메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 51, Issue 2, 1999, Pages 269-296

International liberalism and distributive justice a survey of recent thought

(1)  Beitz, Charles R a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords

LIBERALISM; NATION STATE;

EID: 0032930926     PISSN: 00438871     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S0043887100008194     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (152)

References (115)
  • 1
    • 0004264732 scopus 로고
    • New York: Columbia University Press
    • The literatures are vast and for the most part well known. For the dispute about realism, see David A. Baldwin, ed., Neorealism and Neoliberalism: The Contemporary Debate (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993). On the democratic peace, see Michael W. Doyle's important two-part article "Kant, Liberal Legacies, and Foreign Affairs," pts. 1 and 2, Philosophy and Public Affairs 12 (Sumer and Fall 1983). For a recent effort to formulate a liberal analytical perspective on international affairs, see Andrew Moravcsik, "Taking Preferences Seriously: A Liberal Theory of International Politics," International Organization 51 (Autumn 1997).
    • (1993) Neorealism and Neoliberalism: The Contemporary Debate
    • Baldwin, D.A.1
  • 2
    • 0000248716 scopus 로고
    • Kant, Liberal Legacies, and Foreign Affairs
    • Sumer and Fall
    • The literatures are vast and for the most part well known. For the dispute about realism, see David A. Baldwin, ed., Neorealism and Neoliberalism: The Contemporary Debate (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993). On the democratic peace, see Michael W. Doyle's important two-part article "Kant, Liberal Legacies, and Foreign Affairs," pts. 1 and 2, Philosophy and Public Affairs 12 (Sumer and Fall 1983). For a recent effort to formulate a liberal analytical perspective on international affairs, see Andrew Moravcsik, "Taking Preferences Seriously: A Liberal Theory of International Politics," International Organization 51 (Autumn 1997).
    • (1983) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.12 , Issue.PARTS 1 AND 2
    • Doyle, M.W.1
  • 3
    • 0000546136 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Taking Preferences Seriously: A Liberal Theory of International Politics
    • Autumn
    • The literatures are vast and for the most part well known. For the dispute about realism, see David A. Baldwin, ed., Neorealism and Neoliberalism: The Contemporary Debate (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993). On the democratic peace, see Michael W. Doyle's important two-part article "Kant, Liberal Legacies, and Foreign Affairs," pts. 1 and 2, Philosophy and Public Affairs 12 (Sumer and Fall 1983). For a recent effort to formulate a liberal analytical perspective on international affairs, see Andrew Moravcsik, "Taking Preferences Seriously: A Liberal Theory of International Politics," International Organization 51 (Autumn 1997).
    • (1997) International Organization , vol.51
    • Moravcsik, A.1
  • 5
    • 84923812747 scopus 로고
    • Princeton: Princeton University Press, chap. 11
    • Moravcsik (fn. 1), for example, is clear about this (p. 548). This is not to say that the analytical literature lacks normative motivation; see, e.g., Robert O. Keohane, After Hegemony: Cooperation and Discord in the World Political Economy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984), chap. 11; and idem, "International Liberalism Reconsidered," in John Dunn, ed., The Economic Limits to Modern Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990). Michael Doyle's recent book examines liberal as well as realist and Marxist perspectives on an array of normative questions; see Doyle, Ways of War and Peace (New York: W. W. Norton, 1997).
    • (1984) After Hegemony: Cooperation and Discord in the World Political Economy
    • Keohane, R.O.1
  • 6
    • 0003209793 scopus 로고
    • International Liberalism Reconsidered
    • John Dunn, ed., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Moravcsik (fn. 1), for example, is clear about this (p. 548). This is not to say that the analytical literature lacks normative motivation; see, e.g., Robert O. Keohane, After Hegemony: Cooperation and Discord in the World Political Economy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984), chap. 11; and idem, "International Liberalism Reconsidered," in John Dunn, ed., The Economic Limits to Modern Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990). Michael Doyle's recent book examines liberal as well as realist and Marxist perspectives on an array of normative questions; see Doyle, Ways of War and Peace (New York: W. W. Norton, 1997).
    • (1990) The Economic Limits to Modern Politics
  • 7
    • 0003409521 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: W. W. Norton
    • Moravcsik (fn. 1), for example, is clear about this (p. 548). This is not to say that the analytical literature lacks normative motivation; see, e.g., Robert O. Keohane, After Hegemony: Cooperation and Discord in the World Political Economy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984), chap. 11; and idem, "International Liberalism Reconsidered," in John Dunn, ed., The Economic Limits to Modern Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990). Michael Doyle's recent book examines liberal as well as realist and Marxist perspectives on an array of normative questions; see Doyle, Ways of War and Peace (New York: W. W. Norton, 1997).
    • (1997) Ways of War and Peace
    • Doyle1
  • 8
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Harvard University Press
    • Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971), 7.
    • (1971) A Theory of Justice , pp. 7
    • Rawls1
  • 9
    • 0003766854 scopus 로고
    • London: Macmillan
    • See, for example, Bull's distinction between "international," "individual," and "cosmopolitan" conceptions of international justice in The Anarchical Society, 2d ed. (London: Macmillan, 1995), 81.
