메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 20, Issue 6, 2001, Pages 553-580

The disenfranchisement of felons

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0035601266     PISSN: 01675249     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1023/A:1011942626677     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (24)

References (48)
  • 2
    • 84937261783 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Disenfranchised
    • See Jamie Fellner and Marc Mauer, Losing the Vote: The Impact of Felony Disenfranchisement Laws in the United States (Washington, D.C.: Human Rights Watch and The Sentencing Project, 1998), and Andrew L. Shapiro, "The Disenfranchised," The American Prospect 35 (1997): 60-62.
    • (1997) The American Prospect , vol.35 , pp. 60-62
    • Shapiro, A.L.1
  • 3
    • 0042487733 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Richardson v. Ramirez 418 US 24 (1974)
    • Richardson v. Ramirez 418 US 24 (1974).
  • 4
    • 0041986880 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • However, the Supreme Court has ruled that states may not make completely arbitrary distinctions between groups of felons with respect to their disenfranchisement. See Hunter v. Underwood, 471 US 222 (1985)
    • However, the Supreme Court has ruled that states may not make completely arbitrary distinctions between groups of felons with respect to their disenfranchisement. See Hunter v. Underwood, 471 US 222 (1985).
  • 6
    • 0041986881 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cited in Shapiro, "The Disenfranchised," 60. See also Fellner and Mauer, Losing the Vote: 8-9.
    • The Disenfranchised , pp. 60
    • Shapiro1
  • 7
    • 0041986879 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cited in Shapiro, "The Disenfranchised," 60. See also Fellner and Mauer, Losing the Vote: 8-9.
    • Losing the Vote , pp. 8-9
    • Fellner1    Mauer2
  • 8
    • 0041986877 scopus 로고
    • Voting Rights of Convicted Persons
    • For an overview of disenfranchisement laws in Australia, see Jennifer Fitzgerald and George Zdenkowski, "Voting Rights of Convicted Persons," Criminal Law Journal 11 (1987): 11-39. For a discussion critical of sweeping felon disenfranchisement practices in the United States, as compared with narrowly targeted felon disenfranchisement practices in Germany, see Nora V. Demleitner, "Continuing Payment on One's Debt to Society: The German Model of Felon Disenfranchisement as an Alternative," Minnesota Law Review 84 (2000): 753- 804.
    • (1987) Criminal Law Journal , vol.11 , pp. 11-39
    • Fitzgerald, J.1    Zdenkowski, G.2
  • 9
    • 34548554296 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Continuing Payment on One's Debt to Society: The German Model of Felon Disenfranchisement as an Alternative
    • For an overview of disenfranchisement laws in Australia, see Jennifer Fitzgerald and George Zdenkowski, "Voting Rights of Convicted Persons," Criminal Law Journal 11 (1987): 11-39. For a discussion critical of sweeping felon disenfranchisement practices in the United States, as compared with narrowly targeted felon disenfranchisement practices in Germany, see Nora V. Demleitner, "Continuing Payment on One's Debt to Society: The German Model of Felon Disenfranchisement as an Alternative," Minnesota Law Review 84 (2000): 753-804.
    • (2000) Minnesota Law Review , vol.84 , pp. 753-804
    • Demleitner, N.V.1
  • 10
    • 0042487732 scopus 로고
    • Rights in Legislation
    • P.M.S. Hacker and J. Raz (eds.), Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • This conception of rights, also known as the interest theory of rights, is usually attributed to Neil MacCormick, "Rights in Legislation," in P.M.S. Hacker and J. Raz (eds.), Law, Morality, and Society (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977), pp. 189-209, and Joseph Raz, The Morality of Freedom (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), pp. 65-92.
    • (1977) Law, Morality, and Society , pp. 189-209
    • MacCormick, N.1
  • 11
    • 0003956640 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • This conception of rights, also known as the interest theory of rights, is usually attributed to Neil MacCormick, "Rights in Legislation," in P.M.S. Hacker and J. Raz (eds.), Law, Morality, and Society (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977), pp. 189-209, and Joseph Raz, The Morality of Freedom (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), pp. 65-92.
