메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 109, Issue 3, 1999, Pages 548-578

Of assisted suicide and "the philosophers' brief"

(1)  Weithman, Paul J a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords

ANALYTICAL APPROACH; ARTICLE; ASSISTED SUICIDE; BEHAVIOR; CIVIL RIGHTS; DEATH AND EUTHANASIA; DOCTOR PATIENT RELATION; ETHICS; EUTHANASIA; FEMALE; GOVERNMENT; GOVERNMENT REGULATION; HUMAN; INFORMED CONSENT; JURISPRUDENCE; MALE; MEDICAL ETHICS; MISCELLANEOUS NAMED GROUPS; MORALITY; MOTIVATION; PALLIATIVE THERAPY; PASSIVE EUTHANASIA; PHYSICIAN; PROFESSIONAL PATIENT RELATIONSHIP; RIGHT TO DIE; SEXUAL CRIME; SEXUALITY; SOCIAL CHANGE; SOCIAL CONTROL; SOCIAL DOMINANCE; SOCIAL PSYCHOLOGY; TRUST; UNITED STATES; VACCO V. QUILL; VOLUNTARY EUTHANASIA; VULNERABLE POPULATION; WASHINGTON V. GLUCKSBERG;

EID: 0033106468     PISSN: 00141704     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1086/233921     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (16)

References (84)
  • 1
    • 0009403402 scopus 로고
    • of Harvard Classics, ed. Charles W. Eliot Cambridge, Mass.: P. F. Collier & Sons
    • Scientific Papers: Physiology, Medicine, Surgery, Geology, vol. 38 of Harvard Classics, ed. Charles W. Eliot (Cambridge, Mass.: P. F. Collier & Sons, 1910), p. 3.
    • (1910) Scientific Papers: Physiology, Medicine, Surgery, Geology , vol.38 , pp. 3
  • 2
    • 0031302515 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Use of the hippocratic oath: A review of twentieth century practice and a content analysis of oaths administered in medical schools in the U.S. and Canada in 1993
    • R. D. Orr, N. Pang, E. D. Pellegrino, and M. Seigier, "Use of the Hippocratic Oath: A Review of Twentieth Century Practice and a Content Analysis of Oaths Administered in Medical Schools in the U.S. and Canada in 1993 "Journal of Clinical Ethics 8 (1997): 377-88.
    • (1997) Journal of Clinical Ethics , vol.8 , pp. 377-388
    • Orr, R.D.1    Pang, N.2    Pellegrino, E.D.3    Seigier, M.4
  • 3
    • 0031587707 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Assisted suicide: The philosophers' brief
    • March 27
    • Ronald Dworkin et al., "Assisted Suicide: The Philosophers' Brief," New York Review of Books 44 (March 27, 1997): 41-47; pp. 41-42 are an introduction authored solely by Dworkin.
    • (1997) New York Review of Books , vol.44 , pp. 41-47
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 4
    • 0030621662 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The right to die
    • For an argument that the right to assisted suicide does not merit constitutional protection by an author who believes the practice should be legalized by democratic processes, see Cass Sunstein, "The Right to Die," Yale Law Journal 106 (1997): 1123-63.
    • (1997) Yale Law Journal , vol.106 , pp. 1123-1163
    • Sunstein, C.1
  • 5
    • 85033954876 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin et al., p. 41
    • Dworkin et al., p. 41.
  • 7
    • 85033942345 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • emphasis added
    • Ibid., p. 43, emphasis added.
  • 8
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Columbia University Press
    • John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996), p. 243; cf. pp. 1-li, as well as "The Idea of Public Reason Revisited," University of Chicago Law Review 64 (1997): 765-807.
    • (1996) Political Liberalism , pp. 243
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 9
    • 0347873666 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The idea of public reason revisited
    • John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996), p. 243; cf. pp. 1-li, as well as "The Idea of Public Reason Revisited," University of Chicago Law Review 64 (1997): 765-807.
    • (1997) University of Chicago Law Review , vol.64 , pp. 765-807
  • 13
    • 0029979403 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Life support: The debate continues
    • R. W. Carlson, M. L. Campbell, and R. R. Frank, "Life Support: The Debate Continues," Chest 109 (1996): 852-53; a patient is "terminally weaned" when the support provided by the mechanical ventilator is gradually decreased but the endotracheal tube is left in place.