    • (1995) The Anarchical Society, 2d Ed. , pp. 81
    • Bull1
  • 10
    • 0004002174 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • Miller, On Nationality (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995); Rawls, "The Law of Peoples," in Stephen Shute and Susan Hurley, eds., On Human Rights: The Oxford Amnesty Lectures 1993 (New York: Basic Books, 1993); R. J. Vincent, Human Rights and International Relations (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986). Although she refers to international distributive justice only in passing, Yael Tamir's comments in Liberal Nationalism (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993) are interesting for the particularistic foundations adduced for the view; see pp. 117-21, 160-63.
    • (1995) On Nationality
    • Miller1
  • 11
    • 0002923507 scopus 로고
    • The Law of Peoples
    • Stephen Shute and Susan Hurley, eds., New York: Basic Books
    • Miller, On Nationality (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995); Rawls, "The Law of Peoples," in Stephen Shute and Susan Hurley, eds., On Human Rights: The Oxford Amnesty Lectures 1993 (New York: Basic Books, 1993); R. J. Vincent, Human Rights and International Relations (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986). Although she refers to international distributive justice only in passing, Yael Tamir's comments in Liberal Nationalism (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993) are interesting for the particularistic foundations adduced for the view; see pp. 117-21, 160-63.
    • (1993) On Human Rights: the Oxford Amnesty Lectures 1993
    • Rawls1
  • 12
    • 0004123866 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Miller, On Nationality (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995); Rawls, "The Law of Peoples," in Stephen Shute and Susan Hurley, eds., On Human Rights: The Oxford Amnesty Lectures 1993 (New York: Basic Books, 1993); R. J. Vincent, Human Rights and International Relations (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986). Although she refers to international distributive justice only in passing, Yael Tamir's comments in Liberal Nationalism (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993) are interesting for the particularistic foundations adduced for the view; see pp. 117-21, 160-63.
    • (1986) Human Rights and International Relations
    • Vincent, R.J.1
  • 13
    • 0003929983 scopus 로고
    • Princeton: Princeton University Press
    • Miller, On Nationality (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995); Rawls, "The Law of Peoples," in Stephen Shute and Susan Hurley, eds., On Human Rights: The Oxford Amnesty Lectures 1993 (New York: Basic Books, 1993); R. J. Vincent, Human Rights and International Relations (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986). Although she refers to international distributive justice only in passing, Yael Tamir's comments in Liberal Nationalism (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993) are interesting for the particularistic foundations adduced for the view; see pp. 117-21, 160-63.
    • (1993) Liberal Nationalism , pp. 117-121
    • Tamir, Y.1
  • 14
    • 85038190990 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Miller (fn 6), 75-77, 107-8. All forms of social liberalism must specify some such threshold, but views may differ about its character and severity. For example, compare the passages cited from Miller with Vincent (fn. 6), 143-50; and Rawls (fn. 6), 76-77.
  • 15
    • 85038175980 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls (fn. 6)
    • Rawls (fn. 6).
  • 16
    • 85038190345 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See particularly Rawls (fn. 4), sec. 58
    • See particularly Rawls (fn. 4), sec. 58.
  • 17
    • 74549134013 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Law of Peoples
    • forthcoming
    • I leave aside many other parts of "The Law of Peoples." I note also that Rawls has set forth the theory in greater detail in a monograph also entitled The Law of Peoples (forthcoming). It is a rich and stimulating work that will repay close study. Regrettably, I must limit myself here to the already published paper.
    • The Law of Peoples
  • 18
    • 85038184299 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The idea of a well-ordered, hierarchical society is intended to represent societies based on "comprehensive" (e.g., religious) doctrines. Such a society, although neither liberal nor democratic, seeks the common good of its people and respects basic human rights. Rawls (fn. 6), 60-62.
  • 19
    • 85038190273 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The law of peoples is prior to domestic justice in that it limits the authority of individual states, not only in their foreign relations but also, through the requirement to respect human rights, in regard to their own people. Human rights, therefore, establish the limits of acceptable pluralism in international society. Rawls (fn. 6), 70-71.
  • 20
    • 85038177869 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Ibid., 56. The passage refers explicitly to the principles that would be agreed to by representatives of liberal societies. Rawls later claims that the same principles would be accepted by representatives of well-ordered nonliberal societies (pp. 64-65).
  • 21
    • 85038185298 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid. 42
    • Ibid., 42.
  • 22
    • 85038177118 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Of the latter there are two nonexclusive kinds: "outlaw" states, which do not respect the law ot peoples (e.g., by failing to respect the integrity of other states or their own peoples' human rights), and societies subject to unfavorable economic and social conditions, which for that reason are unable to sustain well-ordered institutions. Rawls (fn. 6), 72.
  • 23
    • 85038186539 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 73
    • Ibid., 73.
  • 24
    • 85038177740 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 75
    • Ibid., 75.
  • 25
    • 0004240568 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • For a recent example of the standard view, see Alan Gewirth, The Community of Rights (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996).
    • (1996) The Community of Rights
    • Gewirth, A.1
  • 26
    • 85038178090 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls (fn. 6), 68, 78
    • Rawls (fn. 6), 68, 78.
  • 27
    • 85038180540 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Ibid., 71. Rawls holds that there may be a right of forcible intervention, for example, when necessary to defend the well-ordered societies against "outlaw regimes" or ("in grave cases") to defend individuals subject to outlaw regimes that threaten their human rights (p. 73).
