-
1
-
-
0039138780
-
The aesthetic definition of art
-
edited by Hugh Curtler New York: Haven
-
If we hold such a view, we can be shy of committing ourselves to a particular theory of aesthetic properties. We can bracket off that issue as a separate topic. The point is to see how far we can get in understanding art by giving an account that draws on aesthetic properties - whatever their nature. Such a theory can be constructed with the true nature of aesthetic properties as a variable. For one such account, see Monroe Beardsley, "The Aesthetic Definition of Art," in What Is Art? edited by Hugh Curtler (New York: Haven, 1983); for another, see Nick Zangwill, "The Creative Theory of Art," American Philosophical Quarterly, 32(1995):315-32; and Nick Zangwill, "Aesthetic Functionalism," in Aesthetic Concepts: Sibley and After, edited by Emily Brady and Jerrold Levinson (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001).
-
(1983)
What Is Art?
-
-
Beardsley, M.1
-
2
-
-
0039138777
-
The creative theory of art
-
If we hold such a view, we can be shy of committing ourselves to a particular theory of aesthetic properties. We can bracket off that issue as a separate topic. The point is to see how far we can get in understanding art by giving an account that draws on aesthetic properties - whatever their nature. Such a theory can be constructed with the true nature of aesthetic properties as a variable. For one such account, see Monroe Beardsley, "The Aesthetic Definition of Art," in What Is Art? edited by Hugh Curtler (New York: Haven, 1983); for another, see Nick Zangwill, "The Creative Theory of Art," American Philosophical Quarterly, 32(1995):315-32; and Nick Zangwill, "Aesthetic Functionalism," in Aesthetic Concepts: Sibley and After, edited by Emily Brady and Jerrold Levinson (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001).
-
(1995)
American Philosophical Quarterly
, vol.32
, pp. 315-332
-
-
Zangwill, N.1
-
3
-
-
0040917083
-
Aesthetic functionalism
-
edited by Emily Brady and Jerrold Levinson Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
If we hold such a view, we can be shy of committing ourselves to a particular theory of aesthetic properties. We can bracket off that issue as a separate topic. The point is to see how far we can get in understanding art by giving an account that draws on aesthetic properties - whatever their nature. Such a theory can be constructed with the true nature of aesthetic properties as a variable. For one such account, see Monroe Beardsley, "The Aesthetic Definition of Art," in What Is Art? edited by Hugh Curtler (New York: Haven, 1983); for another, see Nick Zangwill, "The Creative Theory of Art," American Philosophical Quarterly, 32(1995):315-32; and Nick Zangwill, "Aesthetic Functionalism," in Aesthetic Concepts: Sibley and After, edited by Emily Brady and Jerrold Levinson (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001).
-
(2001)
Aesthetic Concepts: Sibley and After
-
-
Zangwill, N.1
-
4
-
-
0004044848
-
-
London: Routledge & Kegan Paul
-
Pierre Bourdieu, Distinction (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1984); Terry Eagleton, The Ideology of the Aesthetic (Oxford: Blackwell, 1984).
-
(1984)
Distinction
-
-
Bourdieu, P.1
-
5
-
-
0004241152
-
-
Oxford: Blackwell
-
Pierre Bourdieu, Distinction (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1984); Terry Eagleton, The Ideology of the Aesthetic (Oxford: Blackwell, 1984).
-
(1984)
The Ideology of the Aesthetic
-
-
Eagleton, T.1
-
6
-
-
0039731139
-
Against the sociology of taste
-
See Nick Zangwill, "Against the Sociology of Taste," Cultural Values Journal 5(2001), reprinted in Nick Zangwill, Metaphysics of Beauty (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2001), chap. 12.
-
(2001)
Cultural Values Journal
, vol.5
-
-
Zangwill, N.1
-
7
-
-
0039138779
-
-
Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, chap. 12
-
See Nick Zangwill, "Against the Sociology of Taste," Cultural Values Journal 5(2001), reprinted in Nick Zangwill, Metaphysics of Beauty (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2001), chap. 12.