    • (1996) Chest , vol.109 , pp. 852-853
    • Carlson, R.W.1    Campbell, M.L.2    Frank, R.R.3
  • 14
    • 0026570345 scopus 로고
    • Ordering and administration of sedatives and analgesics during the withholding and withdrawal of life support from critically ill patients
    • William C. Wilson, Nicholas G. Smedira, Carol Fink, James A. McDowell, and John M. Luce, "Ordering and Administration of Sedatives and Analgesics during the Withholding and Withdrawal of Life Support from Critically Ill Patients," Journal of the American Medical Association 267 (1992): 949-53, esp. p. 949.
    • (1992) Journal of the American Medical Association , vol.267 , pp. 949-953
    • Wilson, W.C.1    Smedira, N.G.2    Fink, C.3    McDowell, J.A.4    Luce, J.M.5
  • 16
    • 0027508847 scopus 로고
    • Dehydration in terminally ill patients: Is it appropriate palliative care?
    • M. Andrews, T. R. Bell, S. A. Smith, J. F. Tischler, and J. M. Veglia, "Dehydration in Terminally Ill Patients: Is It Appropriate Palliative Care?" Postgraduate Medicine 93 (1993): 201-3, 206-8, cited at Howard Brody, Margaret L. Campbell, Kathy Faber-Langendoen, and Karen S. Ogle, "Withdrawing Intensive Lite-Sustaining Treatment - Recommendations for Compassionate Clinical Management," New England Journal of Medicine 336 (1997): 652-57, n. 50.
    • (1993) Postgraduate Medicine , vol.93 , pp. 201-203
    • Andrews, M.1    Bell, T.R.2    Smith, S.A.3    Tischler, J.F.4    Veglia, J.M.5
  • 17
    • 0031049741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Withdrawing intensive lite-sustaining treatment - Recommendations for compassionate clinical management
    • cited at
    • M. Andrews, T. R. Bell, S. A. Smith, J. F. Tischler, and J. M. Veglia, "Dehydration in Terminally Ill Patients: Is It Appropriate Palliative Care?" Postgraduate Medicine 93 (1993): 201-3, 206-8, cited at Howard Brody, Margaret L. Campbell, Kathy Faber-Langendoen, and Karen S. Ogle, "Withdrawing Intensive Lite-Sustaining Treatment - Recommendations for Compassionate Clinical Management," New England Journal of Medicine 336 (1997): 652-57, n. 50.
    • (1997) New England Journal of Medicine , vol.336 , Issue.50 , pp. 652-657
    • Brody, H.1    Campbell, M.L.2    Faber-Langendoen, K.3    Ogle, K.S.4
  • 18
    • 0015769226 scopus 로고
    • Rights and deaths
    • sec. II
    • See Judith Jarvis Thomson, "Rights and Deaths," Philosophy and Public Affairs 2 (1973): 146-59, sec. II; also Thomas Nagel, "War and Massacre," Philosophy and Public Affairs 1 (1972): 123-44, pp. 130-31.
    • (1973) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.2 , pp. 146-159
    • Thomson, J.J.1
  • 19
    • 0015769226 scopus 로고
    • War and massacre
    • See Judith Jarvis Thomson, "Rights and Deaths," Philosophy and Public Affairs 2 (1973): 146-59, sec. II; also Thomas Nagel, "War and Massacre," Philosophy and Public Affairs 1 (1972): 123-44, pp. 130-31.
    • (1972) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.1 , pp. 123-144
    • Nagel, T.1
  • 20
    • 85033955043 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin et al., p. 42
    • Dworkin et al., p. 42; see also F. M. Kamm, "A Right to Choose Death?" Boston Review 22 (1997): 20-23, esp. n. 1 and accompanying text.
  • 21
    • 0002794247 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A right to choose death?
    • Dworkin et al., p. 42; see also F. M. Kamm, "A Right to Choose Death?" Boston Review 22 (1997): 20-23, esp. n. 1 and accompanying text.
    • (1997) Boston Review , vol.22 , Issue.1 , pp. 20-23
    • Kamm, F.M.1
  • 22
    • 0003906719 scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • See Robert P. George, Making Men Moral (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993), p. 190.
    • (1993) Making Men Moral , pp. 190
    • George, R.P.1
  • 23
    • 66749131592 scopus 로고
    • Promises and practices
    • See the brief but very illuminating remarks of Thomas Scanlon, "Promises and Practices," Philosophy and Public Affairs 19 (1990): 199-226, pp. 223 ff.
