메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 19, Issue 2, 2002, Pages 212-244

The distribution of life-saving medical resources: Equality, life expectancy, and choice behind the veil

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords

AGE; ANALYTICAL APPROACH; ARTICLE; DISABLED PERSON; ETHICAL THEORY; ETHICS; HEALTH CARE AND PUBLIC HEALTH; HEALTH CARE ORGANIZATION; HOSPITAL ADMISSION; HUMAN; LIFE EXPECTANCY; ORGAN TRANSPLANTATION; PHILOSOPHICAL APPROACH; PROGNOSIS; QUALITY ADJUSTED LIFE YEAR; RANDOMIZATION; RESOURCE ALLOCATION; SOCIAL JUSTICE; STANDARD; UNITED STATES;

EID: 0037514505     PISSN: 02650525     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S0265052502192090     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (17)

References (130)
  • 1
    • 0036165435 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Utilitarianism and the disabled: Distribution of resources
    • As I have elsewhere indicated, I am an intuitionist first and a utilitarian second. See Mark S. Stein, "Utilitarianism and the Disabled: Distribution of Resources, " Bioethics 16, no. 1 (2002): 1-19; and Mark S. Stein, "Utilitarianism and the Disabled: Distribution of Life, " Social Theory and Practice 27, no. 4 (2001): 561-78.
    • (2002) Bioethics , vol.16 , Issue.1 , pp. 1-19
    • Stein, M.S.1
  • 2
    • 0036165435 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Utilitarianism and the disabled: Distribution of life
    • As I have elsewhere indicated, I am an intuitionist first and a utilitarian second. See Mark S. Stein, "Utilitarianism and the Disabled: Distribution of Resources, " Bioethics 16, no. 1 (2002): 1-19; and Mark S. Stein, "Utilitarianism and the Disabled: Distribution of Life, " Social Theory and Practice 27, no. 4 (2001): 561-78.
    • (2001) Social Theory and Practice , vol.27 , Issue.4 , pp. 561-578
    • Stein, M.S.1
  • 3
    • 0004282258 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • See John E. Roemer, Theories of Distributive Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996), 161-62, for an example of this involving infant mortality.
    • (1996) Theories of Distributive Justice , pp. 161-162
    • Roemer, J.E.1
  • 4
    • 0003477501 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press
    • Robert M. Veatch, Transplantation Ethics (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 2000), 280, 288-89.
    • (2000) Transplantation Ethics , pp. 280
    • Veatch, R.M.1
  • 5
    • 85013941764 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I discuss this issue further in Section IIIA.
  • 9
    • 0007118680 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New Haven, CT: Yale University Press
    • See also Ian Shapiro, Democratic Justice (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1999), 207, on the paradoxes of using life expectancy as an allocation criterion.
    • (1999) Democratic Justice , pp. 207
    • Shapiro, I.1
  • 10
    • 85013965635 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I assume, unless otherwise specified, that both candidates for treatment would die without treatment at about the same time, so that the difference in posttreatment life expectancy is the same as the difference in overall life expectancy to be gained from treating one or the other of the candidates. For a discussion of contrary cases, see Section IIIB.
  • 11
    • 85013917428 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I say "almost complete priority, " because one can imagine cases in which the candidate from the "lucky" race has a very low posttreatment life expectancy in any event.
  • 12
    • 0004274013 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Amartya Sen, Inequality Reexamined (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1992).
    • (1992) Inequality Reexamined
    • Amartya, S.1
  • 13
    • 85013956328 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • To its credit, utilitarianism is often associated with a concern to reduce suffering among animals as well as people. However, the issue of concern for animals does not necessarily distinguish utilitarianism from other moral theories. Egalitarians could seek to equalize welfare or resources between people and animals, and rights theorists could seek (and some do seek) to protect the asserted rights of animals.
  • 15
    • 85013907984 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • My definition of welfare egalitarianism is even a little broader than Dworkin's; he hesitates as to Sen. Ibid.
