메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 47, Issue 1, 1999, Pages 67-82

Freedom and opportunity

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0032670094     PISSN: 00323217     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/1467-9248.00188     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (29)

References (58)
  • 1
    • 84937294620 scopus 로고
    • The independent value of freedom
    • 1 I. Carter, 'The independent value of freedom', Ethics, 105 (1995), 819-45.
    • (1995) Ethics , vol.105 , pp. 819-845
    • Carter, I.1
  • 2
    • 0003917729 scopus 로고
    • San Francisco, Holden-Day
    • 2 A. K. Sen, Collective Choice and Social Welfare (San Francisco, Holden-Day, 1970). Sen formulated his theorem in terms of social choice theory. For alternative approaches, see P. Gärdenfors, 'Rights, games and social choice'. Noûs, 15 (1981). 341-56; W. Gaertner, P. K. Pattanaik and K. Suzumura, 'Individual rights revisited', Economica, 59 (1992), 161-77; M. van Hees, Rights and Decisions. Formal Models of Law and Liberalism (Dordrecht, Kluwer, 1995).
    • (1970) Collective Choice and Social Welfare
    • Sen, A.K.1
  • 3
    • 84868119373 scopus 로고
    • Rights, games and social choice
    • 2 A. K. Sen, Collective Choice and Social Welfare (San Francisco, Holden-Day, 1970). Sen formulated his theorem in terms of social choice theory. For alternative approaches, see P. Gärdenfors, 'Rights, games and social choice'. Noûs, 15 (1981). 341-56; W. Gaertner, P. K. Pattanaik and K. Suzumura, 'Individual rights revisited', Economica, 59 (1992), 161-77; M. van Hees, Rights and Decisions. Formal Models of Law and Liberalism (Dordrecht, Kluwer, 1995).
    • (1981) Noûs , vol.15 , pp. 341-356
    • Gärdenfors, P.1
  • 4
    • 0002995535 scopus 로고
    • Individual rights revisited
    • 2 A. K. Sen, Collective Choice and Social Welfare (San Francisco, Holden-Day, 1970). Sen formulated his theorem in terms of social choice theory. For alternative approaches, see P. Gärdenfors, 'Rights, games and social choice'. Noûs, 15 (1981). 341-56; W. Gaertner, P. K. Pattanaik and K. Suzumura, 'Individual rights revisited', Economica, 59 (1992), 161-77; M. van Hees, Rights and Decisions. Formal Models of Law and Liberalism (Dordrecht, Kluwer, 1995).
    • (1992) Economica , vol.59 , pp. 161-177
    • Gaertner, W.1    Pattanaik, P.K.2    Suzumura, K.3
  • 5
    • 0004127479 scopus 로고
    • Dordrecht, Kluwer
    • 2 A. K. Sen, Collective Choice and Social Welfare (San Francisco, Holden-Day, 1970). Sen formulated his theorem in terms of social choice theory. For alternative approaches, see P. Gärdenfors, 'Rights, games and social choice'. Noûs, 15 (1981). 341-56; W. Gaertner, P. K. Pattanaik and K. Suzumura, 'Individual rights revisited', Economica, 59 (1992), 161-77; M. van Hees, Rights and Decisions. Formal Models of Law and Liberalism (Dordrecht, Kluwer, 1995).
    • (1995) Rights and Decisions. Formal Models of Law and Liberalism
    • Van Hees, M.1
  • 6
    • 0000409618 scopus 로고
    • On ranking opportunity sets in terms of freedom of choice
    • 3 P. K. Pattanaik and Y. Xu, 'On ranking opportunity sets in terms of freedom of choice', Recherches Economiques de Louvain, 56 (1990), 383-90; M. Klemish-Ahlert, 'Freedom of choice. A comparison of different rankings of opportunity sets', Social Choice and Welfare, 10 (1993), 189-207; M. van Hees, 'On the analysis of negative freedom', Theory and Decision, forthcoming.