    • (1990) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.19 , pp. 199-226
    • Scanlon, T.1
  • 24
    • 84928219263 scopus 로고
    • Authority and justification
    • Whether the reasons provided by an oath substitute for other of the agent's reasons or supplement other reasons which remain in force is an interesting question but one I cannot pursue here. On substitutional and supplementary reasons generally, see Joseph Raz, "Authority and Justification," Philosophy and Public Affairs 14 (1985): 3-29.
    • (1985) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.14 , pp. 3-29
    • Joseph, R.1
  • 25
    • 0026420526 scopus 로고
    • Why doctors must not kill
    • For the thought that the prohibitions of the Hippocratic Oath respond to what I have called the "role-specific temptations" of phydcians, I am indebted to Leon Kass, "Why Doctors Must Not Kill," Commonweal 118 (1991): 472-76, particularly p. 474.
    • (1991) Commonweal , vol.118 , pp. 472-476
    • Kass, L.1
  • 26
    • 0003935249 scopus 로고
    • New York: Vintage
    • I say "typically" because X might have reasons to seduce Y with the intention of breaking off at the last moment; cf. Albert Camus, The Stranger (New York: Vintage, 1954), p. 40.
    • (1954) The Stranger , pp. 40
    • Camus, A.1
  • 27
    • 0025841814 scopus 로고
    • Sexual misconduct in the practice of medicine
    • See American Medical Association (AMA), Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs, "Sexual Misconduct in the Practice of Medicine," Journal of the American Medical Association 266 (1991): 2741-45, nn. 2-4 and accompanying text.
    • (1991) Journal of the American Medical Association , vol.266 , Issue.2-4 , pp. 2741-2745
  • 28
    • 85033944375 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kass, pp. 473 and 476
    • Kass, pp. 473 and 476; see also Richard A. McCormick, S.J., "Euthanasia or Allowing to Die: Ethical Distinctions" (unpublished manuscript, University of Notre Dame), p. 19.
  • 31
    • 85033961025 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kass, p. 474
    • Kass, p. 474.
  • 32
    • 0009386076 scopus 로고
    • Are moral requirements hypothetical imperatives?
    • John McDowell, "Are Moral Requirements Hypothetical Imperatives?" Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (1978), pp. 13-29, p. 27. There may seem to be something paradoxical about the suggestion that a virtue should be centered on or associated with an absolute prohibition. Virtue theories typically accord a preeminent role to the cultivation of practical wisdom. They do so, it might be thought, because good actions proceed from properly conducted practical deliberation about the circumstances of an action and its probable consequences. Good action, on this view, requires just the sort of reasoned flexibility that is precluded by adherence to absolute prohibitions. This is why many contemporary defenses of virtue theory oppose it to the rigidity of rule-based theories of morality. There is, however, no paradox in asserting that a person's virtuous character depends in part upon her honoring absolute prohibitions. The thought that there is depends upon an unduly restricted conception of virtue theory. Thus as one would expect, absolute prohibitions occupy a central place in the powerful and richly detailed virtue theory of Thomas Aquinas. It is important that Aquinas's arguments for the claim that it is always wrong to perform an act of a given sort typically turn on the claim that acts of that kind are contrary to one or another of the virtues. Furthermore, in Aquinas's view, the virtuous agent does not exercise practical reason to determine whether she may act against a putatively absolute prohibition in the case at hand. Rather she exerc ses it to determine whether the action she is considering is, under the circumstances, of a type governed by the absolute prohibition in question. Aquinas's famous discussion of whether an agent who takes another's property in desperation violates the absolute prohibition of theft is exemplary in this regard; see Summa theologiae II-IiI66,7 ad 2. Finally, though I cannot argue the point here, I would conjecture that the emergence of casuistry as a theory of moral reasoning in the early modern period is best explained by the fact that thinkers like Aquinas had assigned practical reason precisely the task I have just described. For the compatibility of virtue theory with absolute prohibitions, see generally Joseph Boyle, "Natural Law and the Ethics of Traditions," in Natural Law Theory: Contemporary Essays ed. Robert P. George (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992), pp. 3-30, For an attempt to accommodate an absolute prohibition on lying within a Thomistic theory of the virtues but without Aquinas's theological presuppositions, see Alasdair MacIntyre, "Truthfulness, Lies and Moral Philosophers: What Can We Learn from Mill and Kant?" in Tanner Lectures on Human Values, vol. 16 (Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press, 1995), pp. 307-62. On the emergence of casuistry with explicit reference to Aquinas's discussion of theft, see Edmund Leites, ed., Conscience and Casuistry in Early Modern Europe (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1988), p. 7.
