메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 109, Issue 2, 1999, Pages 165-246

Rethinking cost-benefit analysis

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0013065921     PISSN: 00440094     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.2307/797489     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (166)

References (315)
  • 1
    • 84923752592 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See sources cited infra notes 10-18
    • See sources cited infra notes 10-18.
  • 2
    • 84923752590 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Exec. Order No. 12,866, 3 C.F.R. 638, 639 (1993), reprinted in 5 U.S.C. § 601 (1994); Exec. Order No. 12,291, 3 C.F.R. 127 (1981), revoked by Exec. Order No. 12,866
    • See Exec. Order No. 12,866, 3 C.F.R. 638, 639 (1993), reprinted in 5 U.S.C. § 601 (1994); Exec. Order No. 12,291, 3 C.F.R. 127 (1981), revoked by Exec. Order No. 12,866. Clinton's order qualified Reagan's order a bit but essentially endorsed the use of CBA.
  • 3
    • 84885215480 scopus 로고
    • Reinventing the regulatory state
    • See Richard H. Pildes & Cass R. Sunstein, Reinventing the Regulatory State, 62 U. CHI. L. REV. 1, 6-7 (1995).
    • (1995) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.62 , pp. 1
    • Pildes, R.H.1    Sunstein, C.R.2
  • 4
    • 0345867265 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Judicial review of discount rates used in regulatory cost-benefit analysis
    • See Edward R. Morrison, Judicial Review of Discount Rates Used in Regulatory Cost-Benefit Analysis, 65 U. CHI. L. REV. 1333, 1333 (1998) (citing statutes requiring cost-benefit analyses).
    • (1998) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.65 , pp. 1333
    • Morrison, E.R.1
  • 5
    • 85079107637 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Economic analysis: Benefits, costs, implications
    • Richard D. Morgenstern ed., [hereinafter ECONOMIC ANALYSES AT EPA].
    • See Richard D. Morgenstern & Marc K. Landy, Economic Analysis: Benefits, Costs, Implications, in ECONOMIC ANALYSES AT EPA: ASSESSING REGULATORY IMPACT 455, 461-62 (Richard D. Morgenstern ed., 1997) [hereinafter ECONOMIC ANALYSES AT EPA].
    • (1997) Economic Analyses at EPA: Assessing Regulatory Impact , pp. 455
    • Morgenstern, R.D.1    Landy, M.K.2
  • 6
    • 0004232141 scopus 로고
    • discussing the Flood Control Act of 1936, ch. 688, § 1, 49 Stat. 1570, 1570 (codified as amended at 33 U.S.C. § 701a (1994))
    • See AJIT K. DASGUPTA & D.W. PEARCE, COST-BENEFIT ANALYSIS: THEORY AND PRACTICE 12-13 (1972) (discussing the Flood Control Act of 1936, ch. 688, § 1, 49 Stat. 1570, 1570 (codified as amended at 33 U.S.C. § 701a (1994)), which held that projects should be approved if "the benefits to whomsoever they may accrue are in excess of the estimated costs") (emphasis added).
    • (1972) Cost-benefit Analysis: Theory and Practice , pp. 12-13
    • Dasgupta, A.K.1    Pearce, D.W.2
  • 8
    • 0032410022 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cost-benefit analysis and environmental policy
    • discussing the history of CBA
    • For a brief history, see THEODORE M. PORTER, TRUST IN NUMBERS: THE PURSUIT OF OBJECTIVITY IN SCIENCE AND PUBLIC LIFE 148-89 (1995). See also David Pearce, Cost-Benefit Analysis and Environmental Policy, 14 OXFORD REV. ECON. POL'Y 84, 88-91 (1998) (discussing the history of CBA).
    • (1998) Oxford Rev. Econ. Pol'y , vol.14 , pp. 84
    • Pearce, D.1
  • 9
    • 0001899684 scopus 로고
    • The economics profession and the making of public policy
    • See Robert H. Nelson, The Economics Profession and the Making of Public Policy, 25 J. ECON. LITERATURE 49, 52-54 (1987).
    • (1987) J. Econ. Literature , vol.25 , pp. 49
    • Nelson, R.H.1
  • 10
    • 84923752588 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id.
    • See id.
  • 11
    • 84923752586 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DASGUPTA & PEARCE, supra note 5, at 12-13. id. at 14
    • See DASGUPTA & PEARCE, supra note 5, at 12-13. In addition, private companies had independently developed techniques for evaluating their investment decisions, and these techniques could be transferred to the public sector. See id. at 14.
  • 12
    • 0004145802 scopus 로고
    • 2d ed.
    • See I.M.D. LITTLE, A CRITIQUE OF WELFARE ECONOMICS 84 (2d ed. 1957). One could alternatively date modern welfare economics - or at least the Anglo-American version - to Lionel Robbins's attacks in the 1930s on the older "material welfare school," which focused on the material well-being of individuals (as opposed to their utility, in the modern sense), and held that the material well-being of individuals is comparable. See Robert Cooter & Peter Rappoport, Were the Ordinalists Wrong About Welfare Economics?, 22 J. ECON. LITERATURE 507, 520-21 (1984).
    • (1957) A Critique of Welfare Economics , pp. 84
    • Little, I.M.D.1
  • 13
    • 0000964163 scopus 로고
    • Were the ordinalists wrong about welfare economics?
    • See I.M.D. LITTLE, A CRITIQUE OF WELFARE ECONOMICS 84 (2d ed. 1957). One could alternatively date modern welfare economics - or at least the Anglo-American version - to Lionel Robbins's attacks in the 1930s on the older "material welfare school," which focused on the material well-being of individuals (as opposed to their utility, in the modern sense), and held that the material well-being of individuals is comparable. See Robert Cooter & Peter Rappoport, Were the Ordinalists Wrong About Welfare Economics?, 22 J. ECON. LITERATURE 507, 520-21 (1984).
    • (1984) J. Econ. Literature , vol.22 , pp. 507
    • Cooter, R.1    Rappoport, P.2
  • 14
    • 0000082519 scopus 로고
    • The foundations of welfare economics
    • See, e.g., J.R. Hicks, The Foundations of Welfare Economics, 49 ECON. J. 696 (1939); Harold Hotelling, The General Welfare in Relation to Problems of Taxation and of Railway and Utility Rates, 6 ECONOMETRICA 242 (1938); Nicholas Kaldor, Welfare Propositions of Economics and Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility, 49 ECON. J. 549 (1939). A useful discussion of these tests can be found in LITTLE, supra note 10, at 88-96.
    • (1939) Econ. J. , vol.49 , pp. 696
    • Hicks, J.R.1
  • 15
    • 0001514051 scopus 로고
    • The general welfare in relation to problems of taxation and of railway and utility rates
    • See, e.g., J.R. Hicks, The Foundations of Welfare Economics, 49 ECON. J. 696 (1939); Harold Hotelling, The General Welfare in Relation to Problems of Taxation and of Railway and Utility Rates, 6 ECONOMETRICA 242 (1938); Nicholas Kaldor, Welfare Propositions of Economics and Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility, 49 ECON. J. 549 (1939). A useful discussion of these tests can be found in LITTLE, supra note 10, at 88-96.
    • (1938) Econometrica , vol.6 , pp. 242
    • Hotelling, H.1
  • 16
    • 0000310992 scopus 로고
    • Welfare propositions of economics and interpersonal comparisons of utility
    • See, e.g., J.R. Hicks, The Foundations of Welfare Economics, 49 ECON. J. 696 (1939); Harold Hotelling, The General Welfare in Relation to Problems of Taxation and of Railway and Utility Rates, 6 ECONOMETRICA 242 (1938); Nicholas Kaldor, Welfare Propositions of Economics and Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility, 49 ECON. J. 549 (1939). A useful discussion of these tests can be found in LITTLE, supra note 10, at 88-96.
    • (1939) Econ. J. , vol.49 , pp. 549
    • Kaldor, N.1
  • 17
    • 84923752585 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • LITTLE, supra note 10, at 88-96
    • See, e.g., J.R. Hicks, The Foundations of Welfare Economics, 49 ECON. J. 696 (1939); Harold Hotelling, The General Welfare in Relation to Problems of Taxation and of Railway and Utility Rates, 6 ECONOMETRICA 242 (1938); Nicholas Kaldor, Welfare Propositions of Economics and Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility, 49 ECON. J. 549 (1939). A useful discussion of these tests can be found in LITTLE, supra note 10, at 88-96.
  • 19
    • 0001364070 scopus 로고
    • The new welfare economics 1939-1974
    • See, e.g., John S. Chipman & James C. Moore, The New Welfare Economics 1939-1974, 19 INT'L ECON. REV. 547, 548 (1978) (calling modern welfare economics a "failure"). This view is briefly discussed in DASGUPTA & PEARCE, supra note 5, at 15.
    • (1978) Int'l Econ. Rev. , vol.19 , pp. 547
    • Chipman, J.S.1    Moore, J.C.2
  • 20
    • 84923752584 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DASGUPTA & PEARCE, supra note 5, at 15
    • See, e.g., John S. Chipman & James C. Moore, The New Welfare Economics 1939-1974, 19 INT'L ECON. REV. 547, 548 (1978) (calling modern welfare economics a "failure"). This view is briefly discussed in DASGUPTA & PEARCE, supra note 5, at 15.
  • 21
    • 0003501233 scopus 로고
    • See D.W. PEARCE & C.A. NASH, THE SOCIAL APPRAISAL OF PROJECTS: A TEXT ON COST-BENEFIT ANALYSIS 3-4 (1981); R. Shep Melnick, The Politics of Benefit-Cost Analysis, in VALUING HEALTH RISKS, COSTS, AND BENEFITS FOR ENVIRONMENTAL DECISION MAKING 23 (P. Brett Hammond & Rob Coppock eds., 1990) (attributing hostility toward CBA to populist politics).
    • (1981) The Social Appraisal of Projects: A Text on Cost-benefit Analysis , pp. 3-4
    • Pearce, D.W.1    Nash, C.A.2
  • 22
    • 0039093777 scopus 로고
    • The politics of benefit-cost analysis
    • P. Brett Hammond & Rob Coppock eds.
    • See D.W. PEARCE & C.A. NASH, THE SOCIAL APPRAISAL OF PROJECTS: A TEXT ON COST-BENEFIT ANALYSIS 3-4 (1981); R. Shep Melnick, The Politics of Benefit-Cost Analysis, in VALUING HEALTH RISKS, COSTS, AND BENEFITS FOR ENVIRONMENTAL DECISION MAKING 23 (P. Brett Hammond & Rob Coppock eds., 1990) (attributing hostility toward CBA to populist politics).