  • 18
    • 0004065933 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • He Sumner has advocated something close to such a life-satisfaction conception of utility. L. W. Sumner, Welfare, Happiness, and Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996).
    • (1996) Welfare, Happiness, and Ethics
    • Sumner, L.W.1
  • 19
    • 0039031422 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Good, fairness and QALYs
    • J. M. Bell and Susan Mendus, eds., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Broome, "Good, Fairness and QALYs, " in J. M. Bell and Susan Mendus, eds., Philosophy and Medical Welfare (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), 70.
    • (1988) Philosophy and Medical Welfare , pp. 70
    • Broome1
  • 20
    • 0033610743 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The value of DALY life: Problems with ethics and validity of disability adjusted life years
    • A description and critique of the DALY measure, see Trude Arnesen and Erik Nord, "The Value of DALY Life: Problems with Ethics and Validity of Disability Adjusted Life Years, " British Medical Journal 319, no. 7222 (1999): 1423-25.
    • (1999) British Medical Journal , vol.319 , Issue.7222 , pp. 1423-1425
    • Arnesen, T.1    Nord, E.2
  • 21
    • 0004149209 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • e et al. note that public-opinion surveys have found some support for the view that some priority in the distribution of life should be given to "children and young adults -particularly those with dependent children." See McKie et al., The Allocation of Health Care Resources, 118.
    • The Allocation of Health Care Resources , pp. 118
    • McKie1
  • 22
    • 0000584144 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • More and better justice
    • Bell and Mendus, eds
    • John Harris, "More and Better Justice, " in Bell and Mendus, eds., Philosophy and Medical Welfare, 92; Michael Lockwood, "Quality of Life and Resource Allocation, " in Bell and Mendus, eds., Philosophy and Medical Welfare, 50.
    • Philosophy and Medical Welfare , pp. 92
    • Harris, J.1
  • 23
    • 0001788538 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Quality of life and resource allocation
    • Bell and Mendus, eds
    • John Harris, "More and Better Justice, " in Bell and Mendus, eds., Philosophy and Medical Welfare, 92; Michael Lockwood, "Quality of Life and Resource Allocation, " in Bell and Mendus, eds., Philosophy and Medical Welfare, 50.
    • Philosophy and Medical Welfare , pp. 50
    • Lockwood, M.1
  • 27
    • 0004295144 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • For discussions of equality and time, see Larry S. Temkin, Inequality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993), 232-44; and Dennis McKerlie, "Equality and Time, " Ethics 99, no. 3 (1989): 475-91. These authors do not focus on the distribution of life.
    • (1993) Inequality , pp. 232-244
    • Temkin, L.S.1
  • 28
    • 84928846848 scopus 로고
    • Equality and time
    • For discussions of equality and time, see Larry S. Temkin, Inequality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993), 232-44; and Dennis McKerlie, "Equality and Time, " Ethics 99, no. 3 (1989): 475-91. These authors do not focus on the distribution of life.
    • (1989) Ethics , vol.99 , Issue.3 , pp. 475-491
    • McKerlie, D.1
  • 29
    • 85013930902 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This would not be a case of "leveling down" to equality; we would only be harming those who are better off if we could to some extent help those who are worse off.
  • 30
    • 0004266379 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • See, for example, Judith Jarvis Thomson, The Realm of Rights (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990), 135-48.
    • (1990) The Realm of Rights , pp. 135-148
    • Thomson, J.J.1
  • 31
    • 85013979495 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Section V below
    • See Section V below.
  • 32
    • 85013904810 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Or, equivalently, we must be confident that the difference between the less urgent candidate's life expectancy with treatment and his life expectancy without treatment is greater than the difference between the more urgent candidate's life expectancy with treatment and her life expectancy without treatment. Suppose that we can give life-saving treatment either to A or to B. Candidate A would die without treatment in one month, and she would die with treatment in six months. Candidate B would die without treatment in ten months, and he would die with treatment in fourteen months. Here, B would have a longer posttreatment life (fourteen months versus six months), but life-year maximization tells us to give the treatment to A, the more urgent candidate, because she would gain five additional months of life, while B would gain only four additional months of life. Equivalently, the fourteen-month posttreatment life of B, the less urgent candidate, would be one month shorter than the sum of (1) the posttreatment life of A, plus (2) the difference between the remaining life of B without treatment and the remaining life of A without treatment.