    • (1978) Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society , pp. 13-29
    • McDowell, J.1
  • 33
    • 0009386077 scopus 로고
    • Truthfulness, lies and moral philosophers: What can we learn from Mill and Kant?
    • Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press
    • John McDowell, "Are Moral Requirements Hypothetical Imperatives?" Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (1978), pp. 13-29, p. 27. There may seem to be something paradoxical about the suggestion that a virtue should be centered on or associated with an absolute prohibition. Virtue theories typically accord a preeminent role to the cultivation of practical wisdom. They do so, it might be thought, because good actions proceed from properly conducted practical deliberation about the circumstances of an action and its probable consequences. Good action, on this view, requires just the sort of reasoned flexibility that is precluded by adherence to absolute prohibitions. This is why many contemporary defenses of virtue theory oppose it to the rigidity of rule-based theories of morality. There is, however, no paradox in asserting that a person's virtuous character depends in part upon her honoring absolute prohibitions. The thought that there is depends upon an unduly restricted conception of virtue theory. Thus as one would expect, absolute prohibitions occupy a central place in the powerful and richly detailed virtue theory of Thomas Aquinas. It is important that Aquinas's arguments for the claim that it is always wrong to perform an act of a given sort typically turn on the claim that acts of that kind are contrary to one or another of the virtues. Furthermore, in Aquinas's view, the virtuous agent does not exercise practical reason to determine whether she may act against a putatively absolute prohibition in the case at hand. Rather she exerc ses it to determine whether the action she is considering is, under the circumstances, of a type governed by the absolute prohibition in question. Aquinas's famous discussion of whether an agent who takes another's property in desperation violates the absolute prohibition of theft is exemplary in this regard; see Summa theologiae II-IiI66,7 ad 2. Finally, though I cannot argue the point here, I would conjecture that the emergence of casuistry as a theory of moral reasoning in the early modern period is best explained by the fact that thinkers like Aquinas had assigned practical reason precisely the task I have just described. For the compatibility of virtue theory with absolute prohibitions, see generally Joseph Boyle, "Natural Law and the Ethics of Traditions," in Natural Law Theory: Contemporary Essays ed. Robert P. George (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992), pp. 3-30, For an attempt to accommodate an absolute prohibition on lying within a Thomistic theory of the virtues but without Aquinas's theological presuppositions, see Alasdair MacIntyre, "Truthfulness, Lies and Moral Philosophers: What Can We Learn from Mill and Kant?" in Tanner Lectures on Human Values, vol. 16 (Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press, 1995), pp. 307-62. On the emergence of casuistry with explicit reference to Aquinas's discussion of theft, see Edmund Leites, ed., Conscience and Casuistry in Early Modern Europe (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1988), p. 7.
    • (1995) Tanner Lectures on Human Values , vol.16 , pp. 307-362
    • MacIntyre, A.1
  • 34
    • 0009386078 scopus 로고
    • New York: Cambridge University Press
    • John McDowell, "Are Moral Requirements Hypothetical Imperatives?" Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (1978), pp. 13-29, p. 27. There may seem to be something paradoxical about the suggestion that a virtue should be centered on or associated with an absolute prohibition. Virtue theories typically accord a preeminent role to the cultivation of practical wisdom. They do so, it might be thought, because good actions proceed from properly conducted practical deliberation about the circumstances of an action and its probable consequences. Good action, on this view, requires just the sort of reasoned flexibility that is precluded by adherence to absolute prohibitions. This is why many contemporary defenses of virtue theory oppose it to the rigidity of rule-based theories of morality. There is, however, no paradox in asserting that a person's virtuous character depends in part upon her honoring absolute prohibitions. The thought that there is depends upon an unduly restricted conception of virtue theory. Thus as one would expect, absolute prohibitions occupy a central place in the powerful and richly detailed virtue theory of Thomas Aquinas. It is important that Aquinas's arguments for the claim that it is always wrong to perform an act of a given sort typically turn on the claim that acts of that kind are contrary to one or another of the virtues. Furthermore, in Aquinas's view, the virtuous agent does not exercise practical reason to determine whether she may act against a putatively absolute prohibition in the case at hand. Rather she exerc ses it to determine whether the action she is considering is, under the circumstances, of a type governed by the absolute prohibition in question. Aquinas's famous discussion of whether an agent who takes another's property in desperation violates the absolute prohibition of theft is exemplary in this regard; see Summa theologiae II-IiI66,7 ad 2. Finally, though I cannot argue the point here, I would conjecture that the emergence of casuistry as a theory of moral reasoning in the early modern period is best explained by the fact that thinkers like Aquinas had assigned practical reason precisely the task I have just described. For the compatibility of virtue theory with absolute prohibitions, see generally Joseph Boyle, "Natural Law and the Ethics of Traditions," in Natural Law Theory: Contemporary Essays ed. Robert P. George (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992), pp. 3-30, For an attempt to accommodate an absolute prohibition on lying within a Thomistic theory of the virtues but without Aquinas's theological presuppositions, see Alasdair MacIntyre, "Truthfulness, Lies and Moral Philosophers: What Can We Learn from Mill and Kant?" in Tanner Lectures on Human Values, vol. 16 (Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press, 1995), pp. 307-62. On the emergence of casuistry with explicit reference to Aquinas's discussion of theft, see Edmund Leites, ed., Conscience and Casuistry in Early Modern Europe (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1988), p. 7.