    • (1990) Valuing Health Risks, Costs, and Benefits for Environmental Decision Making , pp. 23
    • Shep Melnick, R.1
  • 23
    • 0039685997 scopus 로고
    • Symposium on efficiency as a legal concern
    • A large legal literature addresses the related question whether legal rules in general, and the common law in particular, do or should reflect efficiency concerns. See, e.g., Symposium on Efficiency as a Legal Concern, 8 HOFSTRA L. REV. 485 (1980). This literature is of limited usefulness for our purposes. It does not address CBA, for the most part, and much of it is concerned about the role of common-law judges. Otherwise it resembles earlier discussions in the economics literature. More recent treatments in the legal literature include MARK KELMAN, A GUIDE TO CRITICAL LEGAL STUDIES 114-50 (1987); David M. Driesen, The Societal Cost of Environmental Regulation: Beyond Administrative Cost-Benefit Analysis, 24 ECOLOGY L.Q. 545 (1997); Lewis A. Kornhauser, Wealth Maximization, in THE NEW PALGRAVE DICTIONARY OF ECONOMICS AND THE LAW (Peter Newman ed., 1998); and Richard S. Markovits, Duncan's Do Nots: Cost-Benefit Analysis and the Determination of Legal Entitlements, 36 STAN. L. REV. 1169 (1984). There is also a burgeoning legal literature on "incommensurability," which, among other things, is typically critical of CBA. See, e.g., Cass R. Sunstein, Incommensurability and Valuation in Law, 92 MlCH. L. REV. 779 (1994); infra note 192 (responding to the incommensurability critique); see also Laurence H. Tribe, Policy Science: Analysis or Ideology?, 2 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 66 (1972) (criticizing "policy science," including CBA).
    • (1980) Hofstra L. Rev. , vol.8 , pp. 485
  • 24
    • 0003901881 scopus 로고
    • A large legal literature addresses the related question whether legal rules in general, and the common law in particular, do or should reflect efficiency concerns. See, e.g., Symposium on Efficiency as a Legal Concern, 8 HOFSTRA L. REV. 485 (1980). This literature is of limited usefulness for our purposes. It does not address CBA, for the most part, and much of it is concerned about the role of common-law judges. Otherwise it resembles earlier discussions in the economics literature. More recent treatments in the legal literature include MARK KELMAN, A GUIDE TO CRITICAL LEGAL STUDIES 114-50 (1987); David M. Driesen, The Societal Cost of Environmental Regulation: Beyond Administrative Cost-Benefit Analysis, 24 ECOLOGY L.Q. 545 (1997); Lewis A. Kornhauser, Wealth Maximization, in THE NEW PALGRAVE DICTIONARY OF ECONOMICS AND THE LAW (Peter Newman ed., 1998); and Richard S. Markovits, Duncan's Do Nots: Cost-Benefit Analysis and the Determination of Legal Entitlements, 36 STAN. L. REV. 1169 (1984). There is also a burgeoning legal literature on "incommensurability," which, among other things, is typically critical of CBA. See, e.g., Cass R. Sunstein, Incommensurability and Valuation in Law, 92 MlCH. L. REV. 779 (1994); infra note 192 (responding to the incommensurability critique); see also Laurence H. Tribe, Policy Science: Analysis or Ideology?, 2 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 66 (1972) (criticizing "policy science," including CBA).
    • (1987) A Guide to Critical Legal Studies , pp. 114-150
    • Kelman, M.1
  • 25
    • 21944456167 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The societal cost of environmental regulation: Beyond administrative cost-benefit analysis
    • A large legal literature addresses the related question whether legal rules in general, and the common law in particular, do or should reflect efficiency concerns. See, e.g., Symposium on Efficiency as a Legal Concern, 8 HOFSTRA L. REV. 485 (1980). This literature is of limited usefulness for our purposes. It does not address CBA, for the most part, and much of it is concerned about the role of common-law judges. Otherwise it resembles earlier discussions in the economics literature. More recent treatments in the legal literature include MARK KELMAN, A GUIDE TO CRITICAL LEGAL STUDIES 114-50 (1987); David M. Driesen, The Societal Cost of Environmental Regulation: Beyond Administrative Cost-Benefit Analysis, 24 ECOLOGY L.Q. 545 (1997); Lewis A. Kornhauser, Wealth Maximization, in THE NEW PALGRAVE DICTIONARY OF ECONOMICS AND THE LAW (Peter Newman ed., 1998); and Richard S. Markovits, Duncan's Do Nots: Cost-Benefit Analysis and the Determination of Legal Entitlements, 36 STAN. L. REV. 1169 (1984). There is also a burgeoning legal literature on "incommensurability," which, among other things, is typically critical of CBA. See, e.g., Cass R. Sunstein, Incommensurability and Valuation in Law, 92 MlCH. L. REV. 779 (1994); infra note 192 (responding to the incommensurability critique); see also Laurence H. Tribe, Policy Science: Analysis or Ideology?, 2 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 66 (1972) (criticizing "policy science," including CBA).
    • (1997) Ecology L.Q. , vol.24 , pp. 545
    • Driesen, D.M.1
  • 26
    • 0005830677 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wealth maximization
    • Peter Newman ed.
    • A large legal literature addresses the related question whether legal rules in general, and the common law in particular, do or should reflect efficiency concerns. See, e.g., Symposium on Efficiency as a Legal Concern, 8 HOFSTRA L. REV. 485 (1980). This literature is of limited usefulness for our purposes. It does not address CBA, for the most part, and much of it is concerned about the role of common-law judges. Otherwise it resembles earlier discussions in the economics literature. More recent treatments in the legal literature include MARK KELMAN, A GUIDE TO CRITICAL LEGAL STUDIES 114-50 (1987); David M. Driesen, The Societal Cost of Environmental Regulation: Beyond Administrative Cost-Benefit Analysis, 24 ECOLOGY L.Q. 545 (1997); Lewis A. Kornhauser, Wealth Maximization, in THE NEW PALGRAVE DICTIONARY OF ECONOMICS AND THE LAW (Peter Newman ed., 1998); and Richard S. Markovits, Duncan's Do Nots: Cost-Benefit Analysis and the Determination of Legal Entitlements, 36 STAN. L. REV. 1169 (1984). There is also a burgeoning legal literature on "incommensurability," which, among other things, is typically critical of CBA. See, e.g., Cass R. Sunstein, Incommensurability and Valuation in Law, 92 MlCH. L. REV. 779 (1994); infra note 192 (responding to the incommensurability critique); see also Laurence H. Tribe, Policy Science: Analysis or Ideology?, 2 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 66 (1972) (criticizing "policy science," including CBA).
    • (1998) The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics and the Law
    • Kornhauser, L.A.1
  • 27
    • 84927455982 scopus 로고
    • Duncan's do nots: Cost-benefit analysis and the determination of legal entitlements
    • A large legal literature addresses the related question whether legal rules in general, and the common law in particular, do or should reflect efficiency concerns. See, e.g., Symposium on Efficiency as a Legal Concern, 8 HOFSTRA L. REV. 485 (1980). This literature is of limited usefulness for our purposes. It does not address CBA, for the most part, and much of it is concerned about the role of common-law judges. Otherwise it resembles earlier discussions in the economics literature. More recent treatments in the legal literature include MARK KELMAN, A GUIDE TO CRITICAL LEGAL STUDIES 114-50 (1987); David M. Driesen, The Societal Cost of Environmental Regulation: Beyond Administrative Cost-Benefit Analysis, 24 ECOLOGY L.Q. 545 (1997); Lewis A. Kornhauser, Wealth Maximization, in THE NEW PALGRAVE DICTIONARY OF ECONOMICS AND THE LAW (Peter Newman ed., 1998); and Richard S. Markovits, Duncan's Do Nots: Cost-Benefit Analysis and the Determination of Legal Entitlements, 36 STAN. L. REV. 1169 (1984). There is also a burgeoning legal literature on "incommensurability," which, among other things, is typically critical of CBA. See, e.g., Cass R. Sunstein, Incommensurability and Valuation in Law, 92 MlCH. L. REV. 779 (1994); infra note 192 (responding to the incommensurability critique); see also Laurence H. Tribe, Policy Science: Analysis or Ideology?, 2 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 66 (1972) (criticizing "policy science," including CBA).
    • (1984) Stan. L. Rev. , vol.36 , pp. 1169
    • Markovits, R.S.1
  • 28
    • 0000247536 scopus 로고
    • Incommensurability and valuation in law
    • A large legal literature addresses the related question whether legal rules in general, and the common law in particular, do or should reflect efficiency concerns. See, e.g., Symposium on Efficiency as a Legal Concern, 8 HOFSTRA L. REV. 485 (1980). This literature is of limited usefulness for our purposes. It does not address CBA, for the most part, and much of it is concerned about the role of common-law judges. Otherwise it resembles earlier discussions in the economics literature. More recent treatments in the legal literature include MARK KELMAN, A GUIDE TO CRITICAL LEGAL STUDIES 114-50 (1987); David M. Driesen, The Societal Cost of Environmental Regulation: Beyond Administrative Cost-Benefit Analysis, 24 ECOLOGY L.Q. 545 (1997); Lewis A. Kornhauser, Wealth Maximization, in THE NEW PALGRAVE DICTIONARY OF ECONOMICS AND THE LAW (Peter Newman ed., 1998); and Richard S. Markovits, Duncan's Do Nots: Cost-Benefit Analysis and the Determination of Legal Entitlements, 36 STAN. L. REV. 1169 (1984). There is also a burgeoning legal literature on "incommensurability," which, among other things, is typically critical of CBA. See, e.g., Cass R. Sunstein, Incommensurability and Valuation in Law, 92 MlCH. L. REV. 779 (1994); infra note 192 (responding to the incommensurability critique); see also Laurence H. Tribe, Policy Science: Analysis or Ideology?, 2 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 66 (1972) (criticizing "policy science," including CBA).
    • (1994) Mlch. L. Rev. , vol.92 , pp. 779
    • Sunstein, C.R.1
  • 29
    • 84923752583 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • infra note 192
    • A large legal literature addresses the related question whether legal rules in general, and the common law in particular, do or should reflect efficiency concerns. See, e.g., Symposium on Efficiency as a Legal Concern, 8 HOFSTRA L. REV. 485 (1980). This literature is of limited usefulness for our purposes. It does not address CBA, for the most part, and much of it is concerned about the role of common-law judges. Otherwise it resembles earlier discussions in the economics literature. More recent treatments in the legal literature include MARK KELMAN, A GUIDE TO CRITICAL LEGAL STUDIES 114-50 (1987); David M. Driesen, The Societal Cost of Environmental Regulation: Beyond Administrative Cost-Benefit Analysis, 24 ECOLOGY L.Q. 545 (1997); Lewis A. Kornhauser, Wealth Maximization, in THE NEW PALGRAVE DICTIONARY OF ECONOMICS AND THE LAW (Peter Newman ed., 1998); and Richard S. Markovits, Duncan's Do Nots: Cost-Benefit Analysis and the Determination of Legal Entitlements, 36 STAN. L. REV. 1169 (1984). There is also a burgeoning legal literature on "incommensurability," which, among other things, is typically critical of CBA. See, e.g., Cass R. Sunstein, Incommensurability and Valuation in Law, 92 MlCH. L. REV. 779 (1994); infra note 192 (responding to the incommensurability critique); see also Laurence H. Tribe, Policy Science: Analysis or Ideology?, 2 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 66 (1972) (criticizing "policy science," including CBA).
  • 30
    • 85050834292 scopus 로고
    • Policy science: Analysis or ideology?