  • 33
    • 85013903030 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In practice, the imminence criterion is tied to the present moment, as there are always people who are about to die.
  • 36
    • 85013990732 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Section V below
    • See Section V below.
  • 37
    • 0040809995 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kamm states that "one year to a 20-year-old may, morally speaking, be worth three to a 60-year-old." See Kamm, Death and Whom to Save from It, 316. For the reasons given in the text, I conclude that, at least in this example, Kamm actually gives life expectancy at least as much weight as age.
    • Death and Whom to Save from it , pp. 316
    • Kamm1
  • 38
    • 85013887608 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • An advocate of random allocation might (or might not) give preference to candidates who had never previously received scarce life-saving medical resources.
  • 39
    • 0032827284 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Justice and equal opportunities in health care
    • John Harris, "Justice and Equal Opportunities in Health Care, " Bioethics 13, no. 5 (1999): 392-404; John Harris, "Would Aristotle Have Played Russian Roulette?" Journal of Medical Ethics 22, no. 4 (1996): 209-15; John Harris, "Double Jeopardy and the Veil of Ignorance - A Reply, " Journal of Medical Ethics 21, no. 3 (1995): 151-57; Harris, "More and Better Justice, " 75-96.
    • (1999) Bioethics , vol.13 , Issue.5 , pp. 392-404
    • Harris, J.1
  • 40
    • 0029758168 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Would Aristotle have played Russian Roulette?
    • John Harris, "Justice and Equal Opportunities in Health Care, " Bioethics 13, no. 5 (1999): 392-404; John Harris, "Would Aristotle Have Played Russian Roulette?" Journal of Medical Ethics 22, no. 4 (1996): 209-15; John Harris, "Double Jeopardy and the Veil of Ignorance - A Reply, " Journal of Medical Ethics 21, no. 3 (1995): 151-57; Harris, "More and Better Justice, " 75-96.
    • (1996) Journal of Medical Ethics , vol.22 , Issue.4 , pp. 209-215
    • Harris, J.1
  • 41
    • 0029317929 scopus 로고
    • Double jeopardy and the veil of ignorance - A reply
    • John Harris, "Justice and Equal Opportunities in Health Care, " Bioethics 13, no. 5 (1999): 392-404; John Harris, "Would Aristotle Have Played Russian Roulette?" Journal of Medical Ethics 22, no. 4 (1996): 209-15; John Harris, "Double Jeopardy and the Veil of Ignorance - A Reply, " Journal of Medical Ethics 21, no. 3 (1995): 151-57; Harris, "More and Better Justice, " 75-96.
    • (1995) Journal of Medical Ethics , vol.21 , Issue.3 , pp. 151-157
    • Harris, J.1
  • 42
    • 0032827284 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • John Harris, "Justice and Equal Opportunities in Health Care, " Bioethics 13, no. 5 (1999): 392-404; John Harris, "Would Aristotle Have Played Russian Roulette?" Journal of Medical Ethics 22, no. 4 (1996): 209-15; John Harris, "Double Jeopardy and the Veil of Ignorance - A Reply, " Journal of Medical Ethics 21, no. 3 (1995): 151-57; Harris, "More and Better Justice, " 75-96.
    • More and Better Justice , pp. 75-96
    • Harris1
  • 43
    • 0021501701 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Broome, "Good, Fairness and QALYs, " 57-73; John Broome, "Selecting People Randomly, " Ethics 95, no. 1 (1984): 38-55.
    • Good, Fairness and QALYs , pp. 57-73
    • Broome1
  • 44
    • 0021501701 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Selecting people randomly
    • Broome, "Good, Fairness and QALYs, " 57-73; John Broome, "Selecting People Randomly, " Ethics 95, no. 1 (1984): 38-55.
