
    • Mulgan, R.1
  • 110
    • 85037763537 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle, 7.4.1325b38-40
    • Aristotle, 7.4.1325b38-40.
  • 111
    • 85037778266 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See p. 91 above
    • See p. 91 above.
  • 112
    • 0004275697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nussbaum, Fragility of Goodness, p. 349, argues that the key virtues of justice and equity are largely political in scope and that a life of full virtue requires citizenship and (at least the right of) political participation. It can be argued, however, that the virtues of the ethical treatises, though compatible with citizenship, do not require it; see Richard Mulgan, "Aristotle and the Value of Political Participation," Political Theory 18 (1990): 195-215. See also Miller, pp. 237-39; Tim Duvall and Paul Dotson, "Political Participation and Eudaimonia in Aristotle's Politics," History of Political Thought 19 (1998); 21-34. Of the external goods, it is the loss of family and friends rather than of power and citizenship which particularly damage happiness (Aristotle, EN 1.8.1099b5-6, 1.9.1100a7-8). Thus, Aristotle's own life as a metic (foreign noncitizen) was not as deficient as Nussbaum suggests (Fragility of Goodness, p. 497, n. 8; see also her "Shame, Separateness, and Political Unity," p. 419, and "Aristotelian Social Democracy," pp. 232-33).
    • Fragility of Goodness , pp. 349
    • Nussbaum1
  • 113
    • 84972729097 scopus 로고
    • Aristotle and the value of political participation
    • Nussbaum, Fragility of Goodness, p. 349, argues that the key virtues of justice and equity are largely political in scope and that a life of full virtue requires citizenship and (at least the right of) political participation. It can be argued, however, that the virtues of the ethical treatises, though compatible with citizenship, do not require it; see Richard Mulgan, "Aristotle and the Value of Political Participation," Political Theory 18 (1990): 195-215. See also Miller, pp. 237-39; Tim Duvall and Paul Dotson, "Political Participation and Eudaimonia in Aristotle's Politics," History of Political Thought 19 (1998); 21-34. Of the external goods, it is the loss of family and friends rather than of power and citizenship which particularly damage happiness (Aristotle, EN 1.8.1099b5-6, 1.9.1100a7-8). Thus, Aristotle's own life as a metic (foreign noncitizen) was not as deficient as Nussbaum suggests (Fragility of Goodness, p. 497, n. 8; see also her "Shame, Separateness, and Political Unity," p. 419, and "Aristotelian Social Democracy," pp. 232-33).
    • (1990) Political Theory , vol.18 , pp. 195-215
    • Mulgan, R.1
  • 114
    • 0032363338 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Political participation and Eudaimonia in Aristotle's politics
    • Miller, pp. 237-39
    • Nussbaum, Fragility of Goodness, p. 349, argues that the key virtues of justice and equity are largely political in scope and that a life of full virtue requires citizenship and (at least the right of) political participation. It can be argued, however, that the virtues of the ethical treatises, though compatible with citizenship, do not require it; see Richard Mulgan, "Aristotle and the Value of Political Participation," Political Theory 18 (1990): 195-215. See also Miller, pp. 237-39; Tim Duvall and Paul Dotson, "Political Participation and Eudaimonia in Aristotle's Politics," History of Political Thought 19 (1998); 21-34. Of the external goods, it is the loss of family and friends rather than of power and citizenship which particularly damage happiness (Aristotle, EN 1.8.1099b5-6, 1.9.1100a7-8). Thus, Aristotle's own life as a metic (foreign noncitizen) was not as deficient as Nussbaum suggests (Fragility of Goodness, p. 497, n. 8; see also her "Shame, Separateness, and Political Unity," p. 419, and "Aristotelian Social Democracy," pp. 232-33).
    • (1998) History of Political Thought , vol.19 , pp. 21-34
    • Duvall, T.1    Dotson, P.2
  • 115
    • 84875356328 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1.8.1099b5-6, 1.9.1100a7-8
    • Nussbaum, Fragility of Goodness, p. 349, argues that the key virtues of justice and equity are largely political in scope and that a life of full virtue requires citizenship and (at least the right of) political participation. It can be argued, however, that the virtues of the ethical treatises, though compatible with citizenship, do not require it; see Richard Mulgan, "Aristotle and the Value of Political Participation," Political Theory 18 (1990): 195-215. See also Miller, pp. 237-39; Tim Duvall and Paul Dotson, "Political Participation and Eudaimonia in Aristotle's Politics," History of Political Thought 19 (1998); 21-34. Of the external goods, it is the loss of family and friends rather than of power and citizenship which particularly damage happiness (Aristotle, EN 1.8.1099b5-6, 1.9.1100a7-8). Thus, Aristotle's own life as a metic (foreign noncitizen) was not as deficient as Nussbaum suggests (Fragility of Goodness, p. 497, n. 8; see also her "Shame, Separateness, and Political Unity," p. 419, and "Aristotelian Social Democracy," pp. 232-33).