    • (1990) Recherches Economiques de Louvain , vol.56 , pp. 383-390
    • Pattanaik, P.K.1    Xu, Y.2
  • 7
    • 0742319398 scopus 로고
    • Freedom of choice. A comparison of different rankings of opportunity sets
    • 3 P. K. Pattanaik and Y. Xu, 'On ranking opportunity sets in terms of freedom of choice', Recherches Economiques de Louvain, 56 (1990), 383-90; M. Klemish-Ahlert, 'Freedom of choice. A comparison of different rankings of opportunity sets', Social Choice and Welfare, 10 (1993), 189-207; M. van Hees, 'On the analysis of negative freedom', Theory and Decision, forthcoming.
    • (1993) Social Choice and Welfare , vol.10 , pp. 189-207
    • Klemish-Ahlert, M.1
  • 8
    • 85034175431 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the analysis of negative freedom
    • forthcoming
    • 3 P. K. Pattanaik and Y. Xu, 'On ranking opportunity sets in terms of freedom of choice', Recherches Economiques de Louvain, 56 (1990), 383-90; M. Klemish-Ahlert, 'Freedom of choice. A comparison of different rankings of opportunity sets', Social Choice and Welfare, 10 (1993), 189-207; M. van Hees, 'On the analysis of negative freedom', Theory and Decision, forthcoming.
    • Theory and Decision
    • Van Hees, M.1
  • 9
    • 0009326832 scopus 로고
    • Welfare, freedom and social choice. A reply
    • 4 A. K. Sen, 'Welfare, freedom and social choice. A reply', Recherches Economiques de Louvain, 56 (1990), 451-85; A. K. Sen, 'Welfare, preference and freedom', Journal of Econometrics, 50 (1991), 15-29; C. Puppe, 'An axiomatic approach to "Preferences for freedom of choice"' Journal of Economic Theory, 68 (1996), 174-99; P. K. Pattanaik and Y. Xu, 'On preference and freedom' Theory and Decision, forthcoming.
    • (1990) Recherches Economiques de Louvain , vol.56 , pp. 451-485
    • Sen, A.K.1
  • 10
    • 0002514845 scopus 로고
    • Welfare, preference and freedom
    • 4 A. K. Sen, 'Welfare, freedom and social choice. A reply', Recherches Economiques de Louvain, 56 (1990), 451-85; A. K. Sen, 'Welfare, preference and freedom', Journal of Econometrics, 50 (1991), 15-29; C. Puppe, 'An axiomatic approach to "Preferences for freedom of choice"' Journal of Economic Theory, 68 (1996), 174-99; P. K. Pattanaik and Y. Xu, 'On preference and freedom' Theory and Decision, forthcoming.
    • (1991) Journal of Econometrics , vol.50 , pp. 15-29
    • Sen, A.K.1
  • 11
    • 0029690672 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An axiomatic approach to "Preferences for freedom of choice"
    • 4 A. K. Sen, 'Welfare, freedom and social choice. A reply', Recherches Economiques de Louvain, 56 (1990), 451-85; A. K. Sen, 'Welfare, preference and freedom', Journal of Econometrics, 50 (1991), 15-29; C. Puppe, 'An axiomatic approach to "Preferences for freedom of choice"' Journal of Economic Theory, 68 (1996), 174-99; P. K. Pattanaik and Y. Xu, 'On preference and freedom' Theory and Decision, forthcoming.
    • (1996) Journal of Economic Theory , vol.68 , pp. 174-199
    • Puppe, C.1
  • 12
    • 85034183474 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On preference and freedom
    • forthcoming
    • 4 A. K. Sen, 'Welfare, freedom and social choice. A reply', Recherches Economiques de Louvain, 56 (1990), 451-85; A. K. Sen, 'Welfare, preference and freedom', Journal of Econometrics, 50 (1991), 15-29; C. Puppe, 'An axiomatic approach to "Preferences for freedom of choice"' Journal of Economic Theory, 68 (1996), 174-99; P. K. Pattanaik and Y. Xu, 'On preference and freedom' Theory and Decision, forthcoming.