    • (1986) The Morality of Freedom , pp. 65-92
    • Raz, J.1
  • 12
    • 0004284447 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press
    • My account of the interests designated by the right to democratic participation draws on J. Roland Pennock, Democratic Political Theory (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1979), pp. 441-445, and Thomas Christiano, "Social Choice and Democracy," in D. Copp, J. Hampton and J. Roemer (eds.), The Idea of Democracy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), pp. 173-195.
    • (1979) Democratic Political Theory , pp. 441-445
    • Pennock, J.R.1
  • 13
    • 0041986875 scopus 로고
    • Social Choice and Democracy
    • D. Copp, J. Hampton and J. Roemer (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • My account of the interests designated by the right to democratic participation draws on J. Roland Pennock, Democratic Political Theory (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1979), pp. 441-445, and Thomas Christiano, "Social Choice and Democracy," in D. Copp, J. Hampton and J. Roemer (eds.), The Idea of Democracy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), pp. 173-195.
    • (1993) The Idea of Democracy , pp. 173-195
    • Christiano, T.1
  • 14
    • 0011593990 scopus 로고
    • Democracy' as a Contested Idea
    • P. Green (ed.), Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press
    • For an overview of the debate among democratic theorists, see Phillip Green, "'Democracy' as a Contested Idea," in P. Green (ed.), Democracy (Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press, 1993), pp. 2-18.
    • (1993) Democracy , pp. 2-18
    • Green, P.1
  • 15
    • 0042988480 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This claim should only pose problems for those who attempt to ground rights in the actual preferences of individuals, rather than in their rational preferences or in a normative conception of the person.
  • 16
    • 0042988479 scopus 로고
    • New York: McGraw-Hill
    • See Michael Mushlin, Rights of Prisoners (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1993), pp. 157-161.
    • (1993) Rights of Prisoners , pp. 157-161
    • Mushlin, M.1
  • 17
    • 84928224456 scopus 로고
    • The Right to Threaten and the Right to Punish
    • See Warren Quinn, "The Right to Threaten and the Right to Punish," Philosophy and Public Affairs 14 (1985): 332-333; and Rex Martin, A System of Rights (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1993), pp. 280-284. See also my "Criminal Offenders and Right Forfeiture," Journal of Social Philosophy 32 (2001): 78-89.
    • (1985) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.14 , pp. 332-333
    • Quinn, W.1
  • 18
    • 0004098751 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • See Warren Quinn, "The Right to Threaten and the Right to Punish," Philosophy and Public Affairs 14 (1985): 332-333; and Rex Martin, A System of Rights (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1993), pp. 280-284. See also my "Criminal Offenders and Right Forfeiture," Journal of Social Philosophy 32 (2001): 78-89.
    • (1993) A System of Rights , pp. 280-284
    • Martin, R.1
  • 19
    • 0041485830 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Criminal Offenders and Right Forfeiture
    • See Warren Quinn, "The Right to Threaten and the Right to Punish," Philosophy and Public Affairs 14 (1985): 332-333; and Rex Martin, A System of Rights (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1993), pp. 280-284. See also my "Criminal Offenders and Right Forfeiture," Journal of Social Philosophy 32 (2001): 78-89.
    • (2001) Journal of Social Philosophy , vol.32 , pp. 78-89
  • 20
    • 0042487731 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Rights and Responsibilities
    • 17n
    • The view that disenfranchisement is simply an adjunct to legal punishment and therefore not directly related to the achievement of traditional penal aims is stated by John Deigh in "On Rights and Responsibilities," Law and Philosophy 7 (1998): 158, 17n.
    • (1998) Law and Philosophy , vol.7 , pp. 158
    • Deigh, J.1
  • 21
    • 0041986878 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Several of the arguments in this section might be coupled with retributive approaches to the justification of legal punishment. However, the arguments need not be coupled in this way and are not treated as such.
  • 22
    • 0019511183 scopus 로고
    • The Right to Vote as Applied to Ex-Felons
    • John R. Vile, "The Right to Vote as Applied to Ex-Felons," Federal Probation 45 (1981): 16. Vile rejects most of the arguments for disenfranchisement that he finds in the legal literature.