  • 28
    • 0038889466 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • Ibid., 227-28 n. 46. But Rawls also holds that all well-ordered regimes should aim to satisfy their people's basic needs and that therefore the rights to liberty and security imply rights to subsistence (p. 225 n. 26). Though as a matter of political theory this seems correct, there is some tension with the language of the declaration, which plainly presupposes a distinction between liberty and welfare. For the 1948 declaration, see Ian Brownlie, ed., Basic Documents in International Law, 4th ed. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995), 255-61.
    • (1995) Basic Documents in International Law, 4th Ed. , pp. 255-261
    • Brownlie, I.1
  • 29
    • 84976003206 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Rawlsian Theory of International Law
    • See Fernando R. Teson, "The Rawlsian Theory of International Law," Ethics and International Affairs 9 (1995); and Peter Jones, "International Human Rights: Philosophical or Political?" in Simon Caney, David George, and Peter Jones, eds., National Rights, International Obligations (Boulder, Colo.: Westview, 1996).
    • (1995) Ethics and International Affairs , vol.9
    • Teson, F.R.1
  • 30
    • 84976003206 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • International Human Rights: Philosophical or Political?
    • Simon Caney, David George, and Peter Jones, eds., Boulder, Colo.: Westview
    • See Fernando R. Teson, "The Rawlsian Theory of International Law," Ethics and International Affairs 9 (1995); and Peter Jones, "International Human Rights: Philosophical or Political?" in Simon Caney, David George, and Peter Jones, eds., National Rights, International Obligations (Boulder, Colo.: Westview, 1996).
    • (1996) National Rights, International Obligations
    • Jones, P.1
  • 31
    • 85038190601 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The difference principle requires social and economic inequalities be to the greatest benefit of those least advantaged by them. See Rawls (fn. 4), 83.
  • 32
    • 85038182058 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Rawls (fn. 6) suggests in a footnote that international justice might require redistribution of benefits derived from unequal resource endowments (p. 228 n. 52). The point is not developed in the text and there is no clear foundation for such a requirement in the theory.
  • 33
    • 41349120878 scopus 로고
    • Response
    • David Miller and Michael Walzer, eds., Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • This idea is shared by other social liberals. Thus Michael Walzer: "I am inclined to think that, for now at least, ordinary moral principles regarding humane treatment and mutual aid do more work than any specific account of [international] distributive justice." "Response," in David Miller and Michael Walzer, eds., Pluralism, Justice, and Equality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995), 293. Compare Michael Donelan, Elements of International Political Theory (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990), 196-97.
    • (1995) Pluralism, Justice, and Equality , pp. 293
    • Walzer, M.1
  • 34
    • 0042400867 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • This idea is shared by other social liberals. Thus Michael Walzer: "I am inclined to think that, for now at least, ordinary moral principles regarding humane treatment and mutual aid do more work than any specific account of [international] distributive justice." "Response," in David Miller and Michael Walzer, eds., Pluralism, Justice, and Equality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995), 293. Compare Michael Donelan, Elements of International Political Theory (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990), 196-97.
    • (1990) Elements of International Political Theory , pp. 196-197
    • Donelan, M.1
  • 35
    • 85038186087 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The point is made several times in Rawls (fn. 6), e.g., 46-47, 48, 65-66, and particularly 75-76.
  • 36
    • 85038174528 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 75
    • Ibid., 75.
  • 37
    • 85038191624 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Ibid., 77 and 228 n. 52. Although this point is made in the context of a discussion aimed at showing why there is no international analog of the difference principle, it may not be meant to explain why this should be so. I discuss the relevance of the observation below.
  • 38
    • 0003556319 scopus 로고
    • Princeton: Princeton University Press
    • Arguments for a global difference principle are worked out in Beitz, Political Theory and International Relations (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1979), 143-53; and in Thomas Pogge, Realizing Rawls (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1989), chaps. 5-6.
    • (1979) Political Theory and International Relations , pp. 143-153
    • Beitz1
  • 39
    • 0004248343 scopus 로고
    • Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, chaps. 5-6
    • Arguments for a global difference principle are worked out in Beitz, Political Theory and International Relations (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1979), 143-53; and in Thomas Pogge, Realizing Rawls (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1989), chaps. 5-6.
    • (1989) Realizing Rawls
    • Pogge, T.1
  • 40
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고
    • New York: Columbia University Press
    • John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993), 15.
    • (1993) Political Liberalism , pp. 15
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 41
    • 85038171732 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Those "who do their part . . . are to benefit in an appropriate way"; Rawls (fn. 30), 16.
  • 42
    • 85038175100 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Ibid., 15. On the parallel requirement for well-ordered hierarchical societies, see Rawls (fn. 6), 69.
  • 43
    • 0344916796 scopus 로고
    • trans. Donald A. Cress Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett
    • Recall Rousseau's admonition: "The boundaries of what is possible in moral matters are less narrow than we think. It is our weaknesses, our vices and our prejudices that shrink them"; Rousseau, On the Social Contract, trans. Donald A. Cress (Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett, 1983), III:xii.
    • (1983) On the Social Contract , vol.3
    • Rousseau1
  • 45
    • 85038192228 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Rawls (fn. 6) grants that in other respects the parties might apply a different principle in the international case than they would in the domestic case. For example, in explaining why hierarchical societies would insist on equal treatment in the international original position, even though they have inegalitarian domestic institutions, he writes: "Though a society lacks basic equality, it is not unreasonable for that society to insist on equality in making claims against other societies" (p. 65).