    • Theory and Decision
    • Pattanaik, P.K.1    Xu, Y.2
  • 13
    • 0000442874 scopus 로고
    • Markets and freedoms: Achievements and limitations of the market mechanism in promoting individual freedoms
    • p. 522
    • 5 A. K. Sen, 'Markets and freedoms: Achievements and limitations of the market mechanism in promoting individual freedoms', Oxford Economic Papers, 45 (1993), 519-54, p. 522.
    • (1993) Oxford Economic Papers , vol.45 , pp. 519-554
    • Sen, A.K.1
  • 14
    • 0009324413 scopus 로고
    • On liberty and the real will
    • 6 The present discussion reflects many points made earlier in political theory. For a forceful defence of a non-preference based conception of freedom, see J. P. Day, 'On liberty and the real will', Philosophy, 45 (1970), 177-92. Specific cardinal measurements were proposed by H. Steiner 'How Free. Computing Personal Liberty', in A. Phillips Griffiths (ed.), Of Liberty (Cambridge University Press, 1983), pp. 73-89 and I. Carter, 'The measurement of pure negative freedom', Political Studies, 40 (1992), 38-50. The idea that the preferences of reasonable persons should count can be found in S. I. Benn and W. L. Weinstein, 'Being free to act, and being a free man', Mind, 80 (1971), 194-211 and J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Oxford University Press, 1971).
    • (1970) Philosophy , vol.45 , pp. 177-192
    • Day, J.P.1
  • 15
    • 0009324413 scopus 로고
    • How free. Computing personal liberty
    • A. Phillips Griffiths (ed.), Cambridge University Press
    • 6 The present discussion reflects many points made earlier in political theory. For a forceful defence of a non-preference based conception of freedom, see J. P. Day, 'On liberty and the real will', Philosophy, 45 (1970), 177-92. Specific cardinal measurements were proposed by H. Steiner 'How Free. Computing Personal Liberty', in A. Phillips Griffiths (ed.), Of Liberty (Cambridge University Press, 1983), pp. 73-89 and I. Carter, 'The measurement of pure negative freedom', Political Studies, 40 (1992), 38-50. The idea that the preferences of reasonable persons should count can be found in S. I. Benn and W. L. Weinstein, 'Being free to act, and being a free man', Mind, 80 (1971), 194-211 and J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Oxford University Press, 1971).
    • (1983) Of Liberty , pp. 73-89
    • Steiner, H.1
  • 16
    • 0002611368 scopus 로고
    • The measurement of pure negative freedom
    • 6 The present discussion reflects many points made earlier in political theory. For a forceful defence of a non-preference based conception of freedom, see J. P. Day, 'On liberty and the real will', Philosophy, 45 (1970), 177-92. Specific cardinal measurements were proposed by H. Steiner 'How Free. Computing Personal Liberty', in A. Phillips Griffiths (ed.), Of Liberty (Cambridge University Press, 1983), pp. 73-89 and I. Carter, 'The measurement of pure negative freedom', Political Studies, 40 (1992), 38-50. The idea that the preferences of reasonable persons should count can be found in S. I. Benn and W. L. Weinstein, 'Being free to act, and being a free man', Mind, 80 (1971), 194-211 and J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Oxford University Press, 1971).
    • (1992) Political Studies , vol.40 , pp. 38-50
    • Carter, I.1
  • 17
    • 0009324413 scopus 로고
    • Being free to act, and being a free man
    • 6 The present discussion reflects many points made earlier in political theory. For a forceful defence of a non-preference based conception of freedom, see J. P. Day, 'On liberty and the real will', Philosophy, 45 (1970), 177-92. Specific cardinal measurements were proposed by H. Steiner 'How Free. Computing Personal Liberty', in A. Phillips Griffiths (ed.), Of Liberty (Cambridge University Press, 1983), pp. 73-89 and I. Carter, 'The measurement of pure negative freedom', Political Studies, 40 (1992), 38-50. The idea that the preferences of reasonable persons should count can be found in S. I. Benn and W. L. Weinstein, 'Being free to act, and being a free man', Mind, 80 (1971), 194-211 and J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Oxford University Press, 1971).
