메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 107, Issue 3, 1997, Pages 427-446

Special obligations to compatriots

(1)  Mason, Andrew a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0001682044     PISSN: 00141704     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1086/233743     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (83)

References (66)
  • 1
    • 0003294352 scopus 로고
    • Legal obligation and the duty of fair play
    • ed. S. Hook New York: New York University Press
    • Many political theorists also suppose that we have an obligation to obey the law which can be understood as a special obligation to compatriots than as a special obligation to the state. This idea has a long pedigree. It is to be found in social contract theories such as Thomas Hobbes's as well as in theories which attempt to ground an obligation to obey the law on a principle of "fair play": that since one has enjoyed the benefits of others' obeying the law, one should accept the burdens of one's own compliance with it. The fair play argument seems first to have been invoked by Socrates in the Crito, when he explained why he should receive the punishment handed to him rather than escape from Athens. John Rawls explicitly proposed the argument in his "Legal Obligation and the Duty of Fair Play," in Law and Philosophy, ed. S. Hook (New York: New York University Press, 1964). I shall not discuss this idea here because of the particular problems it raises, although some of what I say is relevant to it.
    • (1964) Law and Philosophy
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 2
    • 0040269930 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Although charity is often taken to refer to actions that are beyond the call of duty rather than those which are obligatory.
  • 3
    • 21144468983 scopus 로고
    • A misconceived discourse on political obligation
    • Bhikhu Parekh, "A Misconceived Discourse on Political Obligation," Political Studies 41 (1993): 236-51, p. 243.
    • (1993) Political Studies , vol.41 , pp. 236-251
    • Parekh, B.1
  • 4
    • 0001996443 scopus 로고
    • The idea of negative liberty: Philosophical and historical perspectives
    • ed. Richard Rorty, J. B. Schneewind, and Quentin Skinner Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See, e.g., Quentin Skinner, "The Idea of Negative Liberty: Philosophical and Historical Perspectives," in Philosophy in History, ed. Richard Rorty, J. B. Schneewind, and Quentin Skinner (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984); Richard Bellamy, "Citizenship and Rights," in Theories and Concepts of Politics: An Introduction, ed. Richard Bellamy (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1993), p. 63. Civic republicans often prefer to talk about the virtues of citizens rather than the obligations or duties of citizenship, but it is clear that they regard the fulfillment of such obligations as partially constitutive of what it is to be a good citizen. Compare Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues: Citizenship, Virtue, and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), pp. 272-74.
    • (1984) Philosophy in History
    • Skinner, Q.1
  • 5
    • 0009131632 scopus 로고
    • Citizenship and rights
    • ed. Richard Bellamy Manchester: Manchester University Press
    • See, e.g., Quentin Skinner, "The Idea of Negative Liberty: Philosophical and Historical Perspectives," in Philosophy in History, ed. Richard Rorty, J. B. Schneewind, and Quentin Skinner (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984); Richard Bellamy, "Citizenship and Rights," in Theories and Concepts of Politics: An Introduction, ed. Richard Bellamy (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1993), p. 63. Civic republicans often prefer to talk about the virtues of citizens rather than the obligations or duties of citizenship, but it is clear that they regard the fulfillment of such obligations as partially constitutive of what it is to be a good citizen. Compare Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues: Citizenship, Virtue, and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), pp. 272-74.
    • (1993) Theories and Concepts of Politics: An Introduction , pp. 63
    • Bellamy, R.1
  • 6
    • 0003796286 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • See, e.g., Quentin Skinner, "The Idea of Negative Liberty: Philosophical and Historical Perspectives," in Philosophy in History, ed. Richard Rorty, J. B. Schneewind, and Quentin Skinner (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984); Richard Bellamy, "Citizenship and Rights," in Theories and Concepts of Politics: An Introduction, ed. Richard Bellamy (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1993), p. 63. Civic republicans often prefer to talk about the virtues of citizens rather than the obligations or duties of citizenship, but it is clear that they regard the fulfillment of such obligations as partially constitutive of what it is to be a good citizen. Compare Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues: Citizenship, Virtue, and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), pp. 272-74.