    • A large legal literature addresses the related question whether legal rules in general, and the common law in particular, do or should reflect efficiency concerns. See, e.g., Symposium on Efficiency as a Legal Concern, 8 HOFSTRA L. REV. 485 (1980). This literature is of limited usefulness for our purposes. It does not address CBA, for the most part, and much of it is concerned about the role of common-law judges. Otherwise it resembles earlier discussions in the economics literature. More recent treatments in the legal literature include MARK KELMAN, A GUIDE TO CRITICAL LEGAL STUDIES 114-50 (1987); David M. Driesen, The Societal Cost of Environmental Regulation: Beyond Administrative Cost-Benefit Analysis, 24 ECOLOGY L.Q. 545 (1997); Lewis A. Kornhauser, Wealth Maximization, in THE NEW PALGRAVE DICTIONARY OF ECONOMICS AND THE LAW (Peter Newman ed., 1998); and Richard S. Markovits, Duncan's Do Nots: Cost-Benefit Analysis and the Determination of Legal Entitlements, 36 STAN. L. REV. 1169 (1984). There is also a burgeoning legal literature on "incommensurability," which, among other things, is typically critical of CBA. See, e.g., Cass R. Sunstein, Incommensurability and Valuation in Law, 92 MlCH. L. REV. 779 (1994); infra note 192 (responding to the incommensurability critique); see also Laurence H. Tribe, Policy Science: Analysis or Ideology?, 2 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 66 (1972) (criticizing "policy science," including CBA).
    • (1972) Phil. & Pub. Aff. , vol.2 , pp. 66
    • Tribe, L.H.1
  • 31
    • 0006888996 scopus 로고
    • The justice and rationale of cost-benefit analysis
    • See, e.g., David Copp, The Justice and Rationale of Cost-Benefit Analysis, 23 THEORY & DECISION 65 (1987).
    • (1987) Theory & Decision , vol.23 , pp. 65
    • Copp, D.1
  • 32
    • 0000916518 scopus 로고
    • A review article: The case against the use of the sum of compensating variations in cost-benefit analysis
    • See, e.g., Charles Blackorby & David Donaldson, A Review Article: The Case Against the Use of the Sum of Compensating Variations in Cost-Benefit Analysis, 23 CANADIAN J. ECON. 471 (1990).
    • (1990) Canadian J. Econ. , vol.23 , pp. 471
    • Blackorby, C.1    Donaldson, D.2
  • 33
    • 0004164052 scopus 로고
    • For the sake of completeness, we should note that there is a vein of critical scholarship about CBA within the political science and policy-analysis literature. See, e.g., JAMES T. CAMPEN, BENEFIT, COST, AND BEYOND: THE POLITICAL ECONOMY OF BENEFIT-COST ANALYSIS (1986); Steven Kelman, Cost-Benefit Analysis: An Ethical Critique, REGULATION, Jan.-Feb. 1981, at 33; Lester Lave, Benefit-Cost Analysis: Do the Benefits Exceed the Costs?, in RISKS, COSTS, AND LIVES SAVED: GETTING BETTER RESULTS FROM REGULATION 104 (Robert W. Hahn ed., 1996) [hereinafter RISKS, COSTS, AND LIVES SAVED]. This literature largely overlaps in its critical thrust with the philosophical, economic, or legal scholarship already mentioned.
    • (1986) Benefit, Cost, and Beyond: The Political Economy of Benefit-Cost Analysis
    • Campen, J.T.1
  • 34
    • 0019509417 scopus 로고
    • Cost-Benefit analysis: An ethical critique
    • Jan.-Feb.
    • For the sake of completeness, we should note that there is a vein of critical scholarship about CBA within the political science and policy-analysis literature. See, e.g., JAMES T. CAMPEN, BENEFIT, COST, AND BEYOND: THE POLITICAL ECONOMY OF BENEFIT-COST ANALYSIS (1986); Steven Kelman, Cost-Benefit Analysis: An Ethical Critique, REGULATION, Jan.-Feb. 1981, at 33; Lester Lave, Benefit-Cost Analysis: Do the Benefits Exceed the Costs?, in RISKS, COSTS, AND LIVES SAVED: GETTING BETTER RESULTS FROM REGULATION 104 (Robert W. Hahn ed., 1996) [hereinafter RISKS, COSTS, AND LIVES SAVED]. This literature largely overlaps in its critical thrust with the philosophical, economic, or legal scholarship already mentioned.
    • (1981) Regulation , pp. 33
    • Kelman, S.1
  • 35
    • 0009667483 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Benefit-cost analysis: Do the benefits exceed the costs?
    • Robert W. Hahn ed., hereinafter RISKS, COSTS, AND LIVES SAVED
    • For the sake of completeness, we should note that there is a vein of critical scholarship about CBA within the political science and policy-analysis literature. See, e.g., JAMES T. CAMPEN, BENEFIT, COST, AND BEYOND: THE POLITICAL ECONOMY OF BENEFIT-COST ANALYSIS (1986); Steven Kelman, Cost-Benefit Analysis: An Ethical Critique, REGULATION, Jan.-Feb. 1981, at 33; Lester Lave, Benefit-Cost Analysis: Do the Benefits Exceed the Costs?, in RISKS, COSTS, AND LIVES SAVED: GETTING BETTER RESULTS FROM REGULATION 104 (Robert W. Hahn ed., 1996) [hereinafter RISKS, COSTS, AND LIVES SAVED]. This literature largely overlaps in its critical thrust with the philosophical, economic, or legal scholarship already mentioned.
    • (1996) Risks, Costs, and Lives Saved: Getting Better Results from Regulation , pp. 104
    • Lave, L.1
  • 36
    • 84923752571 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Corrosion Proof Fittings v. EPA, 947 F.2d 1201, 1222-23 (5th Cir. 1991)
    • This seems to have been the suspicion of the court in Corrosion Proof Fittings v. EPA, 947 F.2d 1201, 1222-23 (5th Cir. 1991), which criticized EPA for using inconsistent valuations of life across regulations.
  • 37
    • 84923752568 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 42 U.S.C. § 300g-1 (1994)
    • See 42 U.S.C. § 300g-1 (1994).
  • 38
    • 85079112275 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lead in drinking water
    • supra note 4
    • See Ronnie Levin, Lead in Drinking Water, in ECONOMIC ANALYSES AT EPA, supra note 4, at 205, 216-22.
    • Economic Analyses at EPA , pp. 205
    • Levin, R.1
  • 39
    • 84923752565 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 224-25
    • See id. at 224-25.
  • 40
    • 84923752563 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 225. For the regulation, see Drinking Water Regulations, 56 Fed. Reg. 26,460 (1991) (codified at 40 C.F.R. pts. 141-142)
    • See id. at 225. For the regulation, see Drinking Water Regulations, 56 Fed. Reg. 26,460 (1991) (codified at 40 C.F.R. pts. 141-142).
  • 41
    • 84923752562 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Levin, supra note 21, at 228-30
    • See Levin, supra note 21, at 228-30.
  • 42
    • 84923752561 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Act of June 25, 1947, ch. 125, 61 Stat. 163 (codified as amended at 7 U.S.C. §§ 136-136y (1994))
    • For the original law, see Act of June 25, 1947, ch. 125, 61 Stat. 163 (codified as amended at 7 U.S.C. §§ 136-136y (1994)).
  • 43
    • 85079109068 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Agricultural pesticides and worker protection
    • supra note 4
    • See Louis P. True, Jr., Agricultural Pesticides and Worker Protection, in ECONOMIC ANALYSES AT EPA, supra note 4, at 303, 314-15.
    • Economic Analyses at EPA , pp. 303
    • True L.P., Jr.1
  • 44
    • 84923752559 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 315-16
    • See id. at 315-16.
  • 45
    • 84923752558 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 321-22
    • See id. at 321-22.
  • 46
    • 84923752557 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 322 tbl.2
    • Id. at 322 tbl.2.
  • 47
    • 84923752556 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 323; Worker Protection Standard, 57 Fed. Reg. 38,102, 38,105 (1992) (codified at 40 C.F.R. pts. 156, 170)
    • See id. at 323; Worker Protection Standard, 57 Fed. Reg. 38,102, 38,105 (1992) (codified at 40 C.F.R. pts. 156, 170).
  • 48
    • 84923752543 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • True, supra note 26, at 325
    • See True, supra note 26, at 325.
  • 49
    • 84923752540 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 328
    • Id. at 328.
  • 50
    • 84923752537 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 324
    • See id. at 324.
  • 51
    • 84923711006 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Great Lakes water quality guidance
    • supra note 4
    • See Eloise Trabka Castillo et al., Great Lakes Water Quality Guidance, in ECONOMIC ANALYSES AT EPA, supra note 4, at 419, 438-39.
    • Economic Analyses at EPA , pp. 419
    • Trabka Castillo, E.1
  • 52
    • 85079110329 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Visibility at the Grand Canyon and the Navajo generating station
    • supra note 4
    • See Leland Deck, Visibility at the Grand Canyon and the Navajo Generating Station, in ECONOMIC ANALYSES AT EPA, supra note 4, at 267.
    • Economic Analyses at EPA , pp. 267
    • Deck, L.1
  • 53
    • 84923752535 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Morgenstern & Landy, supra note 4, at 462
    • See, e.g., Morgenstern & Landy, supra note 4, at 462.
  • 54
    • 85079111425 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lead in gasoline
    • supra note 4
    • See Albert L. Nichols, Lead in Gasoline, in ECONOMIC ANALYSES AT EPA, supra note 4, at 49, 78 ("[A] week of lead is like a millennium of radionucleotides . . . .").
    • Economic Analyses at EPA , pp. 49
    • Nichols, A.L.1
  • 55
    • 84923752533 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Exec. Order No. 12,866, 3 C.F.R. 638, 639 (1993), reprinted in 5 U.S.C. § 601 (1994); Exec. Order No. 12,291, 3 C.F.R. 127 (1981), revoked by Exec. Order No. 12,866
    • See Exec. Order No. 12,866, 3 C.F.R. 638, 639 (1993), reprinted in 5 U.S.C. § 601 (1994); Exec. Order No. 12,291, 3 C.F.R. 127 (1981), revoked by Exec. Order No. 12,866. For a more detailed account, see THOMAS O. MCGARITY, REINVENTING RATIONALITY: THE ROLE OF REGULATORY ANALYSIS IN THE FEDERAL BUREAUCRACY 271-79 (1991).
  • 57
    • 84923752531 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • American Trucking Ass'ns v. United States EPA, 175 F.3d 1027 (D.C. Cir. 1999),Id. at 1034
    • This was confirmed strikingly in the recent case American Trucking Ass'ns v. United States EPA, 175 F.3d 1027 (D.C. Cir. 1999), in which the court struck down rules governing the emission of particulate matter and ozone. The court held that EPA's construction of the Clean Air Act violated the nondelegation doctrine because it did not provide an "intelligible principle" for applying the statute. Id. at 1034. The opinion discussed a number of alternatives to EPA's unacceptable standard, and noted in passing that CBA is not available because of prior decisions construing the Clean Air Act to prohibit EPA from taking account of costs. The implication is that CBA could be the intelligible principle EPA was looking for, were it not for the fact that prior decisions had held that it was foreclosed by the statute.
  • 58
    • 0040793136 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Regulatory reform: What do the government's numbers tell us?
    • supra note 18
    • See Robert W. Hahn, Regulatory Reform: What Do the Government's Numbers Tell Us?, in RISKS, COSTS, AND LIVES SAVED, supra note 18, at 208.
    • Risks, Costs, and Lives Saved , pp. 208
    • Hahn, R.W.1
  • 59
    • 0002061405 scopus 로고
    • A review of the record
    • Nov.-Dec.
    • See, e.g., John F. Morall III, A Review of the Record, REGULATION, Nov.-Dec. 1986, at 25.
    • (1986) Regulation , pp. 25
    • Morall J.F. III1
  • 60
    • 0039623483 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Regulatory costs of mythic proportions
    • See Lisa Heinzerling, Regulatory Costs of Mythic Proportions, 107 YALE L.J. 1981, 1984-85 (1998); see also Morrison, supra note 3, 1336-37 (discussing inconsistency in dicounting across agencies); Richard L. Revesz, Environmental Regulation, Cost-Benefit Analysis, and the Discounting of Human Lives, 99 COLUM. L. REV. 941 (1999) (analyzing discounting in cost-benefit analyses of environmental regulations).