    • (1971) Mind , vol.80 , pp. 194-211
    • Benn, S.I.1    Weinstein, W.L.2
  • 18
    • 0009324413 scopus 로고
    • Oxford University Press
    • 6 The present discussion reflects many points made earlier in political theory. For a forceful defence of a non-preference based conception of freedom, see J. P. Day, 'On liberty and the real will', Philosophy, 45 (1970), 177-92. Specific cardinal measurements were proposed by H. Steiner 'How Free. Computing Personal Liberty', in A. Phillips Griffiths (ed.), Of Liberty (Cambridge University Press, 1983), pp. 73-89 and I. Carter, 'The measurement of pure negative freedom', Political Studies, 40 (1992), 38-50. The idea that the preferences of reasonable persons should count can be found in S. I. Benn and W. L. Weinstein, 'Being free to act, and being a free man', Mind, 80 (1971), 194-211 and J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Oxford University Press, 1971).
    • (1971) A Theory of Justice
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 22
    • 0001389526 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Freedom of choice. Concept and content
    • 10 A. K. Sen, 'Freedom of choice. concept and content', european economic Review 32 (1988), 269-94; A. K. Sen, 'Welfare, preference and freedom'; A. K. Sen, 'Markets and freedoms: achievemnts and limitation of the market mechanism in promoting individual freedoms'; A. K. Sen, 'Rationality and social choice', American Economic Review, 85 (1995), 1-24.
    • (1988) European Economic Review , vol.32 , pp. 269-294
    • Sen, A.K.1
  • 23
    • 0001389526 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 10 A. K. Sen, 'Freedom of choice. concept and content', european economic Review 32 (1988), 269-94; A. K. Sen, 'Welfare, preference and freedom'; A. K. Sen, 'Markets and freedoms: achievemnts and limitation of the market mechanism in promoting individual freedoms'; A. K. Sen, 'Rationality and social choice', American Economic Review, 85 (1995), 1-24.
    • Welfare, Preference and Freedom
    • Sen, A.K.1
  • 25
    • 0001389526 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rationality and social choice
    • 10 A. K. Sen, 'Freedom of choice. concept and content', european economic Review 32 (1988), 269-94; A. K. Sen, 'Welfare, preference and freedom'; A. K. Sen, 'Markets and freedoms: achievemnts and limitation of the market mechanism in promoting individual freedoms'; A. K. Sen, 'Rationality and social choice', American Economic Review, 85 (1995), 1-24.
    • (1995) American Economic Review , vol.85 , pp. 1-24
    • Sen, A.K.1
  • 26
    • 0004344766 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 11 Sen, Welfare, freedom and social choice. A reply', p. 471; Cf. J. Raz, The Morality of Freedom (Oxford, Clanderon, 1986); K. Dowding, 'Choice: its increase and its value', British Journal of Political Science, 22 (1992), 301-14 and Th. M, Scanlon, The Significance of choice', in S. M. McMurrin (ed.), The Tanner Lectures on Human Values VIII (University of Utah Press, 1988), pp. 151-216 for alternative accounts of freedom and the value of freedom.
    • Welfare, Freedom and Social Choice. A Reply , pp. 471
    • Sen1
  • 27
    • 0003956640 scopus 로고
    • Oxford, Clanderon
    • 11 Sen, Welfare, freedom and social choice. A reply', p. 471; Cf. J. Raz, The Morality of Freedom (Oxford, Clanderon, 1986); K. Dowding, 'Choice: its increase and its value', British Journal of Political Science, 22 (1992), 301-14 and Th. M, Scanlon, The Significance of choice', in S. M. McMurrin (ed.), The Tanner Lectures on Human Values VIII (University of Utah Press, 1988), pp. 151-216 for alternative accounts of freedom and the value of freedom.