  • 46
    • 85038176804 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 54, 64-65
    • Ibid., 54, 64-65.
  • 47
    • 84992799212 scopus 로고
    • An Egalitarian Law of Peoples
    • Summer
    • Thomas Pogge gives an account of the reasoning in Pogge, "An Egalitarian Law of Peoples," Philosophy and Public Affairs 23 (Summer 1994), 211-14.
    • (1994) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.23 , pp. 211-214
    • Pogge, T.1
  • 48
    • 84972258753 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 77. Analogously, J. S. Mill held that a people could expect to sustain free institutions only if they struggled to achieve these institutions for themselves; Mill, "A Few Words on Non-intervention," in Dissertations and Discussions: Political, Philosophical, and Historical (London: Longmans, Green, Reader, and Dyer, 1867), 3:175.
    • Philosophy and Public Affairs , pp. 77
  • 49
    • 0038836135 scopus 로고
    • A Few Words on Non-intervention
    • London: Longmans, Green, Reader, and Dyer
    • Ibid., 77. Analogously, J. S. Mill held that a people could expect to sustain free institutions only if they struggled to achieve these institutions for themselves; Mill, "A Few Words on Non-intervention," in Dissertations and Discussions: Political, Philosophical, and Historical (London: Longmans, Green, Reader, and Dyer, 1867), 3:175.
    • (1867) Dissertations and Discussions: Political, Philosophical, and Historical , vol.3 , pp. 175
    • Mill1
  • 51
    • 85038177170 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See the text preceding fn. 59
    • See the text preceding fn. 59.
  • 52
    • 84970745478 scopus 로고
    • Globalisation and Inequality
    • Winter
    • See Andrew Hurrell and Ngaire Woods, "Globalisation and Inequality," Millennium 24 (Winter 1995); and Stephan Haggard and Sylvia Maxfield, "The Political Economy of Financial Internationalization in the Developing World," in Robert O. Keohane and Helen V. Milner, eds., Internationalization and Domestic Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996).
    • (1995) Millennium , vol.24
    • Hurrell, A.1    Woods, N.2
  • 53
    • 0000960147 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Political Economy of Financial Internationalization in the Developing World
    • Robert O. Keohane and Helen V. Milner, eds., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See Andrew Hurrell and Ngaire Woods, "Globalisation and Inequality," Millennium 24 (Winter 1995); and Stephan Haggard and Sylvia Maxfield, "The Political Economy of Financial Internationalization in the Developing World," in Robert O. Keohane and Helen V. Milner, eds., Internationalization and Domestic Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996).
    • (1996) Internationalization and Domestic Politics
    • Haggard, S.1    Maxfield, S.2
  • 54
    • 85038183265 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls (fn. 6), 56
    • Rawls (fn. 6), 56.
  • 55
    • 0345312572 scopus 로고
    • Dreams of a Just World Order
    • November 2
    • There are illuminating discussions of Rawls's international theory in Stanley Hoffmann, "Dreams of a Just World Order," a review of On Human Rights: The Oxford Amnesty Lectures 1993, New York Review of Books 42 (November 2, 1995); and Darrel Moellendorf, "Constructing the Law of Peoples," Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 77 (June 1996). See also the works by Jones and Teson (fn. 22); and Pogge (fn. 37).
    • (1995) On Human Rights: The Oxford Amnesty Lectures 1993, New York Review of Books , vol.42
    • Hoffmann, S.1
  • 56
    • 0002188877 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Constructing the Law of Peoples
    • June
    • There are illuminating discussions of Rawls's international theory in Stanley Hoffmann, "Dreams of a Just World Order," a review of On Human Rights: The Oxford Amnesty Lectures 1993, New York Review of Books 42 (November 2, 1995); and Darrel Moellendorf, "Constructing the Law of Peoples," Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 77 (June 1996). See also the works by Jones and Teson (fn. 22); and Pogge (fn. 37).
    • (1996) Pacific Philosophical Quarterly , vol.77
    • Moellendorf, D.1
  • 57
    • 85038181835 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • fn. 22
    • There are illuminating discussions of Rawls's international theory in Stanley Hoffmann, "Dreams of a Just World Order," a review of On Human Rights: The Oxford Amnesty Lectures 1993, New York Review of Books 42 (November 2, 1995); and Darrel Moellendorf, "Constructing the Law of Peoples," Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 77 (June 1996). See also the works by Jones and Teson (fn. 22); and Pogge (fn. 37).
    • Pacific Philosophical Quarterly
    • Jones1    Teson2
  • 58
    • 84929029948 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • fn. 37
    • There are illuminating discussions of Rawls's international theory in Stanley Hoffmann, "Dreams of a Just World Order," a review of On Human Rights: The Oxford Amnesty Lectures 1993, New York Review of Books 42 (November 2, 1995); and Darrel Moellendorf, "Constructing the Law of Peoples," Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 77 (June 1996). See also the works by Jones and Teson (fn. 22); and Pogge (fn. 37).
    • Pacific Philosophical Quarterly
    • Pogge1
  • 60
    • 85038176740 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nozick (fn. 44) is the best-known contemporary defender of this view
    • Nozick (fn. 44) is the best-known contemporary defender of this view.
  • 61
    • 0004128375 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, chaps. 3-4
    • I must forgo an explanation why. There is a good discussion in G. A. Cohen, Self-ownership, Freedom, and Equality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), chaps. 3-4.