    • (1984) Ethics , vol.95 , Issue.1 , pp. 38-55
    • Broome, J.1
  • 45
    • 0029315578 scopus 로고
    • Justice and the ADA: Does prioritizing and rationing health care discriminate against the disabled?
    • Dan W. Brock, "Justice and the ADA: Does Prioritizing and Rationing Health Care Discriminate against the Disabled?" Social Philosophy and Policy 12, no. 2 (1995): 159-85; Dan Brock, "Ethical Issues in Recipient Selection for Organ Transplantation, " in Deborah Mathieu, ed., Organ Substitution Technology: Ethical, Legal, and Public Policy Issues (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1988), 86-99.
    • (1995) Social Philosophy and Policy , vol.12 , Issue.2 , pp. 159-185
    • Brock, D.W.1
  • 46
    • 85083153978 scopus 로고
    • Ethical issues in recipient selection for organ transplantation
    • Deborah Mathieu, ed., Boulder, CO: Westview Press
    • Dan W. Brock, "Justice and the ADA: Does Prioritizing and Rationing Health Care Discriminate against the Disabled?" Social Philosophy and Policy 12, no. 2 (1995): 159-85; Dan Brock, "Ethical Issues in Recipient Selection for Organ Transplantation, " in Deborah Mathieu, ed., Organ Substitution Technology: Ethical, Legal, and Public Policy Issues (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1988), 86-99.
    • (1988) Organ Substitution Technology: Ethical, Legal, and Public Policy Issues , pp. 86-99
    • Brock, D.1
  • 47
    • 0001991872 scopus 로고
    • Social unity and primary goods
    • Amartya Sen and Bernard Williams, eds., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See, for example, John Rawls, "Social Unity and Primary Goods, " in Amartya Sen and Bernard Williams, eds., Utilitarianism and Beyond (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982), 159-85; Bruce Ackerman, Social Justice in the Liberal State (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1980), 46-48; and Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue, 11-64.
    • (1982) Utilitarianism and Beyond , pp. 159-185
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 48
    • 77954105020 scopus 로고
    • New Haven, CT: Yale University Press
    • See, for example, John Rawls, "Social Unity and Primary Goods, " in Amartya Sen and Bernard Williams, eds., Utilitarianism and Beyond (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982), 159-85; Bruce Ackerman, Social Justice in the Liberal State (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1980), 46-48; and Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue, 11-64.
    • (1980) Social Justice in the Liberal State , pp. 46-48
    • Ackerman, B.1
  • 49
    • 0004223708 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, for example, John Rawls, "Social Unity and Primary Goods, " in Amartya Sen and Bernard Williams, eds., Utilitarianism and Beyond (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982), 159-85; Bruce Ackerman, Social Justice in the Liberal State (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1980), 46-48; and Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue, 11-64.
    • Sovereign Virtue , pp. 11-64
    • Dworkin1
  • 53
    • 0040215486 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Brock, "Justice and the ADA, " 168. The example Brock gives also involves a difference in quality of life, but I think that the difference in life expectancy does all of the intuitive work.
    • Justice and the ADA , pp. 168
    • Brock1
  • 56
    • 85013943173 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Brock's weighted lottery might also give a greater chance to candidates who would have a better posttreatment quality of life, but I will ignore that issue here and focus on life expectancy.
  • 57
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), 168. For an argument that the equiprobability assumption is required by the fundamental principle of equal respect for persons, see Ken Binmore, Playing Fair, vol. 1 of Game Theory and the Social Contract (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1994), 338.
    • (1971) A Theory of Justice , pp. 168
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 58
    • 85013976786 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
    • John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), 168. For an argument that the equiprobability assumption is required by the fundamental principle of equal respect for persons, see Ken Binmore, Playing Fair, vol. 1 of Game Theory and the Social Contract (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1994), 338.