    • (1986) The Morality of Freedom
    • Raz, J.1
  • 28
    • 84972364263 scopus 로고
    • Choice: Its increase and its value
    • 11 Sen, Welfare, freedom and social choice. A reply', p. 471; Cf. J. Raz, The Morality of Freedom (Oxford, Clanderon, 1986); K. Dowding, 'Choice: its increase and its value', British Journal of Political Science, 22 (1992), 301-14 and Th. M, Scanlon, The Significance of choice', in S. M. McMurrin (ed.), The Tanner Lectures on Human Values VIII (University of Utah Press, 1988), pp. 151-216 for alternative accounts of freedom and the value of freedom.
    • (1992) British Journal of Political Science , vol.22 , pp. 301-314
    • Dowding, K.1
  • 29
    • 0009420844 scopus 로고
    • The Significance of choice
    • S. M. McMurrin (ed.), University of Utah Press, for alternative accounts of freedom and the value of freedom
    • 11 Sen, Welfare, freedom and social choice. A reply', p. 471; Cf. J. Raz, The Morality of Freedom (Oxford, Clanderon, 1986); K. Dowding, 'Choice: its increase and its value', British Journal of Political Science, 22 (1992), 301-14 and Th. M, Scanlon, The Significance of choice', in S. M. McMurrin (ed.), The Tanner Lectures on Human Values VIII (University of Utah Press, 1988), pp. 151-216 for alternative accounts of freedom and the value of freedom.
    • (1988) The Tanner Lectures on Human Values VIII , pp. 151-216
    • Scanlon, T.M.1
  • 38
    • 0001594020 scopus 로고
    • A Representation theorem for "prefence for flexibility"
    • 20 D. M. Kreps, 'A Representation theorem for "prefence for flexibility"', Econometrica, 47 (1979), 565-77.
    • (1979) Econometrica , vol.47 , pp. 565-577
    • Kreps, D.M.1
  • 41
    • 0004345036 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The reader might suggest that objections to the Ban On Women could well be inspired by a feeling that the Ban is unjust, unfair, undeserved or an unjustifiable case of unequal treatment. The reader would be right. Be that as it may, among the reasons one might have to oppose the Ban, the sense that individual liberty is violated here may still play a major role independent of any considerations of justice
    • 23 Pattanaik and Xu, 'On preference and freedom', p. 5. The reader might suggest that objections to the Ban On Women could well be inspired by a feeling that the Ban is unjust, unfair, undeserved or an unjustifiable case of unequal treatment. The reader would be right. Be that as it may, among the reasons one might have to oppose the Ban, the sense that individual liberty is violated here may still play a major role independent of any considerations of justice.
    • On Preference and Freedom , pp. 5
    • Pattanaik1    Xu2
  • 43
    • 0002726861 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 25 Pattanaik and Xu, 'On preference and freedom', p. 7. Their approach is strongly influenced by P. Jones and R. Sugden, 'Evaluating choice', International Review of Law and Economics, 2 (1982), 47-65. See also R. Sugden, 'The metric of opportunity', Economics and Philosophy, forthcoming.
    • On Preference and Freedom , pp. 7
    • Pattanaik1    Xu2
  • 44
    • 0002726861 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Evaluating choice
    • 25 Pattanaik and Xu, 'On preference and freedom', p. 7. Their approach is strongly influenced by P. Jones and R. Sugden, 'Evaluating choice', International Review of Law and Economics, 2 (1982), 47-65. See also R. Sugden, 'The metric of opportunity', Economics and Philosophy, forthcoming.
    • (1982) International Review of Law and Economics , vol.2 , pp. 47-65
    • Jones, P.1    Sugden, R.2
  • 45
    • 0002726861 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The metric of opportunity
    • forthcoming
    • 25 Pattanaik and Xu, 'On preference and freedom', p. 7. Their approach is strongly influenced by P. Jones and R. Sugden, 'Evaluating choice', International Review of Law and Economics, 2 (1982), 47-65. See also R. Sugden, 'The metric of opportunity', Economics and Philosophy, forthcoming.