-
(2001)
Metaphysics of Beauty
-
-
Zangwill, N.1
-
10
-
-
84967636144
-
-
Berkeley: University of California Press
-
Howard Becker, Art Worlds (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1982).
-
(1982)
Art Worlds
-
-
Becker, H.1
-
12
-
-
84974308014
-
Groundrules in the philosophy of art
-
Nick Zangwill, "Groundrules in the Philosophy of Art," Philosophy 70(1995):533-544.
-
(1995)
Philosophy
, vol.70
, pp. 533-544
-
-
Zangwill, N.1
-
14
-
-
0003942341
-
-
Chicago: University of Chicago Press
-
See Serge Guilbaut, How New York Stole the Idea of the Avant Garde (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983). See also David Wise, "Spook Art," ArtNews, September 2000; and Frances Stonar, The Cultural Cold War (New York: New Press, 2000).
-
(1983)
How New York Stole the Idea of the Avant Garde
-
-
Guilbaut, S.1
-
15
-
-
0040323047
-
Spook art
-
September
-
See Serge Guilbaut, How New York Stole the Idea of the Avant Garde (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983). See also David Wise, "Spook Art," ArtNews, September 2000; and Frances Stonar, The Cultural Cold War (New York: New Press, 2000).
-
(2000)
Artnews
-
-
Wise, D.1
-
16
-
-
0003908139
-
-
New York: New Press
-
See Serge Guilbaut, How New York Stole the Idea of the Avant Garde (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983). See also David Wise, "Spook Art," ArtNews, September 2000; and Frances Stonar, The Cultural Cold War (New York: New Press, 2000).
-
(2000)
The Cultural Cold War
-
-
Stonar, F.1
-
17
-
-
0004118035
-
-
translated by James Creed Meredith Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
Kant, Critique of Judgement, translated by James Creed Meredith (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1928), 65-66.
-
(1928)
Critique of Judgement
, pp. 65-66
-
-
Kant1
-
18
-
-
85013277421
-
-
note
-
Note that there is absolutely no reason to think that an aesthetic theory of art is committed to some doctrine of the "autonomy" of art. That is setting up a straw man: a work of art can have aesthetic values that depend on the meaning of the work, and aesthetic values need not be the only values of a work. Moreover, an aesthetic theory need not privilege high or fine art forms. Nor need it be committed to extreme formalism about aesthetic properties. Kant, for example, was committed to none of this.
-
-
-
-
19
-
-
0003692914
-
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
One very interesting art historian who respects social facts but does not reject aesthetic value is Michael Baxandall. See, for example, his Painting and Experience in Fifteenth Century Italy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1972) and Patterns of Intention (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1985). Contrast Janet Wolff's book, The Social Production of Art, which contains little or no empirical evidence. She merely cites the authority of other sociological writers. See also her Aesthetics and the Sociology of Art (London: Allen & Unwin, 1983), for the same flaws.
-
(1972)
Painting and Experience in Fifteenth Century Italy
-
-
Baxandall, M.1
-
20
-
-
0008459824
-
-
New Haven, CT: Yale University Press
-
One very interesting art historian who respects social facts but does not reject aesthetic value is Michael Baxandall. See, for example, his Painting and Experience in Fifteenth Century Italy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1972) and Patterns of Intention (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1985). Contrast Janet Wolff's book, The Social Production of Art, which contains little or no empirical evidence. She merely cites the authority of other sociological writers. See also her Aesthetics and the Sociology of Art (London: Allen & Unwin, 1983), for the same flaws.