    • (1981) Federal Probation , vol.45 , pp. 16
    • Vile, J.R.1
  • 23
    • 0041485839 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Vile, "The Right to Vote as Applied to Ex-Felons," 15. See also Fitzgerald and Zdenkowski, "Voting Rights of Convicted Persons," 12. A. John Simmons argues that Locke's account of the rights forfeited by punishment is largely retributive in character, but he notes that Locke provides no careful formulation of the doctrine of forfeiture. See The Lockean Theory of Rights (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1992), pp. 149-152.
    • The Right to Vote as Applied to Ex-Felons , pp. 15
    • Vile1
  • 24
    • 0041986876 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Vile, "The Right to Vote as Applied to Ex-Felons," 15. See also Fitzgerald and Zdenkowski, "Voting Rights of Convicted Persons," 12. A. John Simmons argues that Locke's account of the rights forfeited by punishment is largely retributive in character, but he notes that Locke provides no careful formulation of the doctrine of forfeiture. See The Lockean Theory of Rights (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1992), pp. 149-152.
    • Voting Rights of Convicted Persons , pp. 12
    • Fitzgerald1    Zdenkowski2
  • 25
    • 0003779590 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press
    • Vile, "The Right to Vote as Applied to Ex-Felons," 15. See also Fitzgerald and Zdenkowski, "Voting Rights of Convicted Persons," 12. A. John Simmons argues that Locke's account of the rights forfeited by punishment is largely retributive in character, but he notes that Locke provides no careful formulation of the doctrine of forfeiture. See The Lockean Theory of Rights (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1992), pp. 149-152.
    • (1992) The Lockean Theory of Rights , pp. 149-152
  • 27
    • 0006299267 scopus 로고
    • St. Paul, MN: West
    • The criminal law distinguishes felonies and misdemeanors on grounds that are simply too arbitrary for philosophical purposes. Essentially, felonies are crimes punishable by death or incarceration in a state prison, while misdemeanors are crimes punishable by fines or imprisonment in a local jail. See Wayne R. LaFave and Austin W. Scott, Jr., Handbook on Criminal Law (St. Paul, MN: West, 1972), p. 26. Yet we are unlikely to find any more philosophically defensible and clear line separating lesser and greater crimes, and thus the sentences appropriate to each, because in many instances the differences between lesser and greater crimes will be matters of degree. For example, felony and misdemeanor theft may only be distinguished by the value of the property stolen.
    • (1972) Handbook on Criminal Law , pp. 26
    • LaFave, W.R.1    Scott A.W., Jr.2
  • 28
    • 0042988476 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Hardness of Hard Treatment
    • Andrew Ashworth and Martin Wasik (eds.), Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • For discussion of such limits, see John Kleinig, "The Hardness of Hard Treatment," in Andrew Ashworth and Martin Wasik (eds.), Fundamentals in Sentencing Theory (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998), pp. 273-298.
    • (1998) Fundamentals in Sentencing Theory , pp. 273-298
    • Kleinig, J.1
  • 29
    • 0042487730 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • It is also not obvious, if deterrence is our goal, that the franchise should automatically be restored to offenders once they have endured the other sanctions attaching to their crimes. We would at least have to consider whether the benefits of continuing their disenfranchisement exceeded any losses or burdens imposed by doing so.
  • 30
    • 0003785029 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: HarperCollins
    • See, for instance, the recommendations made by the National Criminal Justice Commission in Steven R. Donziger (ed.), The Real War on Crime (New York: HarperCollins, 1996).
    • (1996) The Real War on Crime
    • Donziger, S.R.1
  • 31
    • 0003715865 scopus 로고
    • Dorderecht, Netherlands: D. Reidel
    • See, for instance, Wojciech Sadurski, Giving Desert Its Due (Dorderecht, Netherlands: D. Reidel, 1985), pp. 221-258.
    • (1985) Giving Desert Its Due , pp. 221-258
    • Sadurski, W.1
  • 32
    • 0041161623 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • For criticism of this type of retributivism, see R.A. Duff, Trials and Punishments (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986), pp. 205-217.