    • Economics and Philosophy
    • Sugden, R.1
  • 47
    • 85034158677 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • And as one of the referees pointed out to us, Thomas More did prefer decapitation at dawn to becoming a Protestant, a choice which he felt to be reasonable given his circumstances
    • 27 And as one of the referees pointed out to us, Thomas More did prefer decapitation at dawn to becoming a Protestant, a choice which he felt to be reasonable given his circumstances.
  • 48
    • 85034187131 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • If an individual's position is indeed unique and non-reproducible, the amount of freedom enjoyed depends not only on the exact situation but also on the particular individual; freedom would not be just determined 'situationally' but even purely subjectively
    • 28 If an individual's position is indeed unique and non-reproducible, the amount of freedom enjoyed depends not only on the exact situation but also on the particular individual; freedom would not be just determined 'situationally' but even purely subjectively.
  • 50
    • 84871647310 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 30 For a more comprehensive treatment of the reasonable, see J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 56-8, and B. Barry, Justice as Impartiality. A Treatise on Social Justice Volume II (Oxford, Claredon, 1995), p. 69; traces of this idea can also in Robert Nozick's Anarchy, State and Utopia (New York, Basic, 1974), pp. 48-51.
    • A Theory of Justice , pp. 56-58
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 51
    • 0003555163 scopus 로고
    • Oxford, Claredon
    • 30 For a more comprehensive treatment of the reasonable, see J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 56-8, and B. Barry, Justice as Impartiality. A Treatise on Social Justice Volume II (Oxford, Claredon, 1995), p. 69; traces of this idea can also in Robert Nozick's Anarchy, State and Utopia (New York, Basic, 1974), pp. 48-51.
    • (1995) Justice As Impartiality. A Treatise on Social Justice Volume II , pp. 69
    • Barry, B.1
  • 52
    • 0004273805 scopus 로고
    • New York, Basic
    • 30 For a more comprehensive treatment of the reasonable, see J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 56-8, and B. Barry, Justice as Impartiality. A Treatise on Social Justice Volume II (Oxford, Claredon, 1995), p. 69; traces of this idea can also in Robert Nozick's Anarchy, State and Utopia (New York, Basic, 1974), pp. 48-51.
    • (1974) Anarchy, State and Utopia , pp. 48-51
    • Nozick's, R.1
  • 53
    • 85034182796 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • They might, of course, exclude preference relations that are not orderings
    • 31 They might, of course, exclude preference relations that are not orderings.
  • 54
    • 85034171489 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • points out that a similar argumentative loop sometimes occurs in political philosophy when claims are made about the superior degree of freedom that a theory of justice would guarantee, when freedom has first been defined in terms of that same conception of justice
    • 32 Carter ('The independent value of freedom', p. 844) points out that a similar argumentative loop sometimes occurs in political philosophy when claims are made about the superior degree of freedom that a theory of justice would guarantee, when freedom has first been defined in terms of that same conception of justice.
    • The Independent Value of Freedom , pp. 844
    • Carter1
  • 55
    • 85034172203 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • 33 Let C denote the set consisting of all feasible alternatives which maximize utility in at least one utility function with positive probability. Under Arrow's conception of freedom, an agent derives as much freedom from C as from the set of all feasible alternatives X. Thus, in the most extreme case in which there is a utility function with probability one, the singleton set consisting of the most preferred alternative, say {x}, yields as much freedom as X: a government-enforced allocation of only and exactly the one thing x that an individual most wants will give as much opportunity freedom as being able to choose any feasible alternative from a set that includes other elements next to x.
  • 56
    • 85034183063 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For further discussion of the individuation issue see Steiner, 'How Free. Computing Personal Liberty'; Dowding, 'Choice: its increase and its value'
    • 34 For further discussion of the individuation issue see Steiner, 'How Free. Computing Personal Liberty'; Dowding, 'Choice: its increase and its value'.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.