    • (1990) Liberal Virtues: Citizenship, Virtue, and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism , pp. 272-274
    • Macedo, S.1
  • 7
    • 0004041895 scopus 로고
    • New York: Simon & Schuster
    • See, e.g., Amitai Etzioni, The Spirit of Community: The Reinvention of American Society (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1993). David Selbourne (The Principle of Duty [London: Sinclair-Stevenson, 1994], pp. 156, 230-31) argues that citizens have an obligation to sustain the civic bond, which includes an obligation to inform themselves about the nature of the civic order to which they belong, and an obligation to participate in local civic affairs.
    • (1993) The Spirit of Community: The Reinvention of American Society
    • Etzioni, A.1
  • 8
    • 0004216321 scopus 로고
    • London: Sinclair-Stevenson
    • See, e.g., Amitai Etzioni, The Spirit of Community: The Reinvention of American Society (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1993). David Selbourne (The Principle of Duty [London: Sinclair-Stevenson, 1994], pp. 156, 230-31) argues that citizens have an obligation to sustain the civic bond, which includes an obligation to inform themselves about the nature of the civic order to which they belong, and an obligation to participate in local civic affairs.
    • (1994) The Principle of Duty , pp. 156
    • Selbourne, D.1
  • 9
    • 0039085916 scopus 로고
    • Are there any natural rights?
    • ed. Anthony Quinton Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • See H. L. A. Hart, "Are There Any Natural Rights?" in Political Philosophy, ed. Anthony Quinton (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1967), pp. 55-56, reprinted from Philosophical Review 64 (1955): 175-91.
    • (1967) Political Philosophy , pp. 55-56
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 10
    • 0000982081 scopus 로고
    • See H. L. A. Hart, "Are There Any Natural Rights?" in Political Philosophy, ed. Anthony Quinton (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1967), pp. 55-56, reprinted from Philosophical Review 64 (1955): 175-91.
    • (1955) Philosophical Review , vol.64 , pp. 175-191
  • 11
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • See John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971), pp. 111-12.
    • (1971) A Theory of Justice , pp. 111-112
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 12
  • 13
    • 0001927381 scopus 로고
    • Ethical universalism and particularism
    • See Alan Gewirth, "Ethical Universalism and Particularism," Journal of Philosophy 85 (1988): 283-302, pp. 284-85.
    • (1988) Journal of Philosophy , vol.85 , pp. 283-302
    • Gewirth, A.1
  • 14
    • 0003924191 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Martin Robertson
    • Michael Walzer argues that political justice requires that long-term "guest" workers be given the opportunity to become citizens: "The processes of self-determination through which a democratic state shapes its internal life, must be open, and equally open, to all those men and women who live within its territory, work in the local economy, and are subject to local law" (Spheres of Justice: A Defence of Pluralism and Equality [Oxford: Martin Robertson, 1983], p. 60). Two useful collections of papers address the morality of immigration controls: Free Movement: Ethical Issues in the Transnational Migration of People and Money, ed. Brian Barry and Robert E. Goodin (Brighton: Wheatsheaf, 1992); and Justice in Immigration, ed. Warren F. Schwartz (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995).
    • (1983) Spheres of Justice: A Defence of Pluralism and Equality , pp. 60
    • Walzer, M.1
  • 15
    • 0003898308 scopus 로고
    • Brighton: Wheatsheaf
    • Michael Walzer argues that political justice requires that long-term "guest" workers be given the opportunity to become citizens: "The processes of self-determination through which a democratic state shapes its internal life, must be open, and equally open, to all those men and women who live within its territory, work in the local economy, and are subject to local law" (Spheres of Justice: A Defence of Pluralism and Equality [Oxford: Martin Robertson, 1983], p. 60). Two useful collections of papers address the morality of immigration controls: Free Movement: Ethical Issues in the Transnational Migration of People and Money, ed. Brian Barry and Robert E. Goodin (Brighton: Wheatsheaf, 1992); and Justice in Immigration, ed. Warren F. Schwartz (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995).