    • (1994) Playing Fair, Vol. 1 of Game Theory and the Social Contract , vol.1 , pp. 338
    • Binmore, K.1
  • 59
    • 85013953112 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • A hypothetical-choice device is only utilitarian if the hypothetical choosers are risk neutral with respect to utility or welfare, not if they are risk neutral with respect to wealth. A hypothetical-choice device in which choosers were risk neutral with respect to wealth would be a wealth-maximizing system.
  • 60
    • 0001698009 scopus 로고
    • Cardinal utility in welfare economics and in the theory of risk-taking
    • John Harsanyi, "Cardinal Utility in Welfare Economics and in the Theory of Risk-Taking, " Journal of Political Economy 61, no. 5 (1953): 434-35; John Harsanyi, "Cardinal Welfare, Individualistic Ethics, and Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility, " Journal of Political Economy 63, no. 4 (1955): 309-21; John Harsanyi, Rational Behavior and Bargaining Equilibrium in Games and Social Situations (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977), 48-83.
    • (1953) Journal of Political Economy , vol.61 , Issue.5 , pp. 434-435
    • Harsanyi, J.1
  • 61
    • 0000689508 scopus 로고
    • Cardinal welfare, individualistic ethics, and interpersonal comparisons of utility
    • John Harsanyi, "Cardinal Utility in Welfare Economics and in the Theory of Risk-Taking, " Journal of Political Economy 61, no. 5 (1953): 434-35; John Harsanyi, "Cardinal Welfare, Individualistic Ethics, and Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility, " Journal of Political Economy 63, no. 4 (1955): 309-21; John Harsanyi, Rational Behavior and Bargaining Equilibrium in Games and Social Situations (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977), 48-83.
    • (1955) Journal of Political Economy , vol.63 , Issue.4 , pp. 309-321
    • Harsanyi, J.1
  • 62
    • 0003706854 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • John Harsanyi, "Cardinal Utility in Welfare Economics and in the Theory of Risk-Taking, " Journal of Political Economy 61, no. 5 (1953): 434-35; John Harsanyi, "Cardinal Welfare, Individualistic Ethics, and Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility, " Journal of Political Economy 63, no. 4 (1955): 309-21; John Harsanyi, Rational Behavior and Bargaining Equilibrium in Games and Social Situations (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977), 48-83.
    • (1977) Rational Behavior and Bargaining Equilibrium in Games and Social Situations , pp. 48-83
    • Harsanyi, J.1
  • 63
    • 0000247373 scopus 로고
    • Measuring marginal utility by reactions to risk
    • William Vickrey, "Measuring Marginal Utility by Reactions to Risk, " Econometrica 13, no. 4 (1945): 319-33; William Vickrey, "Utility, Strategy, and Social Decision Rules, " Quarterly Journal of Economics 74, no. 4 (1960): 507-35.
    • (1945) Econometrica , vol.13 , Issue.4 , pp. 319-333
    • Vickrey, W.1
  • 64
    • 84963012054 scopus 로고
    • Utility, strategy, and social decision rules
    • William Vickrey, "Measuring Marginal Utility by Reactions to Risk, " Econometrica 13, no. 4 (1945): 319-33; William Vickrey, "Utility, Strategy, and Social Decision Rules, " Quarterly Journal of Economics 74, no. 4 (1960): 507-35.
    • (1960) Quarterly Journal of Economics , vol.74 , Issue.4 , pp. 507-535
    • Vickrey, W.1
  • 65
    • 0004282258 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • They are not so considered by everyone. See Roemer, Theories of Distributive Justice, 143 ("Harsanyi's aggregation theorem is not a theorem about utilitarianism").
    • Theories of Distributive Justice , pp. 143
    • Roemer1
  • 66
    • 85013967200 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I say "essentially utilitarian" because of the focus on relative benefit. However, a hypothetical-choice device could exclude considerations relevant to utilitarian analysis if it forced us to consider the interests only of candidates for treatment. See Stein, "Utilitarianism and the Disabled: Distribution of Life, " 575-76 (regarding the effect of discrimination on the general disabled community).
