메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 32, Issue 2, 2002, Pages 206-218

Against the sociology of art

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0038893509     PISSN: 00483931     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1177/004931032002004     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (15)

References (39)
  • 1
    • 0039138780 scopus 로고
    • The aesthetic definition of art
    • edited by Hugh Curtler New York: Haven
    • If we hold such a view, we can be shy of committing ourselves to a particular theory of aesthetic properties. We can bracket off that issue as a separate topic. The point is to see how far we can get in understanding art by giving an account that draws on aesthetic properties - whatever their nature. Such a theory can be constructed with the true nature of aesthetic properties as a variable. For one such account, see Monroe Beardsley, "The Aesthetic Definition of Art," in What Is Art? edited by Hugh Curtler (New York: Haven, 1983); for another, see Nick Zangwill, "The Creative Theory of Art," American Philosophical Quarterly, 32(1995):315-32; and Nick Zangwill, "Aesthetic Functionalism," in Aesthetic Concepts: Sibley and After, edited by Emily Brady and Jerrold Levinson (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001).
    • (1983) What Is Art?
    • Beardsley, M.1
  • 2
    • 0039138777 scopus 로고
    • The creative theory of art
    • If we hold such a view, we can be shy of committing ourselves to a particular theory of aesthetic properties. We can bracket off that issue as a separate topic. The point is to see how far we can get in understanding art by giving an account that draws on aesthetic properties - whatever their nature. Such a theory can be constructed with the true nature of aesthetic properties as a variable. For one such account, see Monroe Beardsley, "The Aesthetic Definition of Art," in What Is Art? edited by Hugh Curtler (New York: Haven, 1983); for another, see Nick Zangwill, "The Creative Theory of Art," American Philosophical Quarterly, 32(1995):315-32; and Nick Zangwill, "Aesthetic Functionalism," in Aesthetic Concepts: Sibley and After, edited by Emily Brady and Jerrold Levinson (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001).
    • (1995) American Philosophical Quarterly , vol.32 , pp. 315-332
    • Zangwill, N.1
  • 3
    • 0040917083 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aesthetic functionalism
    • edited by Emily Brady and Jerrold Levinson Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • If we hold such a view, we can be shy of committing ourselves to a particular theory of aesthetic properties. We can bracket off that issue as a separate topic. The point is to see how far we can get in understanding art by giving an account that draws on aesthetic properties - whatever their nature. Such a theory can be constructed with the true nature of aesthetic properties as a variable. For one such account, see Monroe Beardsley, "The Aesthetic Definition of Art," in What Is Art? edited by Hugh Curtler (New York: Haven, 1983); for another, see Nick Zangwill, "The Creative Theory of Art," American Philosophical Quarterly, 32(1995):315-32; and Nick Zangwill, "Aesthetic Functionalism," in Aesthetic Concepts: Sibley and After, edited by Emily Brady and Jerrold Levinson (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001).
    • (2001) Aesthetic Concepts: Sibley and After
    • Zangwill, N.1
  • 4
    • 0004044848 scopus 로고
    • London: Routledge & Kegan Paul
    • Pierre Bourdieu, Distinction (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1984); Terry Eagleton, The Ideology of the Aesthetic (Oxford: Blackwell, 1984).
    • (1984) Distinction
    • Bourdieu, P.1
  • 5
    • 0004241152 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Blackwell
    • Pierre Bourdieu, Distinction (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1984); Terry Eagleton, The Ideology of the Aesthetic (Oxford: Blackwell, 1984).
    • (1984) The Ideology of the Aesthetic
    • Eagleton, T.1
  • 6
    • 0039731139 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Against the sociology of taste
    • See Nick Zangwill, "Against the Sociology of Taste," Cultural Values Journal 5(2001), reprinted in Nick Zangwill, Metaphysics of Beauty (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2001), chap. 12.
    • (2001) Cultural Values Journal , vol.5
    • Zangwill, N.1
  • 7
    • 0039138779 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, chap. 12
    • See Nick Zangwill, "Against the Sociology of Taste," Cultural Values Journal 5(2001), reprinted in Nick Zangwill, Metaphysics of Beauty (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2001), chap. 12.
    • (2001) Metaphysics of Beauty
    • Zangwill, N.1
  • 10
    • 84967636144 scopus 로고
    • Berkeley: University of California Press
    • Howard Becker, Art Worlds (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1982).
    • (1982) Art Worlds
    • Becker, H.1
  • 12
    • 84974308014 scopus 로고
    • Groundrules in the philosophy of art
    • Nick Zangwill, "Groundrules in the Philosophy of Art," Philosophy 70(1995):533-544.
    • (1995) Philosophy , vol.70 , pp. 533-544
    • Zangwill, N.1
  • 14
    • 0003942341 scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • See Serge Guilbaut, How New York Stole the Idea of the Avant Garde (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983). See also David Wise, "Spook Art," ArtNews, September 2000; and Frances Stonar, The Cultural Cold War (New York: New Press, 2000).