    • (1995) Self-ownership, Freedom, and Equality
    • Cohen, G.A.1
  • 62
    • 0003988298 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Blackwell
    • Steiner, An Essay on Rights (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994); and idem, "Territorial Justice," in Caney, George, and Jones (fn. 22).
    • (1994) An Essay on Rights
    • Steiner1
  • 63
    • 0041071487 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Caney, George, and Jones (fn. 22)
    • Steiner, An Essay on Rights (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994); and idem, "Territorial Justice," in Caney, George, and Jones (fn. 22).
    • Territorial Justice
    • Steiner1
  • 64
    • 84933485779 scopus 로고
    • Justice and Natural Resources
    • See, e.g., Stephen Luper-Foy, "Justice and Natural Resources," Environmental Values 1, no. 1 (1992).
    • (1992) Environmental Values , vol.1 , Issue.1
    • Luper-Foy, S.1
  • 65
    • 0003691257 scopus 로고
    • ed. Peter Laslett, 2d ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, sec. 27
    • Why this should be so is controversial. The controversy is best approached in the literature on Locke's theory of property acquisition, particularly in commentary on his proviso that any appropriation of unowned things should leave "enough, and as good . . . in common for others"; see Locke, Two Treatises of Government, ed. Peter Laslett, 2d ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1967), II, sec. 27. For commentary, see A. John Simmons, The Lockean Theory of Rights (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1992), 288-98 and the references cited there.
    • (1967) Two Treatises of Government , vol.2
    • Locke1
  • 66
    • 0003779590 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Princeton: Princeton University Press, and the references cited there
    • Why this should be so is controversial. The controversy is best approached in the literature on Locke's theory of property acquisition, particularly in commentary on his proviso that any appropriation of unowned things should leave "enough, and as good . . . in common for others"; see Locke, Two Treatises of Government, ed. Peter Laslett, 2d ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1967), II, sec. 27. For commentary, see A. John Simmons, The Lockean Theory of Rights (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1992), 288-98 and the references cited there.
    • (1992) The Lockean Theory of Rights , pp. 288-298
    • John Simmons, A.1
  • 69
    • 0003779590 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 275. Human germ-line genetic information is not to be confused with ability as we commonly understand it, because ability depends not only on genetic endowment but also on what might broadly be called upbringing.
    • The Lockean Theory of Rights , pp. 275
  • 71
    • 85038177999 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Locke (fn. 49) may have held such a view (II, secs. 117, 120-21)
    • Locke (fn. 49) may have held such a view (II, secs. 117, 120-21).
  • 72
    • 85038176254 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Steiner (fn. 47, 1994), 269-70
    • Steiner (fn. 47, 1994), 269-70.
  • 73
    • 4243204967 scopus 로고
    • Commons and Commonwealths: A New Framework for the Justification of Territorial Claims
    • Robert V. Andelson, ed., London: Shepheard-Walwyn
    • Ibid., 270 n. 9, emphasis in original. On the valuation of resources, see T. Nicolaus Tideman, "Commons and Commonwealths: A New Framework for the Justification of Territorial Claims," in Robert V. Andelson, ed., Commons without Tragedy (London: Shepheard-Walwyn, 1991).
    • (1991) Commons Without Tragedy
    • Nicolaus Tideman, T.1
  • 74
    • 85038179870 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Of course, nothing in either version of laissez-faire liberalism precludes charitable transfers to help avoid or relieve human-rights deprivations.
  • 75
    • 19044370131 scopus 로고
    • Humanity and Justice in Global Perspective
    • Barry, Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • I made such an argument in Beitz (fn. 29), 136-43. For a similar view, see Brian Barry, "Humanity and Justice in Global Perspective," in Barry, Democracy, Power and Justice: Essays in Political Theory (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989), 448-52.
    • (1989) Democracy, Power and Justice: Essays in Political Theory , pp. 448-452
    • Barry, B.1
  • 76
    • 0026005036 scopus 로고
    • Toward a Model of Development
    • Lawrence B. Krause and Kim Kihwan, eds., Berkeley: University of California Press, emphasis in original
    • Gustav Ranis, "Toward a Model of Development," in Lawrence B. Krause and Kim Kihwan, eds., Liberalization in the Process of Economic Development (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1991), 100, emphasis in original; and Jeffrey D. Sachs and Andrew M. Warner, Natural Resource Abundance and Economic Growth, NBER Working Paper no. 5398 (Cambridge, Mass.: National Bureau of Economic Research, 1995).
    • (1991) Liberalization in the Process of Economic Development , pp. 100
    • Ranis, G.1
  • 77
    • 0026005036 scopus 로고
    • NBER Working Paper no. 5398 Cambridge, Mass.: National Bureau of Economic Research
    • Gustav Ranis, "Toward a Model of Development," in Lawrence B. Krause and Kim Kihwan, eds., Liberalization in the Process of Economic Development (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1991), 100, emphasis in original; and Jeffrey D. Sachs and Andrew M. Warner, Natural Resource Abundance and Economic Growth, NBER Working Paper no. 5398 (Cambridge, Mass.: National Bureau of Economic Research, 1995).