    • Utilitarianism and the Disabled: Distribution of Life , pp. 575-576
    • Stein1
  • 67
    • 0037906986 scopus 로고
    • What is equality? Part 2: Equality of resources
    • Ronald Dworkin, "What Is Equality? Part 2: Equality of Resources, " Philosophy and Public Affairs 10, no. 4 (1981): 283-345 (hereinafter "Equality of Resources"). Dworkin has recently republished "Equality of Resources, " virtually unchanged, as chapter 2 of his book Sovereign Virtue.
    • (1981) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.10 , Issue.4 , pp. 283-345
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 68
    • 0004340089 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Equality of resources
    • virtually unchanged, as chapter 2 of his book
    • Ronald Dworkin, "What Is Equality? Part 2: Equality of Resources, " Philosophy and Public Affairs 10, no. 4 (1981): 283-345 (hereinafter "Equality of Resources"). Dworkin has recently republished "Equality of Resources, " virtually unchanged, as chapter 2 of his book Sovereign Virtue.
    • Sovereign Virtue
    • Dworkin1
  • 69
    • 0028771863 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Will Clinton's plan be fair?
    • January 13
    • Ronald Dworkin, "Will Clinton's Plan Be Fair?" New York Review of Books, January 13, 1994, 20-25. Dworkin has republished most of "Will Clinton's Plan Be Fair?" as chapter 8 of Sovereign Virtue, under the title "Justice and the High Cost of Health."
    • (1994) New York Review of Books , pp. 20-25
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 70
    • 0028771863 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Will Clinton's plan be fair?
    • chapter 8 under the title "Justice and the High Cost of Health."
    • Ronald Dworkin, "Will Clinton's Plan Be Fair?" New York Review of Books, January 13, 1994, 20-25. Dworkin has republished most of "Will Clinton's Plan Be Fair?" as chapter 8 of Sovereign Virtue, under the title "Justice and the High Cost of Health."
    • Sovereign Virtue
    • Dworkin1
  • 72
    • 0040809989 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ronald Dworkin on redistribution to the disabled
    • I have previously made an argument along these lines about Dworkin's system, with respect to the distribution of non-life-saving resources between the disabled and the non-disabled. See Mark S. Stein, "Ronald Dworkin on Redistribution to the Disabled, " Syracuse Law Review 51, no. 4 (2001): 987-1014.
    • (2001) Syracuse Law Review , vol.51 , Issue.4 , pp. 987-1014
    • Stein, M.S.1
  • 76
    • 85013879168 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • A version of maximin that considered the young as "worse off" than the old would not necessarily approve of heroic measures to keep the old alive, but it could easily approve of heroic measures to keep the terminally ill young alive. While at one point Dworkin refers to the distribution of resources between the young and the terminally ill old (ibid 314), at other points he indicates that the prudent insurance test would not approve of massive expenses to buy short life extensions for terminally ill people in general (ibid., 315).
  • 77
    • 85013919819 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 317-18
    • Ibid., 317-18.
  • 78
    • 0004340089 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • n. 6
    • Dworkin, "Equality of Resources, " 298 n. 6, reprinted in Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue, 478 n. 5.
    • Equality of Resources , pp. 298
    • Dworkin1
  • 79
    • 0004223708 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • n. 5
    • Dworkin, "Equality of Resources, " 298 n. 6, reprinted in Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue, 478 n. 5.
    • Sovereign Virtue , pp. 478
    • Dworkin1
  • 81
    • 0004213898 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Ronald Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1978), 151.
    • (1978) Taking Rights Seriously , pp. 151
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 82
    • 0004223708 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In Sovereign Virtue, in a chapter on income support and American welfare reform, Dworkin briefly and opaquely rejects the idea that his system, based on hypothetical choice, is actually a version of utilitarianism. See Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue, 349-50. However, Dworkin does not appear to be aware of the main similarity between his system and utilitarianism, namely, the way in which his system, like utilitarianism, distributes resources to people who would derive greater benefit from those resources, even if those people are already better off than others. This is precisely what sets a maximizing theory like utilitarianism (or the life-expectancy approach) apart from egalitarian theories.