    • (1998) Yale L.J. , vol.107 , pp. 1981
    • Heinzerling, L.1
  • 61
    • 0039623483 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Morrison, supra note 3, 1336-37
    • See Lisa Heinzerling, Regulatory Costs of Mythic Proportions, 107 YALE L.J. 1981, 1984-85 (1998); see also Morrison, supra note 3, 1336-37 (discussing inconsistency in dicounting across agencies); Richard L. Revesz, Environmental Regulation, Cost-Benefit Analysis, and the Discounting of Human Lives, 99 COLUM. L. REV. 941 (1999) (analyzing discounting in cost-benefit analyses of environmental regulations).
  • 62
    • 0033127822 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Environmental regulation, cost-benefit analysis, and the discounting of human lives
    • See Lisa Heinzerling, Regulatory Costs of Mythic Proportions, 107 YALE L.J. 1981, 1984-85 (1998); see also Morrison, supra note 3, 1336-37 (discussing inconsistency in dicounting across agencies); Richard L. Revesz, Environmental Regulation, Cost-Benefit Analysis, and the Discounting of Human Lives, 99 COLUM. L. REV. 941 (1999) (analyzing discounting in cost-benefit analyses of environmental regulations).
    • (1999) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.99 , pp. 941
    • Revesz, R.L.1
  • 63
    • 84923752528 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • GENERAL ACCOUNTING OFFICE, GAO/RCED-98-142, REGULATORY REFORM: AGENCIES COULD IMPROVE DEVELOPMENT, DOCUMENTING, AND CLARITY OF REGULATORY ECONOMIC ANALYSIS (1998)
    • See GENERAL ACCOUNTING OFFICE, GAO/RCED-98-142, REGULATORY REFORM: AGENCIES COULD IMPROVE DEVELOPMENT, DOCUMENTING, AND CLARITY OF REGULATORY ECONOMIC ANALYSIS (1998).
  • 64
    • 84923752527 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MCGARITY, supra note 38, at 174-75
    • Thomas McGarity comes to similar conclusions from his study of regulations issued by EPA, and also by the Department of Agriculture, the Department of Transportation, and the Occupational Safety and Health Administration. See MCGARITY, supra note 38, at 174-75.
  • 65
    • 0004066412 scopus 로고
    • For examples of textbook treatments, see ROBIN BOADWAY & NEIL BRUCE, WELFARE ECONOMICS 26-27, 292-328 (1984); DASGUPTA & PEARCE, supra note 5; and E.J. MISHAN, COST-BENEFIT ANALYSIS (1976).
    • (1984) Welfare Economics , pp. 26-27
    • Boadway, R.1    Bruce, N.2
  • 66
    • 84923752526 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DASGUPTA & PEARCE, supra note 5
    • For examples of textbook treatments, see ROBIN BOADWAY & NEIL BRUCE, WELFARE ECONOMICS 26-27, 292-328 (1984); DASGUPTA & PEARCE, supra note 5; and E.J. MISHAN, COST-BENEFIT ANALYSIS (1976).
  • 67
    • 0004159304 scopus 로고
    • For examples of textbook treatments, see ROBIN BOADWAY & NEIL BRUCE, WELFARE ECONOMICS 26-27, 292-328 (1984); DASGUPTA & PEARCE, supra note 5; and E.J. MISHAN, COST-BENEFIT ANALYSIS (1976).
    • (1976) Cost-Benefit Analysis
    • Mishan, E.J.1
  • 68
    • 84925894745 scopus 로고
    • The ideology of the economic analysis of law
    • See C. Edwin Baker, The Ideology of the Economic Analysis of Law, 5 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 3, 47-48 (1975) (arguing that proposals based on welfare economics promote capitalist ideology and the status quo distribution of wealth rather than welfare or freedom).
    • (1975) Phil. & Pub. Aff. , vol.5 , pp. 3
    • Edwin Baker, C.1
  • 69
    • 84963090940 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A note on welfare propositions in economics
    • See Tibor de Scitovsky, A Note on Welfare Propositions in Economics, 9 REV. ECON. STUD. 77 (1941). Our example is taken from YEW-KWANG NG, WELFARE ECONOMICS: INTRODUCTION AND DEVELOPMENT OF BASIC CONCEPTS 59-66 (1980). See also BOADWAY & BRUCE, supra note 45, at 96-101.
    • (1941) Rev. Econ. Stud. , vol.9 , pp. 77
    • De Scitovsky, T.1
  • 70
    • 84963090940 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Tibor de Scitovsky, A Note on Welfare Propositions in Economics, 9 REV. ECON. STUD. 77 (1941). Our example is taken from YEW-KWANG NG, WELFARE ECONOMICS: INTRODUCTION AND DEVELOPMENT OF BASIC CONCEPTS 59-66 (1980). See also BOADWAY & BRUCE, supra note 45, at 96-101.
    • (1980) Welfare Economics: Introduction and Development of Basic Concepts , pp. 59-66
    • Ng, Y.-K.1
  • 71
    • 84963090940 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BOADWAY & BRUCE, supra note 45, at 96-101
    • See Tibor de Scitovsky, A Note on Welfare Propositions in Economics, 9 REV. ECON. STUD. 77 (1941). Our example is taken from YEW-KWANG NG, WELFARE ECONOMICS: INTRODUCTION AND DEVELOPMENT OF BASIC CONCEPTS 59-66 (1980). See also BOADWAY & BRUCE, supra note 45, at 96-101.
  • 72
    • 84923752511 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • LITTLE, supra note 10, at 106-08
    • Indeed, UPCs may cross multiple times under plausible assumptions about preferences. See LITTLE, supra note 10, at 106-08.
  • 73
    • 84923752508 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MISHAN, supra note 45
    • This is a common view. See, e.g., MISHAN, supra note 45; A. Harberger, Three Basic Postulates for Applied Welfare Economics: An Interpretive Essay, 9 J. ECON. LITERATURE 785, 785-86 (1971); Kaldor, supra note 11, at 549-52; supra text accompanying notes 7-11.
  • 74
    • 0001368993 scopus 로고
    • Three basic postulates for applied welfare economics: An interpretive essay
    • This is a common view. See, e.g., MISHAN, supra note 45; A. Harberger, Three Basic Postulates for Applied Welfare Economics: An Interpretive Essay, 9 J. ECON. LITERATURE 785, 785-86 (1971); Kaldor, supra note 11, at 549-52; supra text accompanying notes 7-11.
    • (1971) J. Econ. Literature , vol.9 , pp. 785
    • Harberger, A.1
  • 75
    • 84923752506 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kaldor, supra note 11, at 549-52
    • This is a common view. See, e.g., MISHAN, supra note 45; A. Harberger, Three Basic Postulates for Applied Welfare Economics: An Interpretive Essay, 9 J. ECON. LITERATURE 785, 785-86 (1971); Kaldor, supra note 11, at 549-52; supra text accompanying notes 7-11.
  • 76
    • 84923752504 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra text accompanying notes 7-11
    • This is a common view. See, e.g., MISHAN, supra note 45; A. Harberger, Three Basic Postulates for Applied Welfare Economics: An Interpretive Essay, 9 J. ECON. LITERATURE 785, 785-86 (1971); Kaldor, supra note 11, at 549-52; supra text accompanying notes 7-11.
  • 77
    • 0003206208 scopus 로고
    • Why the legal system is less efficient than the income tax in redistributing income
    • See Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell, Why the Legal System Is Less Efficient than the Income Tax in Redistributing Income, 23 J. LEGAL STUD. 667, 667 (1994).
    • (1994) J. Legal Stud. , vol.23 , pp. 667
    • Kaplow, L.1    Shavell, S.2
  • 78
    • 0020469501 scopus 로고
    • Cost-benefit criteria and the compensation principle in evaluating small projects
    • See Neil Bruce & Richard G. Harris, Cost-Benefit Criteria and the Compensation Principle in Evaluating Small Projects, 90 J. POL. ECON. 755 (1982).
    • (1982) J. Pol. Econ. , vol.90 , pp. 755
    • Bruce, N.1    Harris, R.G.2
  • 79
    • 84923752502 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Blackorby & Donaldson, supra note 17, at 490-91
    • For a clear statement of this point, see Blackorby & Donaldson, supra note 17, at 490-91. Some economists simply argue that a project should not be approved when approval would lead to a Scitovsky paradox. See, e.g., LITTLE, supra note 10, at 112 (requiring a distributive criterion); Scitovsky, supra note 52, at 86-87. This approach does not remove all difficulties: It can produce intransitivities or indeterminacies. See BOADWAY & BRUCE, supra note 45, at 99-100.
  • 80
    • 84923752500 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • LITTLE, supra note 10, at 112
    • For a clear statement of this point, see Blackorby & Donaldson, supra note 17, at 490-91. Some economists simply argue that a project should not be approved when approval would lead to a Scitovsky paradox. See, e.g., LITTLE, supra note 10, at 112 (requiring a distributive criterion); Scitovsky, supra note 52, at 86-87. This approach does not remove all difficulties: It can produce intransitivities or indeterminacies. See BOADWAY & BRUCE, supra note 45, at 99-100.
  • 81
    • 84923752499 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scitovsky, supra note 52, at 86-87
    • For a clear statement of this point, see Blackorby & Donaldson, supra note 17, at 490-91. Some economists simply argue that a project should not be approved when approval would lead to a Scitovsky paradox. See, e.g., LITTLE, supra note 10, at 112 (requiring a distributive criterion); Scitovsky, supra note 52, at 86-87. This approach does not remove all difficulties: It can produce intransitivities or indeterminacies. See BOADWAY & BRUCE, supra note 45, at 99-100.
  • 82
    • 84923752498 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BOADWAY & BRUCE, supra note 45, at 99-100
    • For a clear statement of this point, see Blackorby & Donaldson, supra note 17, at 490-91. Some economists simply argue that a project should not be approved when approval would lead to a Scitovsky paradox. See, e.g., LITTLE, supra note 10, at 112 (requiring a distributive criterion); Scitovsky, supra note 52, at 86-87. This approach does not remove all difficulties: It can produce intransitivities or indeterminacies. See BOADWAY & BRUCE, supra note 45, at 99-100.
  • 83
    • 0003621511 scopus 로고
    • For the sake of brevity, we do not address several other objections to CBA that have been influential in the literature. These objections include criticisms of CBA's treatment of (1) risk, (2) the discounting of future benefits, and (3) valuation of life and other hard-to-measure goods. For discussions see, for example, W. KIP VISCUSI, FATAL TRADEOFFS: PUBLIC AND PRIVATE RESPONSIBILITIES FOR RISK (1992) (valuation of life); Richard Layard & Stephen Glaister, Introduction to COST-BENEFIT ANALYSIS 1 (Richard Layard & Stephen Glaister eds., 1994) (discounting); and Herman B. Leonard & Richard J. Zeckhauser, Cost-Benefit Analysis Applied to Risks: Its Philosophy and Legitimacy, in VALUES AT RISK 31 (Douglas MacLean ed., 1986) (risk).
    • (1992) Fatal Tradeoffs: Public and Private Responsibilities for Risk
    • Kip Viscusi, W.1
  • 84
    • 0010164260 scopus 로고
    • Richard Layard & Stephen Glaister eds.