    • (1992) Free Movement: Ethical Issues in the Transnational Migration of People and Money
    • Barry, B.1    Goodin, R.E.2
  • 16
    • 0012626507 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Michael Walzer argues that political justice requires that long-term "guest" workers be given the opportunity to become citizens: "The processes of self-determination through which a democratic state shapes its internal life, must be open, and equally open, to all those men and women who live within its territory, work in the local economy, and are subject to local law" (Spheres of Justice: A Defence of Pluralism and Equality [Oxford: Martin Robertson, 1983], p. 60). Two useful collections of papers address the morality of immigration controls: Free Movement: Ethical Issues in the Transnational Migration of People and Money, ed. Brian Barry and Robert E. Goodin (Brighton: Wheatsheaf, 1992); and Justice in Immigration, ed. Warren F. Schwartz (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995).
    • (1995) Justice in Immigration
    • Schwartz, W.F.1
  • 18
    • 0039085851 scopus 로고
    • University of chicago press
    • Chicago: esp. chaps. 2-3
    • Alan Gewirth, Reason and Morality (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1978), esp. chaps. 2-3.
    • (1978) Reason and Morality
    • Gewirth, A.1
  • 22
    • 0039085920 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the first part of his article Gewirth says that his argument "will uphold, for the most part, the . . . thesis that ethical universalism, in the form of a principle of human rights, can show that certain kinds of ethical particularism are morally required or mandatory" (ibid., p. 289), but in the body of the article he doesn't make any explicit case for saying that the forms of ethical particularism he discusses are morally required.
    • Ethical Universalism , pp. 289
  • 23
    • 0039678080 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Gewirth could argue that states usually provide various protections through diplomacy to citizens living abroad. But these protections by their nature are much more limited than those mere residents receive through the impartial enforcement of the criminal law.
  • 24
    • 0039678171 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Of course, Gewirth thinks it mistaken to put any faith in ordinary moral intuitions, so he could simply deny the existence of a demanding obligation to participate in public life. My purpose, however, is to see what moral theory is required in order to account for the two special obligations I described earlier; I do not assume that Gewirth's account is defective because it cannot do so.
  • 25
    • 84973949925 scopus 로고
    • Rights, boundaries, and the bond of community: A qualified defense of moral parochialism
    • Richard Dagger, "Rights, Boundaries, and the Bond of Community: A Qualified Defense of Moral Parochialism," American Political Science Review 79 (1985): 436-47.
    • (1985) American Political Science Review , vol.79 , pp. 436-447
    • Dagger, R.1
  • 26
    • 84931428234 scopus 로고
    • What is so special about our fellow countrymen?
    • Robert E. Goodin, "What Is So Special about Our Fellow Countrymen?" Ethics 98 (1988): 663-86, pp. 676-78.
    • (1988) Ethics , vol.98 , pp. 663-686
    • Goodin, R.E.1
  • 27
    • 0039085854 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 678.
    • Ethics , pp. 678
  • 28
    • 84934454017 scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • Goodin's account should also be of interest to nonconsequentialists of various stripes, for (as he argues) it is compatible with standard forms of nonconsequentialism (Robert E. Goodin, Protecting the Vulnerable: A Reanalysis of Our Social Responsibilities [Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1985], pp. 115 ff.).
    • (1985) Protecting the Vulnerable: A Reanalysis of Our Social Responsibilities
    • Goodin, R.E.1
  • 29
    • 0040864251 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • By 'long-term resident', I just mean to exclude tourists.
  • 30
    • 0004002174 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • See David Miller, On Nationality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995), p. 63.
    • (1995) On Nationality , pp. 63
    • Miller, D.1
  • 32
    • 84936068266 scopus 로고
    • London: Fontana
    • Ronald Dworkin, Law's Empire (London: Fontana, 1986), p. 193.
    • (1986) Law's Empire , pp. 193
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 33
    • 84860836792 scopus 로고
    • Special ties and natural duties
    • Jeremy Waldron, "Special Ties and Natural Duties," Philosophy and Public Affairs 22 (1993): 3-30, p. 13.