    • Sovereign Virtue , pp. 349-350
    • Dworkin1
  • 83
    • 0003412671 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Norman Daniels, Just Health Care (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985); Daniels, Am I My Parents' Keeper?
    • (1985) Just Health Care
    • Daniels, N.1
  • 99
    • 0004266379 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I believe that Thomson also borrows elements of utilitarianism when she argues that it is permissible to kill one person in order to save five if such a decision would be to the ex ante advantage of all six people. See Thomson, The Realm of Rights, 135-95. But space does not permit a full discussion of Thomson's theory.
    • The Realm of Rights , pp. 135-195
    • Thomson1
  • 100
    • 0031993762 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Selection of recipients for donor organs in transplant medicine
    • Volker H. Schmidt, "Selection of Recipients for Donor Organs in Transplant Medicine, " Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 23, no. 1 (1998): 51-58.
    • (1998) Journal of Medicine and Philosophy , vol.23 , Issue.1 , pp. 51-58
    • Schmidt, V.H.1
  • 101
    • 85013872795 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • UNOS is a private entity that performs quasi-public functions. UNOS administers the Organ Procurement and Transplantation Network (OPTN). The OPTN is also a private entity, but it is authorized by law to oversee numerous aspects of transplant medicine in the United States. See 42 U.S.C. §§ 273-74 (1999); and 42 C.F.R. pt. 121 (1999). In most respects, it has been accurate to say that UNOS is the OPTN, but the identity of these two quasi-official bodies may now be diverging.
    • (1999) U.S.C. §§ 273-74 , vol.42
  • 102
    • 85013897352 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • UNOS is a private entity that performs quasi-public functions. UNOS administers the Organ Procurement and Transplantation Network (OPTN). The OPTN is also a private entity, but it is authorized by law to oversee numerous aspects of transplant medicine in the United States. See 42 U.S.C. §§ 273-74 (1999); and 42 C.F.R. pt. 121 (1999). In most respects, it has been accurate to say that UNOS is the OPTN, but the identity of these two quasi-official bodies may now be diverging.
    • (1999) C.F.R. , vol.42
  • 103
    • 85013911738 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The unlisted: Live and let die over transplants
    • April 5, sec. 4
    • Sheryl Gay Stolberg, "The Unlisted: Live and Let Die over Transplants, " New York Times, April 5, 1998, sec. 4, p. 3. The story quotes bioethicist Arthur Caplan as saying: "We love to fight as a society over who gets a transplant from the waiting list. What we are ashamed of asking is who gets on the waiting list. That is where the fiercest, toughest rationing takes place."
    • (1998) New York Times , pp. 3
    • Stolberg, S.G.1
  • 106
    • 0040215472 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Contraindications to heart transplantation
    • It used to be thought that a patient over 50 was too old for a heart transplant. See Special Advisory Group, National Heart, Lung, and Blood Institute, "Contraindications to Heart Transplantation, " in Mathieu, ed., Organ Substitution Technology, 308. Just in the few years between 1996 and 2000, the percentage of organ transplants going to patients over 65 has been rising. UNOS, "UNOS Critical Data: Transplants by Recipient Age, " available on-line at www.unos.org/newsroom/critdata_transplants_age.htm [retrieved July 5, 2001].
    • Organ Substitution Technology , pp. 308
    • Mathieu1
  • 107
    • 0039031401 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • retrieved July 5, 2001
    • It used to be thought that a patient over 50 was too old for a heart transplant. See Special Advisory Group, National Heart, Lung, and Blood Institute, "Contraindications to Heart Transplantation, " in Mathieu, ed., Organ Substitution Technology, 308. Just in the few years between 1996 and 2000, the percentage of organ transplants going to patients over 65 has been rising. UNOS, "UNOS Critical Data: Transplants by Recipient Age, " available on-line at www.unos.org/newsroom/critdata_transplants_age.htm [retrieved July 5, 2001].