    • For the sake of brevity, we do not address several other objections to CBA that have been influential in the literature. These objections include criticisms of CBA's treatment of (1) risk, (2) the discounting of future benefits, and (3) valuation of life and other hard-to-measure goods. For discussions see, for example, W. KIP VISCUSI, FATAL TRADEOFFS: PUBLIC AND PRIVATE RESPONSIBILITIES FOR RISK (1992) (valuation of life); Richard Layard & Stephen Glaister, Introduction to COST-BENEFIT ANALYSIS 1 (Richard Layard & Stephen Glaister eds., 1994) (discounting); and Herman B. Leonard & Richard J. Zeckhauser, Cost-Benefit Analysis Applied to Risks: Its Philosophy and Legitimacy, in VALUES AT RISK 31 (Douglas MacLean ed., 1986) (risk).
    • (1994) Introduction to Cost-Benefit Analysis , pp. 1
    • Layard, R.1    Glaister, S.2
  • 85
    • 0002496585 scopus 로고
    • Cost-benefit analysis applied to risks: Its philosophy and legitimacy
    • Douglas MacLean ed.
    • For the sake of brevity, we do not address several other objections to CBA that have been influential in the literature. These objections include criticisms of CBA's treatment of (1) risk, (2) the discounting of future benefits, and (3) valuation of life and other hard-to-measure goods. For discussions see, for example, W. KIP VISCUSI, FATAL TRADEOFFS: PUBLIC AND PRIVATE RESPONSIBILITIES FOR RISK (1992) (valuation of life); Richard Layard & Stephen Glaister, Introduction to COST-BENEFIT ANALYSIS 1 (Richard Layard & Stephen Glaister eds., 1994) (discounting); and Herman B. Leonard & Richard J. Zeckhauser, Cost-Benefit Analysis Applied to Risks: Its Philosophy and Legitimacy, in VALUES AT RISK 31 (Douglas MacLean ed., 1986) (risk).
    • (1986) Values at Risk , pp. 31
    • Leonard, H.B.1    Zeckhauser, R.J.2
  • 86
    • 0003571810 scopus 로고
    • Notable exceptions include Sen and Harsanyi. See AMARTYA SEN, CHOICE, WELFARE AND MEASUREMENT 84-106 (1982); John C. Harsanyi, Game and Decision Theoretic Models in Ethics, in 1 HANDBOOK OF GAME THEORY WITH ECONOMIC APPLICATIONS 669, 703-04 (Robert J. Aumann & Sergiu Hart eds., 1992). Although both scholars appear to support CBA, at least under certain conditions, neither of them has attempted to reconcile his views with the traditional approach to CBA.
    • (1982) Choice, Welfare and Measurement , pp. 84-106
    • Sen, A.1
  • 87
    • 70350093938 scopus 로고
    • Game and decision theoretic models in ethics
    • Robert J. Aumann & Sergiu Hart eds.
    • Notable exceptions include Sen and Harsanyi. See AMARTYA SEN, CHOICE, WELFARE AND MEASUREMENT 84-106 (1982); John C. Harsanyi, Game and Decision Theoretic Models in Ethics, in 1 HANDBOOK OF GAME THEORY WITH ECONOMIC APPLICATIONS 669, 703-04 (Robert J. Aumann & Sergiu Hart eds., 1992). Although both scholars appear to support CBA, at least under certain conditions, neither of them has attempted to reconcile his views with the traditional approach to CBA.
    • (1992) Handbook of Game Theory With Economic Applications , vol.1 , pp. 669
    • Harsanyi, J.C.1
  • 88
    • 84923752497 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kaldor, supra note 11
    • This view is implicit in Kaldor, supra note 11, which argues that economists should not concern themselves with the distributive consequences of projects, since distribution is essentially a political issue. The implication is that if an "efficient" policy produces Losers, the government can compensate them if the outcome is distributively objectionable.
  • 89
    • 0039093752 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Probabilistic compensation criteria
    • See A. Mitchell Polinsky, Probabilistic Compensation Criteria, 86 Q.J. ECON. 407 (1972) (formalizing this idea, which goes back to Hicks, supra note 11).
    • (1972) Q.J. Econ. , vol.86 , pp. 407
    • Polinsky, A.M.1
  • 90
    • 0039093752 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hicks, supra note 11
    • See A. Mitchell Polinsky, Probabilistic Compensation Criteria, 86 Q.J. ECON. 407 (1972) (formalizing this idea, which goes back to Hicks, supra note 11).
  • 91
    • 84923752486 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MISHAN, supra note 45, at 393
    • See MISHAN, supra note 45, at 393.
  • 92
    • 84923752484 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Harsanyi, supra note 59, at 694-96
    • One path around this objection might be to conceptualize individuals as choosing ex ante between CBA and other procedures under a veil of ignorance - without knowing what their wealth, preferences, and welfare-affecting characteristics will turn out to be. But it is hardly clear that the rational choice, ex ante, under broad uncertainty, is to choose the world where government uses CBA. Harsanyi has argued famously that the rational choice, under such circumstances, is to choose the world where overall well-being is higher. See Harsanyi, supra note 59, at 694-96. Insofar as CBA and overall well-being diverge - as we argue they do - the introduction of uncertainty into an ex ante perspective does not secure the Pareto defense of CBA.
  • 93
    • 84923752483 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • LITTLE, supra note 10, at 120-28
    • See LITTLE, supra note 10, at 120-28.
  • 94
    • 84923752482 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MISHAN, supra note 45, at 382-402; Harberger, supra note 54, at 785. DASGUPTA & PEARCE, supra note 5, at 57
    • See, e.g., MISHAN, supra note 45, at 382-402; Harberger, supra note 54, at 785. A textbook discussion can be found in DASGUPTA & PEARCE, supra note 5, at 57.
  • 95
    • 84923752481 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • We avoid two complications. First, the Kaldor-Hicks standard actually refers loosely to two separate standards, the Kaldor standard and the Hicks standard. The choice between Kaldor and Hicks parallels the choice between CV and EV, and introduces further indeterminacy. Second, we ignore the debate about whether the hypothetical transfer should be considered costless or should be understood to require the costly redistributive instruments at the government's disposal - a debate that, in our view, is idle.
  • 96
    • 84923752480 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Blackorby & Donaldson, supra note 17, at 472
    • See, e.g., Blackorby & Donaldson, supra note 17, at 472.
  • 97
    • 84868002677 scopus 로고
    • The welfare foundations of cost-benefit analysis
    • See Robin W. Boadway, The Welfare Foundations of Cost-Benefit Analysis, 84 ECON. J. 926 (1974).
    • (1974) Econ. J. , vol.84 , pp. 926
    • Boadway, R.W.1
  • 98
    • 0001630127 scopus 로고
    • The ethical and political basis of the efficiency norm in common law adjudication
    • We are not persuaded by the argument that Kaldor-Hicks is justified on the basis of hypothetical consent. See Richard A. Posner, The Ethical and Political Basis of the Efficiency Norm in Common Law Adjudication, 8 HOFSTRA L. REV. 487 (1980). But see, e.g., Jules L. Coleman, Efficiency, Utility, and Wealth Maximization, 8 HOFSTRA L. REV. 509 (1980) (criticizing Posner). Nor are we persuaded that it is consistent with people's moral intuitions. See Richard A. Posner, Utilitarianism, Economics, and Legal Theory, 8 J. LEGAL STUD. 103 (1979). But see, e.g., Ronald M. Dworkin, Is Wealth a Value?, 9 J. LEGAL STUD. 191 (1980) (criticizing Posner). Other contributions to this debate can be found in Symposium on Efficiency as a Legal Concern, supra note 15.
    • (1980) Hofstra L. Rev. , vol.8 , pp. 487
    • Posner, R.A.1
  • 99
    • 0039349225 scopus 로고
    • Efficiency, utility, and wealth maximization
    • We are not persuaded by the argument that Kaldor-Hicks is justified on the basis of hypothetical consent. See Richard A. Posner, The Ethical and Political Basis of the Efficiency Norm in Common Law Adjudication, 8 HOFSTRA L. REV. 487 (1980). But see, e.g., Jules L. Coleman, Efficiency, Utility, and Wealth Maximization, 8 HOFSTRA L. REV. 509 (1980) (criticizing Posner). Nor are we persuaded that it is consistent with people's moral intuitions. See Richard A. Posner, Utilitarianism, Economics, and Legal Theory, 8 J. LEGAL STUD. 103 (1979). But see, e.g., Ronald M. Dworkin, Is Wealth a Value?, 9 J. LEGAL STUD. 191 (1980) (criticizing Posner). Other contributions to this debate can be found in Symposium on Efficiency as a Legal Concern, supra note 15.
    • (1980) Hofstra L. Rev. , vol.8 , pp. 509
    • Coleman, J.L.1
  • 100
    • 0011648055 scopus 로고
    • Utilitarianism, economics, and legal theory
    • We are not persuaded by the argument that Kaldor-Hicks is justified on the basis of hypothetical consent. See Richard A. Posner, The Ethical and Political Basis of the Efficiency Norm in Common Law Adjudication, 8 HOFSTRA L. REV. 487 (1980). But see, e.g., Jules L. Coleman, Efficiency, Utility, and Wealth Maximization, 8 HOFSTRA L. REV. 509 (1980) (criticizing Posner). Nor are we persuaded that it is consistent with people's moral intuitions. See Richard A. Posner, Utilitarianism, Economics, and Legal Theory, 8 J. LEGAL STUD. 103 (1979). But see, e.g., Ronald M. Dworkin, Is Wealth a Value?, 9 J. LEGAL STUD. 191 (1980) (criticizing Posner). Other contributions to this debate can be found in Symposium on Efficiency as a Legal Concern, supra note 15.
    • (1979) J. Legal Stud. , vol.8 , pp. 103
    • Posner, R.A.1
  • 101
    • 0001347311 scopus 로고
    • Is wealth a value?
    • We are not persuaded by the argument that Kaldor-Hicks is justified on the basis of hypothetical consent. See Richard A. Posner, The Ethical and Political Basis of the Efficiency Norm in Common Law Adjudication, 8 HOFSTRA L. REV. 487 (1980). But see, e.g., Jules L. Coleman, Efficiency, Utility, and Wealth Maximization, 8 HOFSTRA L. REV. 509 (1980) (criticizing Posner). Nor are we persuaded that it is consistent with people's moral intuitions. See Richard A. Posner, Utilitarianism, Economics, and Legal Theory, 8 J. LEGAL STUD. 103 (1979). But see, e.g., Ronald M. Dworkin, Is Wealth a Value?, 9 J. LEGAL STUD. 191 (1980) (criticizing Posner). Other contributions to this debate can be found in Symposium on Efficiency as a Legal Concern, supra note 15.
    • (1980) J. Legal Stud. , vol.9 , pp. 191
    • Dworkin, R.M.1
  • 102
    • 84923752479 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NASH, supra note 14, at 26-27.See id.
    • See, e.g., & NASH, supra note 14, at 26-27. Pearce and Nash do not themselves accept this approach. See id.
  • 104
    • 84923752478 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cooter & Rappoport, supra note 10, at 510-12
    • See Cooter & Rappoport, supra note 10, at 510-12.
  • 105
    • 84923752477 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DASGUPTA & PEARCE, supra note 5, at 25
    • See DASGUPTA & PEARCE, supra note 5, at 25.