    • (1986) Trials and Punishments , pp. 205-217
    • Duff, R.A.1
  • 34
    • 0010035413 scopus 로고
    • Correcting Harms Versus Righting Wrongs: The Goal of Retribution
    • Those attracted to more communicative forms of retributivism might suggest that disenfranchisement be used to censure serious offenders or distance the community from their crimes. But again the problem is that various penal sanctions can be used to perform this act of communication, and we need some explanation why disenfranchisement is the most suitable or effective sanction for this purpose. In some cases (e.g., crimes involving direct attacks on democratic political institutions or electoral processes) such an explanation might be available. Yet, as we have seen, most serious crimes do not consist of such attacks. For discussion of a communicative form of retributivism, see Jean Hampton, "Correcting Harms Versus Righting Wrongs: The Goal of Retribution," UCLA Law Review 39 (1992): 1659-1702.
    • (1992) UCLA Law Review , vol.39 , pp. 1659-1702
    • Hampton, J.1
  • 35
    • 0042988477 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I am not suggesting that the death penalty is an inappropriate sanction for such offenders. But there will be many serious offenders who are not appropriate recipients of the death penalty, assuming any offenders are, and it is such offenders that I focus on. Those sentenced to death might also suffer the sort of political death the retributive argument advocates while they await their executions.
  • 36
    • 79959845783 scopus 로고
    • The Moral Education Theory of Punishment
    • For one version of the moral education approach, see Jean Hampton, "The Moral Education Theory of Punishment," Philosophy and Public Affairs 13 (1984): 208-238.
    • (1984) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.13 , pp. 208-238
    • Hampton, J.1
  • 37
    • 0042487728 scopus 로고
    • Can Punishment Morally Educate?
    • See Russ Shafer-Landau, "Can Punishment Morally Educate?" Law and Philosophy 10 (1991): 189-219.
    • (1991) Law and Philosophy , vol.10 , pp. 189-219
    • Shafer-Landau, R.1
  • 38
    • 85021783301 scopus 로고
    • Marxism and Retribution
    • One of the first philosophers to emphasize this point was Jeffrie G. Murphy in "Marxism and Retribution," Philosophy and Public Affairs 2 (1973): 217-243.
    • (1973) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.2 , pp. 217-243
    • Murphy, J.G.1
  • 39
    • 0003785029 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Donziger, The Real War on Crime, pp. 27-30; also Elliott Currie, Crime and Punishment in America (New York: Henry Holt, 1998), pp. 110-161.
    • The Real War on Crime , pp. 27-30
    • Donziger1
  • 40
    • 0003709610 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Henry Holt
    • See Donziger, The Real War on Crime, pp. 27-30; also Elliott Currie, Crime and Punishment in America (New York: Henry Holt, 1998), pp. 110-161.
    • (1998) Crime and Punishment in America , pp. 110-161
    • Currie, E.1
  • 41
    • 0003684227 scopus 로고
    • Washington, D.C.: U.S. Department of Justice
    • Sourcebook of Criminal Justice Statistics (Washington, D.C.: U.S. Department of Justice, 1995), p. 562.
    • (1995) Sourcebook of Criminal Justice Statistics , pp. 562
  • 42
    • 0041485837 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Currie notes that the Hispanic inmate population has more than quintupled since 1980. See Crime and Punishment in America, p. 14.
    • Crime and Punishment in America , pp. 14
  • 43
    • 0041485837 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Currie cites estimates that as many fifty to sixty percent of state prison inmates have drug problems severe enough to warrant treatment. See Crime and Punishment in America, p. 166.
    • Crime and Punishment in America , pp. 166
  • 44
    • 0041485837 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Currie characterizes the tendency of incarceration to make some offenders worse as "one of the best-established findings in criminology ..." See Crime and Punishment in America, p. 74.
    • Crime and Punishment in America , pp. 74
  • 45
    • 0003785029 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, for instance, Donziger, The Real War on Crime, pp. 99-129. See also Michael Tonry, Malign Neglect: Race, Crime, and Punishment in America (New York: Oxford University Press, 1995).
    • The Real War on Crime , pp. 99-129
    • Donziger1
  • 47
    • 0041986876 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Concerns have been expressed about how the voting residence of felons is to be determined. Large voting prison populations in rural localities might overwhelm the local electorate. See Fitzgerald and Zdenkowski, "Voting Rights of Convicted Persons," 36-37. One way to address this problem would be to require felons to adopt as their voting residence the last place they lived prior to their imprisonment.
    • Voting Rights of Convicted Persons , pp. 36-37
    • Fitzgerald1    Zdenkowski2


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.