    • UNOS Critical Data: Transplants by Recipient Age
  • 108
    • 4243482495 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The doctor's world -for heart surgeons, many careful steps
    • July 10
    • For example, the recipient of the first self-contained, battery-powered, artificial heart had been rejected as a candidate for a human heart transplant "because he had kidney failure and abnormally high blood pressure in blood vessels in his lungs which made a transplant unlikely to succeed." Lawrence K. Altman, "The Doctor's World-For Heart Surgeons, Many Careful Steps, " New York Times, July 10 2001 F1.
    • (2001) New York Times , pp. F1
    • Altman, L.K.1
  • 109
    • 85013887372 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • UNOS Policy 3.6
    • UNOS Policy 3.6, available on-line at http:/ /www.unos.org/ About/policy_policies03_06.
  • 110
    • 85013910870 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • However, patients with chronic liver failure in Status 2A may be as close to death as are patients in Status 1. See ibid. for a full description of medical urgency statuses for livers.
  • 111
    • 85013955538 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • UNOS Policy 3.7, retrieved July 1, 2001
    • UNOS Policy 3.7, available on-line at http:/ /www.unos.org/ About/policy_policies03_07. htm [retrieved July 1, 2001].
  • 112
    • 85013915117 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See ibid. for a full description of these statuses
    • See ibid. for a full description of these statuses.
  • 113
    • 85013919930 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid
    • Ibid.
  • 114
    • 85013882517 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For livers, the Eurotransplant website lists, as allocation criteria, "blood group, the donor's weight, clinical urgency and waiting list." For hearts and lungs, Eurotransplant lists "blood group, the donor's height and weight, clinical urgency and waiting list." This information is available on-line at http:/ /www.eurotransplant.nl/about.cfm?content=20 [retrieved July 15, 2001].
  • 115
    • 85013911665 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • UNOS Policy 3.6; UNOS Policy 3.7
    • UNOS Policy 3.6; UNOS Policy 3.7.
  • 117
  • 118
    • 85013922416 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • UNOS Policy 3.7.7, retrievedJuly 1, 2001
    • For example, UNOS Policy 3.7.7 states that candidates for a heart/lung transplant will receive such a transplant if they are either (1) at the top of the heart list in priority, or (2) at the top of the lung list, and there is no suitable Status 1A heart candidate. See UNOS Policy 3.7.7, available on-line at http:/ /www.unos.org/ About/policy_policies03_07.htm [retrieved July 1, 2001].
  • 121
    • 85013921440 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Age is a priority factor among pediatric candidates for kidney transplants, and pediatric candidates generally have priority with respect to organs from pediatric donors.
  • 123
    • 0003477501 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Veatch, Transplantation Ethics, 312-13, 337; Schmidt, "Selection of Organ Recipients, " 56-58.
    • Transplantation Ethics , pp. 312-313
    • Veatch1
  • 126
    • 85013963730 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Yes, this is a tendentious statement, but egalitarian theorists make similar statements about their own favored theories, and without a trace of irony!
  • 127
    • 0040215405 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • table 54, retrieved July 5, 2001
    • UNOS, "2000 SR and OPTN Annual Report, " table 54, available on-line at http:// www.unos.org/data/anrpt00/ar00_table54_11-li.htm [retrieved July 5, 2001].
    • 2000 SR and OPTN Annual Report
  • 129
    • 0003477501 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an extended account, see Veatch, Transplantation Ethics, 363-87. A national list would be more feasible for livers than for hearts and lungs, as livers can survive longer outside the body.
    • Transplantation Ethics , pp. 363-387
    • Veatch1
  • 130
    • 84871359487 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Institute of Medicine, Organ Procurement and Transplantation, 96. The Institute of Medicine is another private entity that is quasi-public in function. It is affiliated with the National Academy of Sciences and often provides advice to the federal government in the United States.
    • Organ Procurement and Transplantation , pp. 96


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.