    • EN
    • Aristotle1
  • 116
    • 85037768334 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nussbaum, Fragility of Goodness, p. 349, argues that the key virtues of justice and equity are largely political in scope and that a life of full virtue requires citizenship and (at least the right of) political participation. It can be argued, however, that the virtues of the ethical treatises, though compatible with citizenship, do not require it; see Richard Mulgan, "Aristotle and the Value of Political Participation," Political Theory 18 (1990): 195-215. See also Miller, pp. 237-39; Tim Duvall and Paul Dotson, "Political Participation and Eudaimonia in Aristotle's Politics," History of Political Thought 19 (1998); 21-34. Of the external goods, it is the loss of family and friends rather than of power and citizenship which particularly damage happiness (Aristotle, EN 1.8.1099b5-6, 1.9.1100a7-8). Thus, Aristotle's own life as a metic (foreign noncitizen) was not as deficient as Nussbaum suggests (Fragility of Goodness, p. 497, n. 8; see also her "Shame, Separateness, and Political Unity," p. 419, and "Aristotelian Social Democracy," pp. 232-33).
    • Fragility of Goodness , vol.8 , pp. 497
  • 117
    • 85037752184 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nussbaum, Fragility of Goodness, p. 349, argues that the key virtues of justice and equity are largely political in scope and that a life of full virtue requires citizenship and (at least the right of) political participation. It can be argued, however, that the virtues of the ethical treatises, though compatible with citizenship, do not require it; see Richard Mulgan, "Aristotle and the Value of Political Participation," Political Theory 18 (1990): 195-215. See also Miller, pp. 237-39; Tim Duvall and Paul Dotson, "Political Participation and Eudaimonia in Aristotle's Politics," History of Political Thought 19 (1998); 21-34. Of the external goods, it is the loss of family and friends rather than of power and citizenship which particularly damage happiness (Aristotle, EN 1.8.1099b5-6, 1.9.1100a7-8). Thus, Aristotle's own life as a metic (foreign noncitizen) was not as deficient as Nussbaum suggests (Fragility of Goodness, p. 497, n. 8; see also her "Shame, Separateness, and Political Unity," p. 419, and "Aristotelian Social Democracy," pp. 232-33).
    • Shame, Separateness, and Political Unity , pp. 419
  • 118
    • 0003352586 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nussbaum, Fragility of Goodness, p. 349, argues that the key virtues of justice and equity are largely political in scope and that a life of full virtue requires citizenship and (at least the right of) political participation. It can be argued, however, that the virtues of the ethical treatises, though compatible with citizenship, do not require it; see Richard Mulgan, "Aristotle and the Value of Political Participation," Political Theory 18 (1990): 195-215. See also Miller, pp. 237-39; Tim Duvall and Paul Dotson, "Political Participation and Eudaimonia in Aristotle's Politics," History of Political Thought 19 (1998); 21-34. Of the external goods, it is the loss of family and friends rather than of power and citizenship which particularly damage happiness (Aristotle, EN 1.8.1099b5-6, 1.9.1100a7-8). Thus, Aristotle's own life as a metic (foreign noncitizen) was not as deficient as Nussbaum suggests (Fragility of Goodness, p. 497, n. 8; see also her "Shame, Separateness, and Political Unity," p. 419, and "Aristotelian Social Democracy," pp. 232-33).
    • Aristotelian Social Democracy , pp. 232-233
  • 119
    • 85037781527 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 3.6.128b20; 9.8.1169b18
    • Aristotle, 1.2.1253a2-7. Aristotle uses the gender neutral anthropos, not the male aner, for "man," which suggests that he is talking about living in a polis, not about the rights of citizenship. Aristotle uses the "political animal" argument to indicate human sociability contrasted with living alone, not political participation contrasted with exclusion from political activity (3.6.128b20; EN 9.8.1169b18). Nussbaum's own analysis of this argument stresses sociability and friendship rather than specifically political activity; see her "Aristotle on Human Nature and the Foundation of Ethics," in World, Mind and Ethics, ed. J. E. J. Altham and Ross Harrison (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), pp. 102-10.
    • EN
  • 120
    • 0002493162 scopus 로고
    • Aristotle on human nature and the foundation of ethics
    • ed. J. E. J. Altham and Ross Harrison Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Aristotle, 1.2.1253a2-7. Aristotle uses the gender neutral anthropos, not the male aner, for "man," which suggests that he is talking about living in a polis, not about the rights of citizenship. Aristotle uses the "political animal" argument to indicate human sociability contrasted with living alone, not political participation contrasted with exclusion from political activity (3.6.128b20; EN 9.8.1169b18). Nussbaum's own analysis of this argument stresses sociability and friendship rather than specifically political activity; see her "Aristotle on Human Nature and the Foundation of Ethics," in World, Mind and Ethics, ed. J. E. J. Altham and Ross Harrison (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), pp. 102-10.
    • (1995) World, Mind and Ethics , pp. 102-110
  • 121
    • 85037762375 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle, 4.1.1288b28-30, 5-6
    • Aristotle, 4.1.1288b28-30, 5-6.
  • 122
    • 0004348416 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nussbaum, "Aristotelian Social Democracy," pp. 208-13. Nussbaum considers Aristotle's account superior because it treats material goods as clearly instrumental and allows for individual variation according to need.
    • Aristotelian Social Democracy , pp. 208-213
    • Nussbaum1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.