    • (1995) Natural Resource Abundance and Economic Growth
    • Sachs, J.D.1    Warner, A.M.2
  • 78
    • 20744445451 scopus 로고
    • Lives of Eminent Philosophers, trans. R. D. Hicks, Loeb Classical Library London: William Heinemann
    • Diogenes Laertius, Diogenes, in Lives of Eminent Philosophers, trans. R. D. Hicks, Loeb Classical Library (London: William Heinemann, 1925), vol. 2, vol. 6:63. rely here and in the next paragraph on my article, "Cosmopolitan Liberalism and the States System," in Chris Brown, ed., Political Restructuring in Europe (London and New York: Routledge, 1994). On the idea of the cosmopolitan and national sentiment, see Martha Nussbaum's leading essay in Martha Nussbaum and respondents, For Love of Country: Debating the Limits of Patriotism, ed. Joshua Cohen (Boston: Beacon Press, 1996).
    • (1925) Diogenes , vol.2-6 , pp. 63
    • Laertius, D.1
  • 79
    • 0002943433 scopus 로고
    • Cosmopolitan Liberalism and the States System
    • London and New York: Routledge
    • Diogenes Laertius, Diogenes, in Lives of Eminent Philosophers, trans. R. D. Hicks, Loeb Classical Library (London: William Heinemann, 1925), vol. 2, vol. 6:63. rely here and in the next paragraph on my article, "Cosmopolitan Liberalism and the States System," in Chris Brown, ed., Political Restructuring in Europe (London and New York: Routledge, 1994). On the idea of the cosmopolitan and national sentiment, see Martha Nussbaum's leading essay in Martha Nussbaum and respondents, For Love of Country: Debating the Limits of Patriotism, ed. Joshua Cohen (Boston: Beacon Press, 1996).
    • (1994) Political Restructuring in Europe
    • Brown, C.1
  • 80
    • 0003942941 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ed. Joshua Cohen Boston: Beacon Press
    • Diogenes Laertius, Diogenes, in Lives of Eminent Philosophers, trans. R. D. Hicks, Loeb Classical Library (London: William Heinemann, 1925), vol. 2, vol. 6:63. rely here and in the next paragraph on my article, "Cosmopolitan Liberalism and the States System," in Chris Brown, ed., Political Restructuring in Europe (London and New York: Routledge, 1994). On the idea of the cosmopolitan and national sentiment, see Martha Nussbaum's leading essay in Martha Nussbaum and respondents, For Love of Country: Debating the Limits of Patriotism, ed. Joshua Cohen (Boston: Beacon Press, 1996).
    • (1996) For Love of Country: Debating the Limits of Patriotism
    • Nussbaum, M.1
  • 81
    • 84925677087 scopus 로고
    • Cosmopolitanism and Sovereignty
    • October
    • Thomas W. Pogge, "Cosmopolitanism and Sovereignty," Ethics 103 (October 1992), 49.
    • (1992) Ethics , vol.103 , pp. 49
    • Pogge, T.W.1
  • 82
    • 0003940096 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Onora O'Neill, Towards Justice and Virtue (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 172.
    • (1996) Towards Justice and Virtue , pp. 172
    • O'Neill, O.1
  • 83
    • 0344018402 scopus 로고
    • The application of such a view to questions of global distributive justice is perhaps clearest in the encyclical letter of Pope Paul VI, Populorum Progressio (Of the development of peoples), Acta Apostolicae Sedis 59:257-99 (1967), reprinted in Claudia Carlen, ed., The Papal Encyclicals (Wilmington, N.C.: McGrath Publishing, 1981), 5:183-201.
    • (1967) Populorum Progressio (Of the Development of Peoples), Acta Apostolicae Sedis , vol.59 , pp. 257-299
    • Paul P. VI1
  • 84
    • 0344018400 scopus 로고
    • Wilmington, N.C.: McGrath Publishing
    • The application of such a view to questions of global distributive justice is perhaps clearest in the encyclical letter of Pope Paul VI, Populorum Progressio (Of the development of peoples), Acta Apostolicae Sedis 59:257-99 (1967), reprinted in Claudia Carlen, ed., The Papal Encyclicals (Wilmington, N.C.: McGrath Publishing, 1981), 5:183-201.
    • (1981) The Papal Encyclicals , vol.5 , pp. 183-201
    • Carlen, C.1
  • 85
    • 84931428234 scopus 로고
    • What Is so Special about Our Fellow Countrymen?
    • July
    • Robert E. Goodin, "What Is So Special about Our Fellow Countrymen?" Ethics 98 (July 1988), 685. For the application to international distributive justice, see Goodin, Protecting the Vulnerable (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1985), 154-69.
    • (1988) Ethics , vol.98 , pp. 685
    • Goodin, R.E.1
  • 86
    • 0003634833 scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • Robert E. Goodin, "What Is So Special about Our Fellow Countrymen?" Ethics 98 (July 1988), 685. For the application to international distributive justice, see Goodin, Protecting the Vulnerable (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1985), 154-69.
    • (1985) Protecting the Vulnerable , pp. 154-169
    • Goodin1
  • 88
    • 0003408858 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Princeton: Princeton University Press
    • Henry Shue, Basic Rights, 2d ed. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996); Pogge (fn. 61); idem, "How Should Human Rights Be Conceived?" Jahrbuch für Recht und Ethik 3 (1995);
    • (1996) Basic Rights, 2d Ed.
    • Shue, H.1
  • 89
    • 0000711138 scopus 로고
    • How Should Human Rights Be Conceived?