  • 108
    • 0001059988 scopus 로고
    • Interpersonal comparisons of utility: A comment
    • See Lionel Robbins, Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility: A Comment, 43 ECON. J. 635 (1938). For a discussion and criticism of Robbins's position, see LITTLE, supra note 10, at 55-66. A recent article states that "most economists think interpersonal welfare comparisons are nonsense." Robert A. Pollak, Welfare Comparisons and Situation Comparisons, 50 J. ECONOMETRICS 31, 31 (1991). However, Pollak, who is himself agnostic on the matter, see id. at 39, does not supply citations, and we have not found recently published work that makes such a strong claim.
    • (1938) Econ. J. , vol.43 , pp. 635
    • Robbins, L.1
  • 109
    • 84923752476 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • LITTLE, supra note 10, at 55-66
    • See Lionel Robbins, Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility: A Comment, 43 ECON. J. 635 (1938). For a discussion and criticism of Robbins's position, see LITTLE, supra note 10, at 55-66. A recent article states that "most economists think interpersonal welfare comparisons are nonsense." Robert A. Pollak, Welfare Comparisons and Situation Comparisons, 50 J. ECONOMETRICS 31, 31 (1991). However, Pollak, who is himself agnostic on the matter, see id. at 39, does not supply citations, and we have not found recently published work that makes such a strong claim.
  • 110
    • 0010113275 scopus 로고
    • Welfare comparisons and situation comparisons
    • See Lionel Robbins, Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility: A Comment, 43 ECON. J. 635 (1938). For a discussion and criticism of Robbins's position, see LITTLE, supra note 10, at 55-66. A recent article states that "most economists think interpersonal welfare comparisons are nonsense." Robert A. Pollak, Welfare Comparisons and Situation Comparisons, 50 J. ECONOMETRICS 31, 31 (1991). However, Pollak, who is himself agnostic on the matter, see id. at 39, does not supply citations, and we have not found recently published work that makes such a strong claim.
    • (1991) J. Econometrics , vol.50 , pp. 31
    • Pollak, R.A.1
  • 111
    • 84923752475 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 39
    • See Lionel Robbins, Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility: A Comment, 43 ECON. J. 635 (1938). For a discussion and criticism of Robbins's position, see LITTLE, supra note 10, at 55-66. A recent article states that "most economists think interpersonal welfare comparisons are nonsense." Robert A. Pollak, Welfare Comparisons and Situation Comparisons, 50 J. ECONOMETRICS 31, 31 (1991). However, Pollak, who is himself agnostic on the matter, see id. at 39, does not supply citations, and we have not found recently published work that makes such a strong claim.
  • 112
    • 84923752474 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pollak, supra note 76, at 37-43
    • See Pollak, supra note 76, at 37-43, for a discussion of the difficulties.
  • 113
    • 84923752473 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • infra Subsection V.A.1
    • See infra Subsection V.A.1 (criticizing direct implementation of the criterion of overall well-being).
  • 114
    • 84923752472 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • PEARCE & NASH, supra note 14, at 27. LITTLE, supra note 10, at 120-27
    • See PEARCE & NASH, supra note 14, at 27. A powerful critique can be found in LITTLE, supra note 10, at 120-27.
  • 115
    • 84923752471 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BOADWAY & BRUCE, supra note 45, at 271-91
    • Most textbooks on CBA recommend distributive weighting and discuss various methods. See, e.g., BOADWAY & BRUCE, supra note 45, at 271-91; PEARCE & NASH, supra note 14, at 31-37; RICHARD O. ZERBE, JR. & DWIGHT D. DIVELY, BENEFIT-COST ANALYSIS IN THEORY AND PRACTICE 236-53 (1994). However, they do not show that the weighting systems are practical, and indeed many textbooks express doubts about their practicality. See, e.g., MISHAN, supra note 45; RAY, supra note 75, at 22-31; ROBERT SUGDEN & ALAN WILLIAMS, THE PRINCIPLES OF PRACTICAL COST-BENEFIT ANALYSIS 206-07 (1978). So the literature leaves one in doubt about what a proper CBA entails. As mentioned in the text, agencies do not appear to use explicit distributional weightings of the sort recommended by textbooks, although they may engage in such weightings surreptitiously or informally. See supra text accompanying note 33 (discussing pesticide regulation). Some scholars argue that the economist should not use distributive weights, but should disaggregate the costs and benefits of a project for particular groups, and allow the policy maker to decide whether its distributional consequences are acceptable. See, e.g., A.R. Prest & R. Turvey, Cost-Benefit Analysis: A Survey, 75 ECON. J. 683, 701-02 (1965).
  • 116
    • 84923752470 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • PEARCE & NASH, supra note 14, at 31-37
    • Most textbooks on CBA recommend distributive weighting and discuss various methods. See, e.g., BOADWAY & BRUCE, supra note 45, at 271-91; PEARCE & NASH, supra note 14, at 31-37; RICHARD O. ZERBE, JR. & DWIGHT D. DIVELY, BENEFIT-COST ANALYSIS IN THEORY AND PRACTICE 236-53 (1994). However, they do not show that the weighting systems are practical, and indeed many textbooks express doubts about their practicality. See, e.g., MISHAN, supra note 45; RAY, supra note 75, at 22-31; ROBERT SUGDEN & ALAN WILLIAMS, THE PRINCIPLES OF PRACTICAL COST-BENEFIT ANALYSIS 206-07 (1978). So the literature leaves one in doubt about what a proper CBA entails. As mentioned in the text, agencies do not appear to use explicit distributional weightings of the sort recommended by textbooks, although they may engage in such weightings surreptitiously or informally. See supra text accompanying note 33 (discussing pesticide regulation). Some scholars argue that the economist should not use distributive weights, but should disaggregate the costs and benefits of a project for particular groups, and allow the policy maker to decide whether its distributional consequences are acceptable. See, e.g., A.R. Prest & R. Turvey, Cost-Benefit Analysis: A Survey, 75 ECON. J. 683, 701-02 (1965).
  • 117
    • 0003683389 scopus 로고
    • Most textbooks on CBA recommend distributive weighting and discuss various methods. See, e.g., BOADWAY & BRUCE, supra note 45, at 271-91; PEARCE & NASH, supra note 14, at 31-37; RICHARD O. ZERBE, JR. & DWIGHT D. DIVELY, BENEFIT-COST ANALYSIS IN THEORY AND PRACTICE 236-53 (1994). However, they do not show that the weighting systems are practical, and indeed many textbooks express doubts about their practicality. See, e.g., MISHAN, supra note 45; RAY, supra note 75, at 22-31; ROBERT SUGDEN & ALAN WILLIAMS, THE PRINCIPLES OF PRACTICAL COST-BENEFIT ANALYSIS 206-07 (1978). So the literature leaves one in doubt about what a proper CBA entails. As mentioned in the text, agencies do not appear to use explicit distributional weightings of the sort recommended by textbooks, although they may engage in such weightings surreptitiously or informally. See supra text accompanying note 33 (discussing pesticide regulation). Some scholars argue that the economist should not use distributive weights, but should disaggregate the costs and benefits of a project for particular groups, and allow the policy maker to decide whether its distributional consequences are acceptable. See, e.g., A.R. Prest & R. Turvey, Cost-Benefit Analysis: A Survey, 75 ECON. J. 683, 701-02 (1965).
    • (1994) Benefit-Cost Analysis in Theory and Practice , pp. 236-253
    • Zerbe R.O., Jr.1    Dively, D.D.2
  • 118
    • 84923752469 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MISHAN, supra note 45
    • Most textbooks on CBA recommend distributive weighting and discuss various methods. See, e.g., BOADWAY & BRUCE, supra note 45, at 271-91; PEARCE & NASH, supra note 14, at 31-37; RICHARD O. ZERBE, JR. & DWIGHT D. DIVELY, BENEFIT-COST ANALYSIS IN THEORY AND PRACTICE 236-53 (1994). However, they do not show that the weighting systems are practical, and indeed many textbooks express doubts about their practicality. See, e.g., MISHAN, supra note 45; RAY, supra note 75, at 22-31; ROBERT SUGDEN & ALAN WILLIAMS, THE PRINCIPLES OF PRACTICAL COST-BENEFIT ANALYSIS 206-07 (1978). So the literature leaves one in doubt about what a proper CBA entails. As mentioned in the text, agencies do not appear to use explicit distributional weightings of the sort recommended by textbooks, although they may engage in such weightings surreptitiously or informally. See supra text accompanying note 33 (discussing pesticide regulation). Some scholars argue that the economist should not use distributive weights, but should disaggregate the costs and benefits of a project for particular groups, and allow the policy maker to decide whether its distributional consequences are acceptable. See, e.g., A.R. Prest & R. Turvey, Cost-Benefit Analysis: A Survey, 75 ECON. J. 683, 701-02 (1965).
  • 119
    • 84923752468 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • RAY, supra note 75, at 22-31
    • Most textbooks on CBA recommend distributive weighting and discuss various methods. See, e.g., BOADWAY & BRUCE, supra note 45, at 271-91; PEARCE & NASH, supra note 14, at 31-37; RICHARD O. ZERBE, JR. & DWIGHT D. DIVELY, BENEFIT-COST ANALYSIS IN THEORY AND PRACTICE 236-53 (1994). However, they do not show that the weighting systems are practical, and indeed many textbooks express doubts about their practicality. See, e.g., MISHAN, supra note 45; RAY, supra note 75, at 22-31; ROBERT SUGDEN & ALAN WILLIAMS, THE PRINCIPLES OF PRACTICAL COST-BENEFIT ANALYSIS 206-07 (1978). So the literature leaves one in doubt about what a proper CBA entails. As mentioned in the text, agencies do not appear to use explicit distributional weightings of the sort recommended by textbooks, although they may engage in such weightings surreptitiously or informally. See supra text accompanying note 33 (discussing pesticide regulation). Some scholars argue that the economist should not use distributive weights, but should disaggregate the costs and benefits of a project for particular groups, and allow the policy maker to decide whether its distributional consequences are acceptable. See, e.g., A.R. Prest & R. Turvey, Cost-Benefit Analysis: A Survey, 75 ECON. J. 683, 701-02 (1965).
  • 120
    • 0004232143 scopus 로고
    • Most textbooks on CBA recommend distributive weighting and discuss various methods. See, e.g., BOADWAY & BRUCE, supra note 45, at 271-91; PEARCE & NASH, supra note 14, at 31-37; RICHARD O. ZERBE, JR. & DWIGHT D. DIVELY, BENEFIT-COST ANALYSIS IN THEORY AND PRACTICE 236-53 (1994). However, they do not show that the weighting systems are practical, and indeed many textbooks express doubts about their practicality. See, e.g., MISHAN, supra note 45; RAY, supra note 75, at 22-31; ROBERT SUGDEN & ALAN WILLIAMS, THE PRINCIPLES OF PRACTICAL COST-BENEFIT ANALYSIS 206-07 (1978). So the literature leaves one in doubt about what a proper CBA entails. As mentioned in the text, agencies do not appear to use explicit distributional weightings of the sort recommended by textbooks, although they may engage in such weightings surreptitiously or informally. See supra text accompanying note 33 (discussing pesticide regulation). Some scholars argue that the economist should not use distributive weights, but should disaggregate the costs and benefits of a project for particular groups, and allow the policy maker to decide whether its distributional consequences are acceptable. See, e.g., A.R. Prest & R. Turvey, Cost-Benefit Analysis: A Survey, 75 ECON. J. 683, 701-02 (1965).