    • (1983) How New York Stole the Idea of the Avant Garde
    • Guilbaut, S.1
  • 15
    • 0040323047 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Spook art
    • September
    • See Serge Guilbaut, How New York Stole the Idea of the Avant Garde (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983). See also David Wise, "Spook Art," ArtNews, September 2000; and Frances Stonar, The Cultural Cold War (New York: New Press, 2000).
    • (2000) Artnews
    • Wise, D.1
  • 16
    • 0003908139 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: New Press
    • See Serge Guilbaut, How New York Stole the Idea of the Avant Garde (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983). See also David Wise, "Spook Art," ArtNews, September 2000; and Frances Stonar, The Cultural Cold War (New York: New Press, 2000).
    • (2000) The Cultural Cold War
    • Stonar, F.1
  • 17
    • 0004118035 scopus 로고
    • translated by James Creed Meredith Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Kant, Critique of Judgement, translated by James Creed Meredith (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1928), 65-66.
    • (1928) Critique of Judgement , pp. 65-66
    • Kant1
  • 18
    • 85013277421 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Note that there is absolutely no reason to think that an aesthetic theory of art is committed to some doctrine of the "autonomy" of art. That is setting up a straw man: a work of art can have aesthetic values that depend on the meaning of the work, and aesthetic values need not be the only values of a work. Moreover, an aesthetic theory need not privilege high or fine art forms. Nor need it be committed to extreme formalism about aesthetic properties. Kant, for example, was committed to none of this.
  • 19
    • 0003692914 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • One very interesting art historian who respects social facts but does not reject aesthetic value is Michael Baxandall. See, for example, his Painting and Experience in Fifteenth Century Italy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1972) and Patterns of Intention (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1985). Contrast Janet Wolff's book, The Social Production of Art, which contains little or no empirical evidence. She merely cites the authority of other sociological writers. See also her Aesthetics and the Sociology of Art (London: Allen & Unwin, 1983), for the same flaws.
    • (1972) Painting and Experience in Fifteenth Century Italy
    • Baxandall, M.1
  • 20
    • 0008459824 scopus 로고
    • New Haven, CT: Yale University Press
    • One very interesting art historian who respects social facts but does not reject aesthetic value is Michael Baxandall. See, for example, his Painting and Experience in Fifteenth Century Italy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1972) and Patterns of Intention (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1985). Contrast Janet Wolff's book, The Social Production of Art, which contains little or no empirical evidence. She merely cites the authority of other sociological writers. See also her Aesthetics and the Sociology of Art (London: Allen & Unwin, 1983), for the same flaws.
    • (1985) Patterns of Intention
  • 21
    • 0003892411 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One very interesting art historian who respects social facts but does not reject aesthetic value is Michael Baxandall. See, for example, his Painting and Experience in Fifteenth Century Italy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1972) and Patterns of Intention (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1985). Contrast Janet Wolff's book, The Social Production of Art, which contains little or no empirical evidence. She merely cites the authority of other sociological writers. See also her Aesthetics and the Sociology of Art (London: Allen & Unwin, 1983), for the same flaws.
    • The Social Production of Art
    • Wolff, J.1
  • 22
    • 0345868931 scopus 로고
    • London: Allen & Unwin, for the same flaws
    • One very interesting art historian who respects social facts but does not reject aesthetic value is Michael Baxandall. See, for example, his Painting and Experience in Fifteenth Century Italy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1972) and Patterns of Intention (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1985). Contrast Janet Wolff's book, The Social Production of Art, which contains little or no empirical evidence. She merely cites the authority of other sociological writers. See also her Aesthetics and the Sociology of Art (London: Allen & Unwin, 1983), for the same flaws.
    • (1983) Aesthetics and the Sociology of Art
  • 23
    • 0001535843 scopus 로고
    • Cultural standing through the production perspective
    • edited by Diana Crane London: Routledge
    • See Richard Peterson, "Cultural Standing through the Production Perspective," in The Sociology of Culture, edited by Diana Crane (London: Routledge, 1994), 175.
    • (1994) The Sociology of Culture , pp. 175
    • Peterson, R.1
  • 24
    • 85013304209 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • It is an irony that one part of cultural production that might plausibly be submitted for sociological explanation is the twentieth-century theoretical rejection of the aesthetic by sociologists of art. Sociologists are remarkably shy of applying their techniques to their own views!
  • 25
    • 79954947724 scopus 로고
    • edited by London: Camden, But in fact the "old" art history was never the naive stereotype that it was made out to be. Earnst Gombrich is as canny as any on this score
    • The so-called "new" art history was keen to unearth ideological properties of works of art (and also of writings about them). See The New Art History, edited by A. L. Rees and Frances Borzello (London: Camden, 1986). But in fact the "old" art history was never the naive stereotype that it was made out to be. Earnst Gombrich is as canny as any on this score.
    • (1986) The New Art History
    • Rees, A.L.1    Borzello, F.2
  • 26
    • 0040323043 scopus 로고
    • 4 vols., edited by Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • See Clement Greenberg: Collected Essays and Criticism, 4 vols., edited by John O'Brian (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1986). See also Clement Greenberg's writings in Modernism and Modernity, edited by Benjamin Buchloch, Serge Guilbaut, and David Solkin (Vancouver, British Columbia, Canada: Nova Scotia Press, 1981): "To Cope with Decadence," his contributions to the discussion on T. J. Clark's paper (pp. 188-93), and his contributions to the general panel discussion (pp. 265-77). See also Clement Greenberg, Homemade Esthetics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999).