    • Henry Shue, Basic Rights, 2d ed. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996); Pogge (fn. 61); idem, "How Should Human Rights Be Conceived?" Jahrbuch für Recht und Ethik 3 (1995); and idem, "Standards of Living within a Global Discourse about Justice: Moral Philosophy and Social Systems," Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 51 (1997). Because discontinuous views resemble the social liberalism of Rawls, it might be asked whether they are really forms of cosmopolitanism at all. The answer is that they are, because they explain the discontinuity in ways consistent with cosmopolitan impartiality.
    • (1995) Jahrbuch für Recht und Ethik , vol.3
    • Pogge1
  • 90
    • 85038186920 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Standards of Living within a Global Discourse about Justice: Moral Philosophy and Social Systems
    • Henry Shue, Basic Rights, 2d ed. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996); Pogge (fn. 61); idem, "How Should Human Rights Be Conceived?" Jahrbuch für Recht und Ethik 3 (1995); and idem, "Standards of Living within a Global Discourse about Justice: Moral Philosophy and Social Systems," Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 51 (1997). Because discontinuous views resemble the social liberalism of Rawls, it might be asked whether they are really forms of cosmopolitanism at all. The answer is that they are, because they explain the discontinuity in ways consistent with cosmopolitan impartiality.
    • (1997) Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung , vol.51
    • Pogge1
  • 91
    • 0003882732 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • For example, Jeremy Waldron argues that the right to "periodic holidays with pay" (Universal Declaration, art. 24) states a universal human interest that should be recognized in a plausible doctrine of human rights; Waldron, Liberal Rights: Collected Papers, 1981-1991 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 12-13. Both Shue and Pogge argue that there is a human right to political participation: Shue (fn. 66), chap. 3; Pogge (fn. 66, 1997).
    • (1993) Liberal Rights: Collected Papers, 1981-1991 , pp. 12-13
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 92
    • 85038176708 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (fn. 66), chap. 3
    • For example, Jeremy Waldron argues that the right to "periodic holidays with pay" (Universal Declaration, art. 24) states a universal human interest that should be recognized in a plausible doctrine of human rights; Waldron, Liberal Rights: Collected Papers, 1981-1991 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 12-13. Both Shue and Pogge argue that there is a human right to political participation: Shue (fn. 66), chap. 3; Pogge (fn. 66, 1997).
    • Liberal Rights: Collected Papers, 1981-1991
    • Shue1
  • 93
    • 85038190030 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • fn. 66
    • For example, Jeremy Waldron argues that the right to "periodic holidays with pay" (Universal Declaration, art. 24) states a universal human interest that should be recognized in a plausible doctrine of human rights; Waldron, Liberal Rights: Collected Papers, 1981-1991 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 12-13. Both Shue and Pogge argue that there is a human right to political participation: Shue (fn. 66), chap. 3; Pogge (fn. 66, 1997).
    • (1997) Liberal Rights: Collected Papers, 1981-1991
    • Pogge1
  • 96
    • 85038172289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Shue (fn. 66) argues for a complex allocation of duties, the most salient falling on institutions at both domestic and international levels. See the 1996 afterword, esp. 224 nn. 21 and 25 and p. 225 n. 27.
  • 97
    • 85038191016 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pogge (fn. 61), 53
    • Pogge (fn. 61), 53.
  • 98
    • 85038189364 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Shue (fn. 66), chap. 2 and the 1996 afterword
    • Shue (fn. 66), chap. 2 and the 1996 afterword.
  • 99
    • 84900247308 scopus 로고
    • Mediating Duties
    • July
    • For a further discussion, see Shue, "Mediating Duties," Ethics 98 (July 1988).
    • (1988) Ethics , vol.98
    • Shue1
  • 100
    • 0002352053 scopus 로고
    • Families, Nations and Strangers
    • Department of Philosophy, University of Kansas
    • A subtle and complex exploration of this idea can be found in a series of papers by Samuel Scheffler: "Families, Nations and Strangers," The Lindley Lecture (Department of Philosophy, University of Kansas, 1995); "Individual Responsibility in a Global Age," Social Philosophy and Policy 12 (1995); "Liberalism, Nationalism, and Egalitarianism," in Robert McKim and Jeff McMahan, eds., The Morality of Nationalism (New York: Oxford University Press, 1997); and "Relationships and Responsibilities," Philosophy and Public Affairs 26 (Summer 1997). There is an extensive further literature on the question of special responsibilities; for a recent discussion, see Andrew Mason, "Special Obligations to Compatriots," Ethics 107 (1997), including the references cited.
    • (1995) The Lindley Lecture
    • Scheffler, S.1
  • 101
    • 84971942362 scopus 로고
    • Individual Responsibility in a Global Age
    • A subtle and complex exploration of this idea can be found in a series of papers by Samuel Scheffler: "Families, Nations and Strangers," The Lindley Lecture (Department of Philosophy, University of Kansas, 1995); "Individual Responsibility in a Global Age," Social Philosophy and Policy 12 (1995); "Liberalism, Nationalism, and Egalitarianism," in Robert McKim and Jeff McMahan, eds., The Morality of Nationalism (New York: Oxford University Press, 1997); and "Relationships and Responsibilities," Philosophy and Public Affairs 26 (Summer 1997). There is an extensive further literature on the question of special responsibilities; for a recent discussion, see Andrew Mason, "Special Obligations to Compatriots," Ethics 107 (1997), including the references cited.