    • (1988) Conscience and Casuistry in Early Modern Europe , pp. 7
    • Leites, E.1
  • 35
    • 0003705423 scopus 로고
    • Chicago: American Medical Association
    • As the American Medical Association's "Code of Medical Ethics" says: "The Oath of Hippocrates (Christianized in the tenth or eleventh century A.D. to eliminate reference to pagan gods) has remained in western civilization as an expression of ideal conduct for the physician" ; see Code of Medical Ethics: Current Opinions with Annotations (Chicago: American Medical Association, 1994). On conception-dependent desires, see Rawls, Political Liberalism, pp. 82 ff.
    • (1994) Code of Medical Ethics: Current Opinions with Annotations
  • 36
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As the American Medical Association's "Code of Medical Ethics" says: "The Oath of Hippocrates (Christianized in the tenth or eleventh century A.D. to eliminate reference to pagan gods) has remained in western civilization as an expression of ideal conduct for the physician" ; see Code of Medical Ethics: Current Opinions with Annotations (Chicago: American Medical Association, 1994). On conception-dependent desires, see Rawls, Political Liberalism, pp. 82 ff.
    • Political Liberalism
    • Rawls1
  • 37
    • 85033964479 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See n. 2 above
    • See n. 2 above.
  • 38
    • 85033955333 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • on file with the Office of Student Affairs, Harvard Medical School, Cambridge, Mass
    • "The Oath of the Class of 1994," on file with the Office of Student Affairs, Harvard Medical School, Cambridge, Mass.
    • The Oath of the Class of 1994
  • 40
    • 0031005191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Correspondence
    • According to a 1990 study, 50 percent of Dutch physicians "suggest" physician-assisted suicide to their patients. See Herbert Hendin, "Correspondence," New England Journal of Medicine 336 (1997): 1385,
    • (1997) New England Journal of Medicine , vol.336 , pp. 1385
    • Hendin, H.1
  • 41
    • 0026782711 scopus 로고
    • Euthanasia and other medical decisions concerning the end of life
    • citing Paul J. van der Maas, J. M. van Delden, and Loes Pijenborg, "Euthanasia and Other Medical Decisions Concerning the End of Life," Health Policy 22 (1992): 1-262. One reason for thinking the percentage would be higher in the United States than in the Netherlands is connected with the requirements of informed consent. Some hospital counsels warn that if physician-assisted suicide were legalized here, staff physicians at American hospitals would be required to present assisted suicide as an option to the terminally ill in order to obtain their informed consent to any treatment of their condition. Or at least, they warn that physicians would be required to do so in the absence of prohibition by a legislatively imposed "gag rule"; the model statute cited at n. 34 below does not contain any such rule. It may even be that worries about informed consent account for the high incidence of discussion of physician-assisted suicide between Dutch doctors and their patients. I am grateful to Maura Ryan for these points.
    • (1992) Health Policy , vol.22 , pp. 1-262
    • Van Der Maas, P.J.1    Van Delden, J.M.2    Pijenborg, L.3
  • 42
    • 84990557133 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Letter to the editor
    • quoted in New York Times October 26, sec. 1
    • Derek Humphry, Letter to the Editor, New York Times, quoted in New York Times (October 26, 1997), sec. 1, p. 19.
    • (1997) New York Times , pp. 19
    • Humphry, D.1
  • 43
    • 0031047996 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Can clinical interventions change care at the end of life?