    • (1993) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.22 , pp. 3-30
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 35
    • 0003929983 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press
    • Yael Tamir, Liberal Nationalism (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1993), p. 99; see also George P. Fletcher, Loyalty: An Essay on the Morality of Personal Relationships (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993), p. 16;
    • (1993) Liberal Nationalism , pp. 99
    • Tamir, Y.1
  • 37
    • 79960371621 scopus 로고
    • The ethical significance of nationality
    • esp. p. 650
    • David Miller, "The Ethical Significance of Nationality," Ethics 98 (1988): 647-62, esp. p. 650, although for a more refined view see On Nationality, pp. 68-70.
    • (1988) Ethics , vol.98 , pp. 647-662
    • Miller, D.1
  • 38
    • 0004002174 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • David Miller, "The Ethical Significance of Nationality," Ethics 98 (1988): 647-62, esp. p. 650, although for a more refined view see On Nationality, pp. 68-70.
    • On Nationality , pp. 68-70
  • 39
    • 0039678084 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Tamir, p. 102. This also seems to be Fletcher's view, p. 35 and chap. 8, passim
    • See Tamir, p. 102. This also seems to be Fletcher's view, p. 35 and chap. 8, passim.
  • 40
    • 0002488049 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Individuals, nations and obligations
    • ed. Simon Caney, David George, and Peter Jones Boulder, Colo.: Westview
    • See Simon Caney, "Individuals, Nations and Obligations," in National Rights and International Obligations, ed. Simon Caney, David George, and Peter Jones (Boulder, Colo.: Westview, 1996), p. 127. Admittedly, however, intuitions are not an especially clear guide in cases like this, for it is hard for them to distinguish between a conflict of obligations where one of the obligations easily overrides and a case where only one obligation is active.
    • (1996) National Rights and International Obligations , pp. 127
    • Caney, S.1
  • 41
    • 0040864172 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Horton, pp. 156-57
    • See Horton, pp. 156-57.
  • 42
    • 0001556235 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Associative political obligations
    • See A. John Simmons, "Associative Political Obligations," Ethics 106 (1996): 247-73, pp. 256-57.
    • (1996) Ethics , vol.106 , pp. 247-273
    • Simmons, A.J.1
  • 43
    • 0040864249 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Tamir, p. 102
    • Tamir, p. 102.
  • 44
    • 0040864246 scopus 로고
    • University of Kansas
    • I do not mean to suggest that Raz's account of how friendship justifies special obligations is the best model for all special obligations. I agree with Samuel Scheffler that it is difficult for any single model to account for all special obligations, given their apparent diversity ("Families, Nations and Strangers," The Lindley Lecture, University of Kansas, 1994, p. 3).
    • (1994) The Lindley Lecture , pp. 3
    • Scheffler, S.1
  • 45
    • 0003150042 scopus 로고
    • Liberating duties
    • See Joseph Raz, "Liberating Duties," Law and Philosophy 8 (1989): 3-21, pp. 18-21.
    • (1989) Law and Philosophy , vol.8 , pp. 3-21
    • Joseph, R.1
  • 46
    • 0039085917 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Raz uses 'intrinsic value' to mean noninstrumental value, and I shall follow him in this usage.
  • 47
    • 0039678166 scopus 로고
    • Promises and obligations
    • ed. P. M. S. Hacker and J. Raz Oxford: Clarendon
    • Raz employs the language of duty rather than the language of obligation, but I don't think that anything turns on this, since he has elsewhere treated them as equivalent. (He does, however, maintain that there are reasons to distinguish between 'A has an obligation or duty to X' and 'A ought to X', and for assigning the former a special role.) See Joseph Raz, "Promises and Obligations," in Law, Morality, and Society: Essays in Honour of H. L. A. Hart, ed. P. M. S. Hacker and J. Raz (Oxford: Clarendon, 1977), pp. 210-28.
    • (1977) Law, Morality, and Society: Essays in Honour of H. L. A. Hart , pp. 210-228
    • Joseph, R.1
  • 49
    • 0040269926 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Here it needs to be emphasized that much of what is valuable about friendship cannot be understood in terms of the recognition of obligations or duties. Indeed it would often be appropriate for one friend to be offended by another if they discovered that they had acted from a sense of duty rather than because they cared about them. The language of responsibility is perhaps more appropriate here because to say that one acted on behalf of a friend because one felt responsible for them carries with it no conversational implication that one's actions were not done out of concern for the friend.