    • (1995) Social Philosophy and Policy , vol.12
  • 102
    • 0010101821 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Liberalism, Nationalism, and Egalitarianism
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • A subtle and complex exploration of this idea can be found in a series of papers by Samuel Scheffler: "Families, Nations and Strangers," The Lindley Lecture (Department of Philosophy, University of Kansas, 1995); "Individual Responsibility in a Global Age," Social Philosophy and Policy 12 (1995); "Liberalism, Nationalism, and Egalitarianism," in Robert McKim and Jeff McMahan, eds., The Morality of Nationalism (New York: Oxford University Press, 1997); and "Relationships and Responsibilities," Philosophy and Public Affairs 26 (Summer 1997). There is an extensive further literature on the question of special responsibilities; for a recent discussion, see Andrew Mason, "Special Obligations to Compatriots," Ethics 107 (1997), including the references cited.
    • (1997) The Morality of Nationalism
    • McKim, R.1    McMahan, J.2
  • 103
    • 0344881495 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Relationships and Responsibilities
    • Summer
    • A subtle and complex exploration of this idea can be found in a series of papers by Samuel Scheffler: "Families, Nations and Strangers," The Lindley Lecture (Department of Philosophy, University of Kansas, 1995); "Individual Responsibility in a Global Age," Social Philosophy and Policy 12 (1995); "Liberalism, Nationalism, and Egalitarianism," in Robert McKim and Jeff McMahan, eds., The Morality of Nationalism (New York: Oxford University Press, 1997); and "Relationships and Responsibilities," Philosophy and Public Affairs 26 (Summer 1997). There is an extensive further literature on the question of special responsibilities; for a recent discussion, see Andrew Mason, "Special Obligations to Compatriots," Ethics 107 (1997), including the references cited.
    • (1997) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.26
  • 104
    • 0001682044 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Special Obligations to Compatriots
    • including the references cited
    • A subtle and complex exploration of this idea can be found in a series of papers by Samuel Scheffler: "Families, Nations and Strangers," The Lindley Lecture (Department of Philosophy, University of Kansas, 1995); "Individual Responsibility in a Global Age," Social Philosophy and Policy 12 (1995); "Liberalism, Nationalism, and Egalitarianism," in Robert McKim and Jeff McMahan, eds., The Morality of Nationalism (New York: Oxford University Press, 1997); and "Relationships and Responsibilities," Philosophy and Public Affairs 26 (Summer 1997). There is an extensive further literature on the question of special responsibilities; for a recent discussion, see Andrew Mason, "Special Obligations to Compatriots," Ethics 107 (1997), including the references cited.
    • (1997) Ethics , vol.107
    • Mason, A.1
  • 108
    • 0345312541 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Tübinger Arbeitspapiere zur Internationalen Politik und Friedensforschung, no. 25 Tübingen: Institut für Politikwissenschaft, Universität Tübingen
    • Few students of international institutions and regimes have systematically explored their distributional effects. The importance of such empirical work cannot be overstated. For a start, see Andreas Hasenclever, Peter Mayer, and Volker Rittberger, Justice, Equality, and the Robustness of International Regimes: A Research Design, Tübinger Arbeitspapiere zur Internationalen Politik und Friedensforschung, no. 25 (Tübingen: Institut für Politikwissenschaft, Universität Tübingen, 1996).
    • (1996) Justice, Equality, and the Robustness of International Regimes: A Research Design
    • Hasenclever, A.1    Mayer, P.2    Rittberger, V.3
  • 110
    • 0041406220 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • TRIPS: Natural Rights and a 'Polite Form of Economic Imperialism
    • May
    • J. H. Reichman, Implications of the Draft TRIPS Agreement for Developing Countries as Competitors in \ an Integrated World Market, UNCTAD Discussion Papers no. 73 (UNCTAD/OSG/DP/73, November 1993); A. Samuel Oddi, "TRIPS: Natural Rights and a 'Polite Form of Economic Imperialism,'" Vanderbilt Journal of Transnational Law 29 (May 1996).
    • (1996) Vanderbilt Journal of Transnational Law , vol.29
    • Samuel Oddi, A.1
  • 112
  • 113
    • 0031534418 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Capital Theory Approach to Sustainability: A Critical Appraisal
    • March
    • The task is complicated by dispute about the extent to which technology can be expected to substitute for exhaustible natural resources. For an accessible discussion, see David I. Stern, "The Capital Theory Approach to Sustainability: A Critical Appraisal," Journal of Economic Issues 31 (March 1997). I am grateful to David Vail for instructive discussion on this point.
    • (1997) Journal of Economic Issues , vol.31
    • Stern, D.I.1
  • 114
    • 84937298064 scopus 로고
    • Justice, International Relations, and Human Rights
    • October
    • There is an eloquent discussion in Geoffrey Best, "Justice, International Relations, and Human Rights," International Affairs 71 (October 1995), esp. 794-98.
    • (1995) International Affairs , vol.71 , pp. 794-798
    • Best, G.1
  • 115
    • 85038183335 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Vincent (fn. 6) argued more than a decade ago for what he called "the priority of subsistence rights" in contemporary international policy, noting, inter alia, the possibility of solutions that do not engage major ideologies in conflict (p. 147).


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.