    • For the latter, see Hanson, Tulsky, and Danis, "Can Clinical Interventions Change Care at the End of Life?" Annals of Internal Medicine 126 (1997): 381-88; also "Doctors Ignoring Last Wishes of the Dying, Study Finds," New York Times News Service (November 22, 1995).
    • (1997) Annals of Internal Medicine , vol.126 , pp. 381-388
    • Hanson, T.1    Danis2
  • 44
    • 0031047996 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Doctors ignoring last wishes of the dying, study finds
    • November 22
    • For the latter, see Hanson, Tulsky, and Danis, "Can Clinical Interventions Change Care at the End of Life?" Annals of Internal Medicine 126 (1997): 381-88; also "Doctors Ignoring Last Wishes of the Dying, Study Finds," New York Times News Service (November 22, 1995).
    • (1995) New York Times News Service
  • 45
    • 0347771689 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A model state act to authorize and regulate physician-assisted suicide
    • As of this writing the model statute is also available through the Deathnet homepage at
    • Charles H. Baron et al., "A Model State Act to Authorize and Regulate Physician-Assisted Suicide," Harvard Journal of Legislation 33 (1996): 1-34, see pp. 27-28. As of this writing the model statute is also available through the Deathnet homepage at http:// www.rights.org/deathnet/MSA.html.
    • (1996) Harvard Journal of Legislation , vol.33 , pp. 1-34
    • Baron, C.H.1
  • 46
    • 85033971733 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Baron et al., p. 17
    • Baron et al., p. 17.
  • 47
    • 85033946574 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • According to a Harris poll released April 28, 1997, more Americans regard medicine as a "very prestigious" profession than any other occupation. The poll also concludes that 87 percent of Americans regard medicine as "prestigious" - far more than any other occupation except scientist, which medicine edged out by a single percentage point. Results of the poll are on file with Louis Harris and Associates, Inc. I am grateful to the Information Services section of Harris and Associates for maki ng their data available to me.
  • 48
    • 85033959649 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Baron et al., pp. 5-6
    • See Baron et al., pp. 5-6.
  • 49
    • 85033956178 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As the American Medical Association acknowledges; see "Brief of the American Medical Association, the American Nurses Association and the American Psychiatric Association, et al.," pp. 7-8, filed in Vaccov. Quill, 117 S. Ct. 2232 (1997)
    • As the American Medical Association acknowledges; see "Brief of the American Medical Association, the American Nurses Association and the American Psychiatric Association, et al.," pp. 7-8, filed in Vaccov. Quill, 117 S. Ct. 2232 (1997).
  • 51
    • 85033966054 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See van der Maas, van Delden, and Pijenborg, p. 50
    • See van der Maas, van Delden, and Pijenborg, p. 50, cited at Susan M. Wolf, "Gender, Feminism and Death," in Feminism and Bioethics: Beyond Reproduction, ed. Susan M. Wolf (New York: Oxford University Press, 1996), pp. 282-317, p. 313, n. 62. Wolf's essay is an outstanding feminist analysis of euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide, with special attention to the way self-sacrificial images of women in literature and culture bear on the questions at issue.
  • 52
    • 0002923178 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gender, feminism and death
    • ed. Susan M. Wolf New York: Oxford University Press
    • See van der Maas, van Delden, and Pijenborg, p. 50, cited at Susan M. Wolf, "Gender, Feminism and Death," in Feminism and Bioethics: Beyond Reproduction, ed. Susan M. Wolf (New York: Oxford University Press, 1996), pp. 282-317, p. 313, n. 62. Wolf's essay is an outstanding feminist analysis of euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide, with special attention to the way self-sacrificial images of women in literature and culture bear on the questions at issue.
    • (1996) Feminism and Bioethics: Beyond Reproduction , Issue.62 , pp. 282-317
    • Wolf, S.M.1
  • 53
    • 0029050262 scopus 로고
    • Attitudes of older people toward suicide and assisted suicide: An analysis of gallup poll findings
    • Seidlitz, Duberstein, Cox, and Conwell, "Attitudes of Older People toward Suicide and Assisted Suicide: An Analysis of Gallup Poll Findings," Journal of the American Geriatric Society 43 (1995): 993-98, p. 996.