    • (1978) The Principles of Practical Cost-Benefit Analysis , pp. 206-207
    • Sugden, R.1    Williams, A.2
  • 121
    • 84923752467 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra text accompanying note 33
    • Most textbooks on CBA recommend distributive weighting and discuss various methods. See, e.g., BOADWAY & BRUCE, supra note 45, at 271-91; PEARCE & NASH, supra note 14, at 31-37; RICHARD O. ZERBE, JR. & DWIGHT D. DIVELY, BENEFIT-COST ANALYSIS IN THEORY AND PRACTICE 236-53 (1994). However, they do not show that the weighting systems are practical, and indeed many textbooks express doubts about their practicality. See, e.g., MISHAN, supra note 45; RAY, supra note 75, at 22-31; ROBERT SUGDEN & ALAN WILLIAMS, THE PRINCIPLES OF PRACTICAL COST-BENEFIT ANALYSIS 206-07 (1978). So the literature leaves one in doubt about what a proper CBA entails. As mentioned in the text, agencies do not appear to use explicit distributional weightings of the sort recommended by textbooks, although they may engage in such weightings surreptitiously or informally. See supra text accompanying note 33 (discussing pesticide regulation). Some scholars argue that the economist should not use distributive weights, but should disaggregate the costs and benefits of a project for particular groups, and allow the policy maker to decide whether its distributional consequences are acceptable. See, e.g., A.R. Prest & R. Turvey, Cost-Benefit Analysis: A Survey, 75 ECON. J. 683, 701-02 (1965).
  • 122
    • 84993845040 scopus 로고
    • Cost-benefit analysis: A survey
    • Most textbooks on CBA recommend distributive weighting and discuss various methods. See, e.g., BOADWAY & BRUCE, supra note 45, at 271-91; PEARCE & NASH, supra note 14, at 31-37; RICHARD O. ZERBE, JR. & DWIGHT D. DIVELY, BENEFIT-COST ANALYSIS IN THEORY AND PRACTICE 236-53 (1994). However, they do not show that the weighting systems are practical, and indeed many textbooks express doubts about their practicality. See, e.g., MISHAN, supra note 45; RAY, supra note 75, at 22-31; ROBERT SUGDEN & ALAN WILLIAMS, THE PRINCIPLES OF PRACTICAL COST-BENEFIT ANALYSIS 206-07 (1978). So the literature leaves one in doubt about what a proper CBA entails. As mentioned in the text, agencies do not appear to use explicit distributional weightings of the sort recommended by textbooks, although they may engage in such weightings surreptitiously or informally. See supra text accompanying note 33 (discussing pesticide regulation). Some scholars argue that the economist should not use distributive weights, but should disaggregate the costs and benefits of a project for particular groups, and allow the policy maker to decide whether its distributional consequences are acceptable. See, e.g., A.R. Prest & R. Turvey, Cost-Benefit Analysis: A Survey, 75 ECON. J. 683, 701-02 (1965).
    • (1965) Econ. J. , vol.75 , pp. 683
    • Prest, A.R.1    Turvey, R.2
  • 123
    • 0040872007 scopus 로고
    • Cost-benefit analysis: Bastard science? and/or insidious poison in the body politick?
    • See Alan Williams, Cost-Benefit Analysis: Bastard Science? and/or Insidious Poison in the Body Politick?, 1 J. PUB. ECON. 199 (1972). Some scholars have proposed alternatives. See, e.g., G. Munda et al., Information Precision andMulticriteria Evaluation Methods, in EFFICIENCY IN THE PUBLIC SECTOR: THE THEORY AND PRACTICE OF COST-BENEFIT ANALYSIS 43 (Alan Williams & Emilio Giardina eds., 1993); V. Kerry Smith, A Conceptual Overview of the Foundations of Benefit-Cost Analysis, in BENEFITS ASSESSMENT: THE STATE OF THE ART 13, 27-31 (Judith D. Bentkover et al. eds., 1986). We discuss these and other alternatives in Part V.
    • (1972) J. Pub. Econ. , vol.1 , pp. 199
    • Williams, A.1
  • 124
    • 0040872007 scopus 로고
    • Information precision andmulticriteria evaluation methods
    • Alan Williams & Emilio Giardina eds.
    • See Alan Williams, Cost-Benefit Analysis: Bastard Science? and/or Insidious Poison in the Body Politick?, 1 J. PUB. ECON. 199 (1972). Some scholars have proposed alternatives. See, e.g., G. Munda et al., Information Precision andMulticriteria Evaluation Methods, in EFFICIENCY IN THE PUBLIC SECTOR: THE THEORY AND PRACTICE OF COST-BENEFIT ANALYSIS 43 (Alan Williams & Emilio Giardina eds., 1993); V. Kerry Smith, A Conceptual Overview of the Foundations of Benefit-Cost Analysis, in BENEFITS ASSESSMENT: THE STATE OF THE ART 13, 27-31 (Judith D. Bentkover et al. eds., 1986). We discuss these and other alternatives in Part V.
    • (1993) Efficiency in the Public Sector: The Theory and Practice of Cost-Benefit Analysis , pp. 43
    • Munda, G.1
  • 125
    • 0040872007 scopus 로고
    • A conceptual overview of the foundations of benefit-cost analysis
    • Judith D. Bentkover et al. eds.
    • See Alan Williams, Cost-Benefit Analysis: Bastard Science? and/or Insidious Poison in the Body Politick?, 1 J. PUB. ECON. 199 (1972). Some scholars have proposed alternatives. See, e.g., G. Munda et al., Information Precision andMulticriteria Evaluation Methods, in EFFICIENCY IN THE PUBLIC SECTOR: THE THEORY AND PRACTICE OF COST-BENEFIT ANALYSIS 43 (Alan Williams & Emilio Giardina eds., 1993); V. Kerry Smith, A Conceptual Overview of the Foundations of Benefit-Cost Analysis, in BENEFITS ASSESSMENT: THE STATE OF THE ART 13, 27-31 (Judith D. Bentkover et al. eds., 1986). We discuss these and other alternatives in Part V.
    • (1986) Benefits Assessment: The State of the Art , pp. 13
    • Kerry Smith, V.1
  • 126
    • 84923752466 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra text accompanying note 50
    • See supra text accompanying note 50.
  • 127
    • 84923752465 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra Subsections III.B.1, III.B.2
    • See supra Subsections III.B.1, III.B.2.
  • 128
    • 84923752464 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 66 and accompanying text
    • See supra note 66 and accompanying text.
  • 129
    • 84923752463 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Actually, this is just a first cut at our position. More precisely, CVs should be defined either as welfare equivalents or as WTP/WTA to the extent the latter measure tracks welfare equivalents with sufficient accuracy and is cheaper, more transparent, more reliably implemented, and so forth. See infra text accompanying note 154.
  • 130
    • 0040277733 scopus 로고
    • For overviews of the philosophical literature on well-being, see JAMES GRIFFIN, WELLBEING 7-72 (1986); DEREK PARFIT, REASONS AND PERSONS 493-502 (1984 );
    • (1986) Wellbeing , pp. 7-72
    • Griffin, J.1
  • 131
    • 0003740191 scopus 로고
    • For overviews of the philosophical literature on well-being, see JAMES GRIFFIN, WELLBEING 7-72 (1986); DEREK PARFIT, REASONS AND PERSONS 493-502 (1984 );
    • (1984) Reasons and Persons , pp. 493-502
    • Parfit, D.1
  • 132
    • 84923752462 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SUMNER, supra note 71, at 45-137.SUMNER, supra note 71, at 91
    • and SUMNER, supra note 71, at 45-137. Sometimes the trichotomy of welfare theories is drawn a bit differently from the way we have just drawn it: as a trichotomy of desire-based theories, objective-list theories, and mental state theories, with the last category in turn given two subcategories, (1) hedonic theories and (2) mental state theories (such as Sidgwick's) that define welfare in terms of desirable mental states rather than positive feeling tones. See SUMNER, supra note 71, at 91 (discussing Sidgwick's view). Since we are trying to draw a sharp distinction between welfare theories that rest upon desires and theories that do not, we include the Sidgwickian variant within our category of desire-based theories.
  • 133
    • 0346408753 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Comparison and the justification of choice
    • On the importance of comparisons for justified choice, see generally Ruth Chang, Comparison and the Justification of Choice, 146 U. PA. L. REV. 1569 (1998).
    • (1998) U. Pa. L. Rev. , vol.146 , pp. 1569
    • Chang, R.1
  • 134
    • 0003529325 scopus 로고
    • What these goods are is a matter for further debate, within the family of objective-list theories, but typically they are taken to include such goods as knowledge, personal relationships, play, the experience of beauty, the accomplishment of worthy goals, and physical fitness. For some specific lists of objective values, see JOHN FINNIS, NATURAL LAW AND NATURAL RIGHTS 85-90 (1980); GRIFFIN, supra note 86, at 67-68; and GEORGE SHER, BEYOND NEUTRALITY: PERFECTIONISM AND POLITICS 199-201 (1997).
    • (1980) Natural Law and Natural Rights , pp. 85-90
    • Finnis, J.1
  • 135
    • 84923752461 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • GRIFFIN, supra note 86, at 67-68
    • What these goods are is a matter for further debate, within the family of objective-list theories, but typically they are taken to include such goods as knowledge, personal relationships, play, the experience of beauty, the accomplishment of worthy goals, and physical fitness. For some specific lists of objective values, see JOHN FINNIS, NATURAL LAW AND NATURAL RIGHTS 85-90 (1980); GRIFFIN, supra note 86, at 67-68; and GEORGE SHER, BEYOND NEUTRALITY: PERFECTIONISM AND POLITICS 199-201 (1997).
  • 136
    • 0004088293 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What these goods are is a matter for further debate, within the family of objective-list theories, but typically they are taken to include such goods as knowledge, personal relationships, play, the experience of beauty, the accomplishment of worthy goals, and physical fitness. For some specific lists of objective values, see JOHN FINNIS, NATURAL LAW AND NATURAL RIGHTS 85-90 (1980); GRIFFIN, supra note 86, at 67-68; and GEORGE SHER, BEYOND NEUTRALITY: PERFECTIONISM AND POLITICS 199-201 (1997).
    • (1997) Beyond Neutrality: Perfectionism and Politics , pp. 199-201
    • Sher, G.1
  • 137
    • 0004206653 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On prepositional attitudes, see JAEGWON KIM, PHILOSOPHY OF MIND 13-14 (1996); on the "valencing" of prepositional attitudes, see RICHARD B. BRANDT, A THEORY OF THE GOOD AND THE RIGHT 24-45 (1998). By contrast with Brandt, however, we think that valence need not be defined in terms of choice. For example, I might retrospectively endorse some state of affairs involving myself, even though I did not choose it, and even though I endorse it just because it happened to me serendipitously rather than through my choice. Cf. SUMNER, supra note 71, at 122-37 (discussing retrospective endorsement).
    • (1996) Philosophy of Mind , pp. 13-14
    • Kim, J.1
  • 138
    • 0003794871 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On prepositional attitudes, see JAEGWON KIM, PHILOSOPHY OF MIND 13-14 (1996); on the "valencing" of prepositional attitudes, see RICHARD B. BRANDT, A THEORY OF THE GOOD AND THE RIGHT 24-45 (1998). By contrast with Brandt, however, we think that valence need not be defined in terms of choice. For example, I might retrospectively endorse some state of affairs involving myself, even though I did not choose it, and even though I endorse it just because it happened to me serendipitously rather than through my choice. Cf. SUMNER, supra note 71, at 122-37 (discussing retrospective endorsement).