  • 51
    • 0003460304 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press, esp. chap. 8
    • On the importance of the cultural context of choice, see Will Kymlicka, Liberalism, Community and Culture (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989), esp. chap. 8. See also Avishai Margalit and Joseph Raz, "National Self-Determination," Journal of Philosophy 87 (1990): 439-61, esp. pp. 448-50.
    • (1989) Liberalism, Community and Culture
    • Kymlicka, W.1
  • 52
    • 0000182108 scopus 로고
    • National self-determination
    • esp. pp. 448-50
    • On the importance of the cultural context of choice, see Will Kymlicka, Liberalism, Community and Culture (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989), esp. chap. 8. See also Avishai Margalit and Joseph Raz, "National Self-Determination," Journal of Philosophy 87 (1990): 439-61, esp. pp. 448-50.
    • (1990) Journal of Philosophy , vol.87 , pp. 439-461
    • Margalit, A.1    Joseph, R.2
  • 53
  • 54
    • 0004002174 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • David Miller, who defends special obligations to fellow nationals and sees them as derived from the nation's public culture and traditions, appears to accept this conclusion; see On Nationality, pp. 68-70.
    • On Nationality , pp. 68-70
    • Miller, D.1
  • 55
    • 84884062670 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, chap. 6
    • I mean to leave it an open question whether citizens may possess equal status even when some of them enjoy special rights. On certain assumptions special rights can be reconciled with a fundamental equality of status. See Kymlicka, esp. chap. 9; Iris Marion Young, Justice and the Politics of Difference (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1990), chap. 6.
    • (1990) Justice and the Politics of Difference
    • Young, I.M.1
  • 56
    • 84925677087 scopus 로고
    • Cosmopolitanism and sovereignty
    • Thomas Pogge, "Cosmopolitanism and Sovereignty," Ethics 103 (1992): 48-75, p. 58.
    • (1992) Ethics , vol.103 , pp. 48-75
    • Pogge, T.1
  • 57
    • 0040269860 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I do not mean to suggest that friendship and citizenship are analogous in all important respects. Clearly there are important differences between them. Friendship (in general) is a voluntary relationship, whereas citizenship (in general) is nonvoluntary; a person may cease to be a friend by persistently failing to fulfill the obligations of friendship, whereas a person does not cease to be a citizen of a state simply by neglecting her duties. The core of the analogy is unaffected by these observations, however. Citizenship, like friendship, is intrinsically valuable, and obligations of citizenship, like obligations of friendship, are part of the good of that relationship as well as being justified by that good.
  • 58
    • 84981567961 scopus 로고
    • Citizenship and pluralism
    • For helpful distinctions between different models of citizenship, and a defense of the republican one, see David Miller, "Citizenship and Pluralism," Political Studies 43 (1995): 432-50.
    • (1995) Political Studies , vol.43 , pp. 432-450
    • Miller, D.1
  • 59
    • 0039678167 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Doesn't this make my account vulnerable to the objection I leveled against Tamir's that it sanctions special obligations between racists? My account avoids this difficulty by maintaining that only relationships which have intrinsic value can generate special obligations in this way. A relationship founded upon shared racial prejudice cannot have such value. If racists are friends, then their friendship may create special obligations, but those special obligations would exist between them qua friends rather than qua racists. Since Tamir argues that special obligations can be generated simply from constitutive attachments, she must allow that special obligations can exist between two racists qua racists since it may be racism that binds them together.
  • 60
    • 0039085860 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Tamir, p. 102. As I noted in the second section, Waldron has provided a potential response to this point in "Special Ties and Natural Duties."
    • Tamir, p. 102. As I noted in the second section, Waldron has provided a potential response to this point in "Special Ties and Natural Duties."
  • 66
    • 0040269924 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The account I am suggesting may still be compatible with broadly consequentialist approaches since it can allow that ultimately harms and benefits to noncitizens count the same as those to citizens, and that they can be weighed against one another.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.