    • (1995) Journal of the American Geriatric Society , vol.43 , pp. 993-998
    • Seidlitz1    Duberstein2    Cox3    Conwell4
  • 54
    • 85033962378 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The 'may' is important for two reasons. One is that there are a number of possible explanations for Gallup's polling data. The other is that a Harris poll conducted immediately after the U.S. Supreme Court decided Glucksberg and Quill showed that a majority of those polled disagreed with the Court's decision, regardless of race or annual income. Whether the results of the poll indicate an enduring trend or merely an episodic reaction to the Court's decision can only be shown by further polling. One reason for questioning the significance of its results is that it showed those polled were equally likely to disagree with the Court's decision whether or not they were familiar with the cases decided. Unlike the earlier Gallup poll, the Harris poll surveyed adults in all age groups. Results of this poll are on file with Louis Harris and Associates, Inc. I am grateful to the Information Services section of Harris and Associates for making their data available to me and to the editors of Ethics for stressing the need to clarify the first of I hese points.
  • 55
    • 85033972659 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin et al., p. 46
    • Dworkin et al., p. 46.
  • 57
    • 0003981612 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • Bowers v. Hardwick may indicate the Supreme Court's refusal to recognize this interest, but Dworkin's writing suggests that he thinks citizens have it. Indeed it is precisely because he thinks citizens have this interest and the Court refused to recognize it that he thinks Bowers mistaken. See Ronald Dworkin, A Matter of Principle (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985), p. 68.
    • (1985) A Matter of Principle , pp. 68
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 61
    • 85033972813 scopus 로고
    • Public vulnerable to bad doctors, study says
    • April 16, sec. I
    • The purposes are prosecution for an injury resulting from sexual conduct during treatment; see 750.520b. (1) (f) (iv) of the Michigan Criminal Code. 50. See "Public Vulnerable to Bad Doctors, Study Says," Los Angeles Times (April 16, 1989), sec. I, p. 3: "In a 100-page report, the University of San Diego's Center for Public Interest Law asserted that a massive restructuring of the California Board of Medical Quality Assurance and the procedures it uses for disciplining physicians will have to be undertaken by the Legislature before consumers can be assured that incompetent doctors are being weeded out of the medical system." That the story from the Times is included in the legislative history of the California statute suggests that the Legislature passed the bill at least in part in response to the study, which clearly evinced concern with public confidence in the medical profession. I am grateful to the staff of the Archives of the California State Assembly for making documents relevant to the bill's legislative history available to me.
    • (1989) Los Angeles Times , pp. 3
  • 62
    • 85033963986 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • It might be objected that there is a disanalogy between the cases because statutes prohibiting sexual relations between physicians and patients do not make it impossible for patients to act on their liberty interest in having nex with other competent and consenting adults. They simply forbid them to act on it with their doctors. But there is no disanalogy. Statutes prohibiting physician-assisted suicide do not make it impossible for patients to act on their alleged liberty interest in determining the time and manner of their deaths. They simply forbid one way of acting on that interest, actions which involve the help of their doctors.
  • 63
    • 85033970697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I am grateful to Cass Sunstein for urging me to emphasize this important point.
  • 68
    • 0009389326 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Feed the face
    • June 9
    • See Michael Walzer,"Feed the Face," New Republic 84 (June 9, 1997): 29.
    • (1997) New Republic , vol.84 , pp. 29
    • Walzer, M.1
  • 69
    • 85033952218 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See n. 38
    • See n. 38.
  • 70
    • 85033960938 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I am grateful to Maura Ryan for invaluable discussion and bibliographic advice.
  • 71
    • 0028283011 scopus 로고
    • Physicians and their patients' suicides
    • I am indebted to Steven H. Miles, "Physicians and Their Patients' Suicides," Journal of the American Medical Association 271 (1994): 1786-88.
    • (1994) Journal of the American Medical Association , vol.271 , pp. 1786-1788
    • Miles, S.H.1
  • 72
    • 0016815884 scopus 로고
    • Psychiatry and the elderly: An overview
    • Robert N. Butler, "Psychiatry and the Elderly: An Overview," American Journal of Psychiatry 132 (1975): 893-900; also Pirkko J. Clarke, "Exploration of Countertransference toward the Dying," American Journal of Orthopsychiatry 51 (1981): 71-77. The point is especially well put in Edmund D. Pellegrino, "Compassion Needs Reason Too," Journal of the American Medical Association 270 (1993): 874-75.
    • (1975) American Journal of Psychiatry , vol.132 , pp. 893-900
    • Butler, R.N.1
  • 73
    • 0019350899 scopus 로고
    • Exploration of countertransference toward the dying
    • Robert N. Butler, "Psychiatry and the Elderly: An Overview," American Journal of Psychiatry 132 (1975): 893-900; also Pirkko J. Clarke, "Exploration of Countertransference toward the Dying," American Journal of Orthopsychiatry 51 (1981): 71-77. The point is especially well put in Edmund D. Pellegrino, "Compassion Needs Reason Too," Journal of the American Medical Association 270 (1993): 874-75.