-
(1985)
Patterns of Intention
-
-
-
21
-
-
0003892411
-
-
One very interesting art historian who respects social facts but does not reject aesthetic value is Michael Baxandall. See, for example, his Painting and Experience in Fifteenth Century Italy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1972) and Patterns of Intention (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1985). Contrast Janet Wolff's book, The Social Production of Art, which contains little or no empirical evidence. She merely cites the authority of other sociological writers. See also her Aesthetics and the Sociology of Art (London: Allen & Unwin, 1983), for the same flaws.
-
The Social Production of Art
-
-
Wolff, J.1
-
22
-
-
0345868931
-
-
London: Allen & Unwin, for the same flaws
-
One very interesting art historian who respects social facts but does not reject aesthetic value is Michael Baxandall. See, for example, his Painting and Experience in Fifteenth Century Italy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1972) and Patterns of Intention (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1985). Contrast Janet Wolff's book, The Social Production of Art, which contains little or no empirical evidence. She merely cites the authority of other sociological writers. See also her Aesthetics and the Sociology of Art (London: Allen & Unwin, 1983), for the same flaws.
-
(1983)
Aesthetics and the Sociology of Art
-
-
-
23
-
-
0001535843
-
Cultural standing through the production perspective
-
edited by Diana Crane London: Routledge
-
See Richard Peterson, "Cultural Standing through the Production Perspective," in The Sociology of Culture, edited by Diana Crane (London: Routledge, 1994), 175.
-
(1994)
The Sociology of Culture
, pp. 175
-
-
Peterson, R.1
-
24
-
-
85013304209
-
-
note
-
It is an irony that one part of cultural production that might plausibly be submitted for sociological explanation is the twentieth-century theoretical rejection of the aesthetic by sociologists of art. Sociologists are remarkably shy of applying their techniques to their own views!
-
-
-
-
25
-
-
79954947724
-
-
edited by London: Camden, But in fact the "old" art history was never the naive stereotype that it was made out to be. Earnst Gombrich is as canny as any on this score
-
The so-called "new" art history was keen to unearth ideological properties of works of art (and also of writings about them). See The New Art History, edited by A. L. Rees and Frances Borzello (London: Camden, 1986). But in fact the "old" art history was never the naive stereotype that it was made out to be. Earnst Gombrich is as canny as any on this score.
-
(1986)
The New Art History
-
-
Rees, A.L.1
Borzello, F.2
-
26
-
-
0040323043
-
-
4 vols., edited by Chicago: University of Chicago Press
-
See Clement Greenberg: Collected Essays and Criticism, 4 vols., edited by John O'Brian (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1986). See also Clement Greenberg's writings in Modernism and Modernity, edited by Benjamin Buchloch, Serge Guilbaut, and David Solkin (Vancouver, British Columbia, Canada: Nova Scotia Press, 1981): "To Cope with Decadence," his contributions to the discussion on T. J. Clark's paper (pp. 188-93), and his contributions to the general panel discussion (pp. 265-77). See also Clement Greenberg, Homemade Esthetics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999).
-
(1986)
Clement Greenberg: Collected Essays and Criticism
-
-
O'Brian, J.1
-
27
-
-
0040917081
-
-
edited by Benjamin Buchloch, Serge Guilbaut, and David Solkin Vancouver, British Columbia, Canada: Nova Scotia Press
-
See Clement Greenberg: Collected Essays and Criticism, 4 vols., edited by John O'Brian (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1986). See also Clement Greenberg's writings in Modernism and Modernity, edited by Benjamin Buchloch, Serge Guilbaut, and David Solkin (Vancouver, British Columbia, Canada: Nova Scotia Press, 1981): "To Cope with Decadence," his contributions to the discussion on T. J. Clark's paper (pp. 188-93), and his contributions to the general panel discussion (pp. 265-77). See also Clement Greenberg, Homemade Esthetics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999).