    • (1986) Clement Greenberg: Collected Essays and Criticism
    • O'Brian, J.1
  • 27
    • 0040917081 scopus 로고
    • edited by Benjamin Buchloch, Serge Guilbaut, and David Solkin Vancouver, British Columbia, Canada: Nova Scotia Press
    • See Clement Greenberg: Collected Essays and Criticism, 4 vols., edited by John O'Brian (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1986). See also Clement Greenberg's writings in Modernism and Modernity, edited by Benjamin Buchloch, Serge Guilbaut, and David Solkin (Vancouver, British Columbia, Canada: Nova Scotia Press, 1981): "To Cope with Decadence," his contributions to the discussion on T. J. Clark's paper (pp. 188-93), and his contributions to the general panel discussion (pp. 265-77). See also Clement Greenberg, Homemade Esthetics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999).
    • (1981) Modernism and Modernity
    • Greenberg, C.1
  • 28
    • 0040917082 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • his contributions to the discussion on and his contributions to the general panel discussion (pp. 265-77)
    • See Clement Greenberg: Collected Essays and Criticism, 4 vols., edited by John O'Brian (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1986). See also Clement Greenberg's writings in Modernism and Modernity, edited by Benjamin Buchloch, Serge Guilbaut, and David Solkin (Vancouver, British Columbia, Canada: Nova Scotia Press, 1981): "To Cope with Decadence," his contributions to the discussion on T. J. Clark's paper (pp. 188-93), and his contributions to the general panel discussion (pp. 265-77). See also Clement Greenberg, Homemade Esthetics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999).
    • To Cope with Decadence , pp. 188-193
    • Clark, T.J.1
  • 29
    • 61049222175 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • See Clement Greenberg: Collected Essays and Criticism, 4 vols., edited by John O'Brian (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1986). See also Clement Greenberg's writings in Modernism and Modernity, edited by Benjamin Buchloch, Serge Guilbaut, and David Solkin (Vancouver, British Columbia, Canada: Nova Scotia Press, 1981): "To Cope with Decadence," his contributions to the discussion on T. J. Clark's paper (pp. 188-93), and his contributions to the general panel discussion (pp. 265-77). See also Clement Greenberg, Homemade Esthetics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999).
    • (1999) Homemade Esthetics
    • Greenberg, C.1
  • 31
    • 0039731138 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • where he describes an economic system in which works of art were exchanged differently from the way works of art have been bought and sold as commodities for most of the twentieth century
    • See Baxandall's Painting and Experience, where he describes an economic system in which works of art were exchanged differently from the way works of art have been bought and sold as commodities for most of the twentieth century.
    • Painting and Experience
    • Baxandall1
  • 32
    • 0040323042 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The CIA funded exhibitions in Paris in 1952 and in Vienna in 1959. See Wise, "Spook Art," 163.
    • Spook Art , pp. 163
    • Wise1
  • 33
    • 85013327114 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Plato says that "beauty is what is pleasant through hearing and sight" (Hippias Major, 298a.). Aquinus says, "Those things we call beautiful are those that please when they are seen" (Suma Theologiae, I.5.4.ad.I). Moreover, the idea that some things "delight the eyes" can be found in Genesis (II.9, III.6) and in Homer (Odyssey, book IV, line 51).
  • 34
    • 34347279633 scopus 로고
    • Unkantian notions of disinterest
    • See Nick Zangill, "UnKantian Notions of Disinterest," British Journal of Aesthetics, 32 (1992): 149-52; and Nick Zangill, "Kant on Pleasure in the Agreeable," Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 53 (1995): 167-76.
    • (1992) British Journal of Aesthetics , vol.32 , pp. 149-152
    • Zangill, N.1
  • 35
    • 34347279633 scopus 로고
    • Kant on pleasure in the agreeable
    • See Nick Zangill, "UnKantian Notions of Disinterest," British Journal of Aesthetics, 32 (1992): 149-52; and Nick Zangill, "Kant on Pleasure in the Agreeable," Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 53 (1995): 167-76.
    • (1995) Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , vol.53 , pp. 167-176
    • Zangill, N.1
  • 36
    • 0040323039 scopus 로고
    • Pleasure and the value of the arts
    • Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press
    • See Jerry Levinson, "Pleasure and the Value of the Arts," in Pleasure, Value and the Arts (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1995).
    • (1995) Pleasure, Value and the Arts
    • Levinson, J.1
  • 37
    • 84970274018 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Nelson Goodman, Languages of Art (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1969), 112.
    • (1969) Languages of Art , pp. 112
    • Goodman, N.1
  • 39
    • 84964992051 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • sec. 50
    • Kant notes that although art making involves the productive imagination, it also involves taste or judgement. See Kant, Critique of Judgement, sec. 50.
    • Critique of Judgement
    • Kant1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.