    • (1981) American Journal of Orthopsychiatry , vol.51 , pp. 71-77
    • Clarke, P.J.1
  • 74
    • 0027312750 scopus 로고
    • Compassion needs reason too
    • Robert N. Butler, "Psychiatry and the Elderly: An Overview," American Journal of Psychiatry 132 (1975): 893-900; also Pirkko J. Clarke, "Exploration of Countertransference toward the Dying," American Journal of Orthopsychiatry 51 (1981): 71-77. The point is especially well put in Edmund D. Pellegrino, "Compassion Needs Reason Too," Journal of the American Medical Association 270 (1993): 874-75.
    • (1993) Journal of the American Medical Association , vol.270 , pp. 874-875
    • Pellegrino, E.D.1
  • 75
    • 85033961706 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See n. 31
    • See n. 31.
  • 76
    • 0026090027 scopus 로고
    • Perceived quality of life and preferences for life-sustaining treatment in older adults
    • See Richard Uhlmann and Robert Pearlman, "Perceived Quality of Life and Preferences for Life-Sustaining Treatment in Older Adults," Archives of Internal Medicine 151 (1991): 495-97. Another study found that physicians significantly underestimated their chronically ill patients' desire for resuscitation. See Richard Uhlmann, Robert Pearlman, and Kevin Cain, "Physicians' and Spouses' Predictions of Elderly Patients' Resuscitation Preferences," Journal of Gerontology 43 (1988): M115-M121.
    • (1991) Archives of Internal Medicine , vol.151 , pp. 495-497
    • Uhlmann, R.1    Pearlman, R.2
  • 77
    • 0023791347 scopus 로고
    • Physicians' and spouses' predictions of elderly patients' resuscitation preferences
    • See Richard Uhlmann and Robert Pearlman, "Perceived Quality of Life and Preferences for Life-Sustaining Treatment in Older Adults," Archives of Internal Medicine 151 (1991): 495-97. Another study found that physicians significantly underestimated their chronically ill patients' desire for resuscitation. See Richard Uhlmann, Robert Pearlman, and Kevin Cain, "Physicians' and Spouses' Predictions of Elderly Patients' Resuscitation Preferences," Journal of Gerontology 43 (1988): M115-M121.
    • (1988) Journal of Gerontology , vol.43
    • Uhlmann, R.1    Pearlman, R.2    Cain, K.3
  • 79
    • 0009380260 scopus 로고
    • New York: Norton
    • See, e.g., Timothy Quill, Death and Dignity (New York: Norton, 1993), pp. 16, 38-39.
    • (1993) Death and Dignity , pp. 16
    • Quill, T.1
  • 80
    • 0025327310 scopus 로고
    • Black-white disparities in health care
    • Council on Judicial and Ethical Affairs of the American Medical Association (AMA), "Black-White Disparities in Health Care," Journal of the American Medical Association 263 (1990): 2344-46.
    • (1990) Journal of the American Medical Association , vol.263 , pp. 2344-2346
  • 82
    • 0026944999 scopus 로고
    • The tuskegee legacy: AIDS and the black community
    • Cited at James H. Jones, "The Tuskegee Legacy: AIDS and the Black Community," Hastings Center Report 22 (1992): 38-40, n. 1 and accompanying text.
    • (1992) Hastings Center Report , vol.22 , Issue.1 , pp. 38-40
    • Jones, J.H.1
  • 83
    • 85033946765 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NIH Publ. no. 94-0324-P (Bethesda, Md.: NIH)
    • On the difficulty and the explanation, see National Institutes of Health (NIH), NIH Outreach Notebook on the Inclusion of Women and Minorities as Subjects in Clinical Studies, NIH Publ. no. 94-0324-P (Bethesda, Md.: NIH), p. 13, where the Tuskegee Syphilis Study is mentioned. I am grateful to Sue Ellen Levkoff for helpful discussion of this matter.
    • NIH Outreach Notebook on the Inclusion of Women and Minorities as Subjects in Clinical Studies , pp. 13
  • 84
    • 85033947738 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jones, p. 39, which attributes resistance to clinical studies of AIDS to the legacy of Tuskegee
    • Jones, p. 39, which attributes resistance to clinical studies of AIDS to the legacy of Tuskegee.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.