-
(1981)
Modernism and Modernity
-
-
Greenberg, C.1
-
28
-
-
0040917082
-
-
his contributions to the discussion on and his contributions to the general panel discussion (pp. 265-77)
-
See Clement Greenberg: Collected Essays and Criticism, 4 vols., edited by John O'Brian (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1986). See also Clement Greenberg's writings in Modernism and Modernity, edited by Benjamin Buchloch, Serge Guilbaut, and David Solkin (Vancouver, British Columbia, Canada: Nova Scotia Press, 1981): "To Cope with Decadence," his contributions to the discussion on T. J. Clark's paper (pp. 188-93), and his contributions to the general panel discussion (pp. 265-77). See also Clement Greenberg, Homemade Esthetics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999).
-
To Cope with Decadence
, pp. 188-193
-
-
Clark, T.J.1
-
29
-
-
61049222175
-
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
See Clement Greenberg: Collected Essays and Criticism, 4 vols., edited by John O'Brian (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1986). See also Clement Greenberg's writings in Modernism and Modernity, edited by Benjamin Buchloch, Serge Guilbaut, and David Solkin (Vancouver, British Columbia, Canada: Nova Scotia Press, 1981): "To Cope with Decadence," his contributions to the discussion on T. J. Clark's paper (pp. 188-93), and his contributions to the general panel discussion (pp. 265-77). See also Clement Greenberg, Homemade Esthetics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999).
-
(1999)
Homemade Esthetics
-
-
Greenberg, C.1
-
31
-
-
0039731138
-
-
where he describes an economic system in which works of art were exchanged differently from the way works of art have been bought and sold as commodities for most of the twentieth century
-
See Baxandall's Painting and Experience, where he describes an economic system in which works of art were exchanged differently from the way works of art have been bought and sold as commodities for most of the twentieth century.
-
Painting and Experience
-
-
Baxandall1
-
32
-
-
0040323042
-
-
The CIA funded exhibitions in Paris in 1952 and in Vienna in 1959. See Wise, "Spook Art," 163.
-
Spook Art
, pp. 163
-
-
Wise1
-
33
-
-
85013327114
-
-
note
-
Plato says that "beauty is what is pleasant through hearing and sight" (Hippias Major, 298a.). Aquinus says, "Those things we call beautiful are those that please when they are seen" (Suma Theologiae, I.5.4.ad.I). Moreover, the idea that some things "delight the eyes" can be found in Genesis (II.9, III.6) and in Homer (Odyssey, book IV, line 51).
-
-
-
-
34
-
-
34347279633
-
Unkantian notions of disinterest
-
See Nick Zangill, "UnKantian Notions of Disinterest," British Journal of Aesthetics, 32 (1992): 149-52; and Nick Zangill, "Kant on Pleasure in the Agreeable," Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 53 (1995): 167-76.
-
(1992)
British Journal of Aesthetics
, vol.32
, pp. 149-152
-
-
Zangill, N.1
-
35
-
-
34347279633
-
Kant on pleasure in the agreeable
-
See Nick Zangill, "UnKantian Notions of Disinterest," British Journal of Aesthetics, 32 (1992): 149-52; and Nick Zangill, "Kant on Pleasure in the Agreeable," Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 53 (1995): 167-76.
-
(1995)
Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism
, vol.53
, pp. 167-176
-
-
Zangill, N.1
-
36
-
-
0040323039
-
Pleasure and the value of the arts
-
Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press
-
See Jerry Levinson, "Pleasure and the Value of the Arts," in Pleasure, Value and the Arts (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1995).
-
(1995)
Pleasure, Value and the Arts
-
-
Levinson, J.1
-
37
-
-
84970274018
-
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
Nelson Goodman, Languages of Art (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1969), 112.
-
(1969)
Languages of Art
, pp. 112
-
-
Goodman, N.1
-
39
-
-
84964992051
-
-
sec. 50
-
Kant notes that although art making involves the productive imagination, it also involves taste or judgement. See Kant, Critique of Judgement, sec. 50.
-
Critique of Judgement
-
-
Kant1
|