    • (1998) A Theory of the Good and the Right , pp. 24-45
    • Brandt, R.B.1
  • 139
    • 84923752460 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SUMNER, supra note 71, at 122-37
    • On prepositional attitudes, see JAEGWON KIM, PHILOSOPHY OF MIND 13-14 (1996); on the "valencing" of prepositional attitudes, see RICHARD B. BRANDT, A THEORY OF THE GOOD AND THE RIGHT 24-45 (1998). By contrast with Brandt, however, we think that valence need not be defined in terms of choice. For example, I might retrospectively endorse some state of affairs involving myself, even though I did not choose it, and even though I endorse it just because it happened to me serendipitously rather than through my choice. Cf. SUMNER, supra note 71, at 122-37 (discussing retrospective endorsement).
  • 140
    • 0003868287 scopus 로고
    • On the nature of preference, see, for example, S.L. HURLEY, NATURAL REASONS: PERSONALITY AND POLITY 55-83 (1989); Richard J. Arneson, Liberalism, Distributive Subjectivism, and Equal Opportunity for Welfare, 19 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 158, 161-64 (1990); and Arthur Ripstein, Preference, in VALUE, WELFARE AND MORALITY 93-111 (R.G. Frey & Christopher W. Morris eds., 1993). A recent anthology of technically sophisticated papers is PREFERENCES (Christoph Fehige & Ulla Wessels eds., 1998). For a full analysis of the related concept of a "want," see ROBERT AUDI, ACTION, INTENTION, AND REASON 35-55 (1993).
    • (1989) Natural Reasons: Personality and Polity , pp. 55-83
    • Hurley, S.L.1
  • 141
    • 0000357472 scopus 로고
    • Liberalism, distributive subjectivism, and equal opportunity for welfare
    • On the nature of preference, see, for example, S.L. HURLEY, NATURAL REASONS: PERSONALITY AND POLITY 55-83 (1989); Richard J. Arneson, Liberalism, Distributive Subjectivism, and Equal Opportunity for Welfare, 19 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 158, 161-64 (1990); and Arthur Ripstein, Preference, in VALUE, WELFARE AND MORALITY 93-111 (R.G. Frey & Christopher W. Morris eds., 1993). A recent anthology of technically sophisticated papers is PREFERENCES (Christoph Fehige & Ulla Wessels eds., 1998). For a full analysis of the related concept of a "want," see ROBERT AUDI, ACTION, INTENTION, AND REASON 35-55 (1993).
    • (1990) Phil. & Pub. Aff. , vol.19 , pp. 158
    • Arneson, R.J.1
  • 142
    • 0040872010 scopus 로고
    • Preference
    • R.G. Frey & Christopher W. Morris eds.
    • On the nature of preference, see, for example, S.L. HURLEY, NATURAL REASONS: PERSONALITY AND POLITY 55-83 (1989); Richard J. Arneson, Liberalism, Distributive Subjectivism, and Equal Opportunity for Welfare, 19 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 158, 161-64 (1990); and Arthur Ripstein, Preference, in VALUE, WELFARE AND MORALITY 93-111 (R.G. Frey & Christopher W. Morris eds., 1993). A recent anthology of technically sophisticated papers is PREFERENCES (Christoph Fehige & Ulla Wessels eds., 1998). For a full analysis of the related concept of a "want," see ROBERT AUDI, ACTION, INTENTION, AND REASON 35-55 (1993).
    • (1993) Value, Welfare and Morality , pp. 93-111
    • Ripstein, A.1
  • 143
    • 0342854895 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the nature of preference, see, for example, S.L. HURLEY, NATURAL REASONS: PERSONALITY AND POLITY 55-83 (1989); Richard J. Arneson, Liberalism, Distributive Subjectivism, and Equal Opportunity for Welfare, 19 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 158, 161-64 (1990); and Arthur Ripstein, Preference, in VALUE, WELFARE AND MORALITY 93-111 (R.G. Frey & Christopher W. Morris eds., 1993). A recent anthology of technically sophisticated papers is PREFERENCES (Christoph Fehige & Ulla Wessels eds., 1998). For a full analysis of the related concept of a "want," see ROBERT AUDI, ACTION, INTENTION, AND REASON 35-55 (1993).
    • (1998) Preferences
    • Fehige, C.1    Wessels, U.2
  • 144
    • 0004281265 scopus 로고
    • On the nature of preference, see, for example, S.L. HURLEY, NATURAL REASONS: PERSONALITY AND POLITY 55-83 (1989); Richard J. Arneson, Liberalism, Distributive Subjectivism, and Equal Opportunity for Welfare, 19 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 158, 161-64 (1990); and Arthur Ripstein, Preference, in VALUE, WELFARE AND MORALITY 93-111 (R.G. Frey & Christopher W. Morris eds., 1993). A recent anthology of technically sophisticated papers is PREFERENCES (Christoph Fehige & Ulla Wessels eds., 1998). For a full analysis of the related concept of a "want," see ROBERT AUDI, ACTION, INTENTION, AND REASON 35-55 (1993).
    • (1993) Action, Intention, and Reason , pp. 35-55
    • Audi, R.1
  • 145
    • 84923752459 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DASGUPTA & PEARCE, supra note 5, at 22-25
    • See DASGUPTA & PEARCE, supra note 5, at 22-25, for a discussion. Perhaps a more plausible formulation is one that defines preference as a disposition to choose (A prefers P over S if and only if A chooses X rather than Y when A believes that X leads to P and Y leads to S, and no other preferences are in play) rather than as an actual choice (A prefers P over S if and only if A chooses P over S). See, e.g., DANIEL M. HAUSMAN & MICHAEL S. MCPHERSON, ECONOMIC ANALYSIS AND MORAL PHILOSOPHY 28 (1996) ("We regard Q's preference ranking as a subjective state of Q that, along with Q's beliefs, explains her choices."). This is not the same as saying that Q's preferences are "revealed" in her choices, since, for example, Q's beliefs may be mistaken. See id. (criticizing the revealed preference view). For our purposes, we need not decide whether the conceptual connection between preference and choice is properly captured by a "revealed preference" view or in some other way.
  • 146
    • 0003460641 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See DASGUPTA & PEARCE, supra note 5, at 22-25, for a discussion. Perhaps a more plausible formulation is one that defines preference as a disposition to choose (A prefers P over S if and only if A chooses X rather than Y when A believes that X leads to P and Y leads to S, and no other preferences are in play) rather than as an actual choice (A prefers P over S if and only if A chooses P over S). See, e.g., DANIEL M. HAUSMAN & MICHAEL S. MCPHERSON, ECONOMIC ANALYSIS AND MORAL PHILOSOPHY 28 (1996) ("We regard Q's preference ranking as a subjective state of Q that, along with Q's beliefs, explains her choices."). This is not the same as saying that Q's preferences are "revealed" in her choices, since, for example, Q's beliefs may be mistaken. See id. (criticizing the revealed preference view). For our purposes, we need not decide whether the conceptual connection between preference and choice is properly captured by a "revealed preference" view or in some other way.
    • (1996) Economic Analysis and Moral Philosophy , pp. 28
    • Hausman, D.M.1    Mcpherson, M.S.2
  • 147
    • 0011350479 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MISHAN. supra note 45
    • For a general presentation of the standard, economic view of well-being, see MISHAN. supra note 45. Critical discussions of the link within welfare economics between preference and well-being are provided by HAUSMAN & MCPHERSON supra note 91, at 71-83; SUMNER, supra note 71, at 113-22; and Tyler Cowen, The Scope and Limits of Preference Sovereignty; 9 ECON. & PHIL. 253 (1993). We do not necessarily endorse all of the criticisms voiced by these authors, but instead focus specifically on the point that well-being is not equivalent to the satisfaction of unrestricted preferences. See infra text accompanying notes 93-94, 98.
  • 148
    • 0011350479 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HAUSMAN & MCPHERSON supra note 91, at 71-83; SUMNER, supra note 71, at 113-22
    • For a general presentation of the standard, economic view of well-being, see MISHAN. supra note 45. Critical discussions of the link within welfare economics between preference and well-being are provided by HAUSMAN & MCPHERSON supra note 91, at 71-83; SUMNER, supra note 71, at 113-22; and Tyler Cowen, The Scope and Limits of Preference Sovereignty; 9 ECON. & PHIL. 253 (1993). We do not necessarily endorse all of the criticisms voiced by these authors, but instead focus specifically on the point that well-being is not equivalent to the satisfaction of unrestricted preferences. See infra text accompanying notes 93-94, 98.
  • 149
    • 0011350479 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The scope and limits of preference sovereignty
    • For a general presentation of the standard, economic view of well-being, see MISHAN. supra note 45. Critical discussions of the link within welfare economics between preference and well-being are provided by HAUSMAN & MCPHERSON supra note 91, at 71-83; SUMNER, supra note 71, at 113-22; and Tyler Cowen, The Scope and Limits of Preference Sovereignty; 9 ECON. & PHIL. 253 (1993). We do not necessarily endorse all of the criticisms voiced by these authors, but instead focus specifically on the point that well-being is not equivalent to the satisfaction of unrestricted preferences. See infra text accompanying notes 93-94, 98.
    • (1993) Econ. & Phil. , vol.9 , pp. 253
    • Cowen, T.1
  • 150
    • 0011350479 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • infra text accompanying notes 93-94, 98
    • For a general presentation of the standard, economic view of well-being, see MISHAN. supra note 45. Critical discussions of the link within welfare economics between preference and well-being are provided by HAUSMAN & MCPHERSON supra note 91, at 71-83; SUMNER, supra note 71, at 113-22; and Tyler Cowen, The Scope and Limits of Preference Sovereignty; 9 ECON. & PHIL. 253 (1993). We do not necessarily endorse all of the criticisms voiced by these authors, but instead focus specifically on the point that well-being is not equivalent to the satisfaction of unrestricted preferences. See infra text accompanying notes 93-94, 98.
  • 151
    • 84923752455 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SUMNER, supra note 71, at 134-35
    • We are hardly the first to articulate the point that the satisfaction of unrestricted preferences should not be conflated with welfare. Others who have made the same point include SUMNER, supra note 71, at 134-35; John Broome, Choice and Value in Economics, 30 OXFORD ECON. PAPERS 313 (1978); Allan Gibbard, Interpersonal Comparisons: Preference, Good, and the Intrinsic Reward of a Life, in FOUNDATIONS OF SOCIAL CHOICE THEORY 165, 173-75 (Jon Elster & Aanund Hylland eds., 1986); Mark Carl Overvold, Self-interest and the Concept of Self-Sacrifice, 10 CANADIAN J. PHIL. 105 (1980); Amartya K. Sen, Rational Fools: A Critique of the Behavioral Foundations of Economic Theory, 6 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 317 (1977); and David Sobel, On the Subjectivity of Welfare, 107 ETHICS 501 (1997). See also David Sobel, Well-Being as the Object of Moral Consideration, 14 ECON. & PHIL. 249, 250 (1998) [hereinafter Sobel Well-Being] ("The second [preference-based] model [of well-being], now dominant in philosophy . . . typically allows that some of one's informed preferences, for example, moral preferences, have no special connection to one's well-being." (citations omitted)).
  • 152
    • 0011763042 scopus 로고
    • Choice and value in economics
    • We are hardly the first to articulate the point that the satisfaction of unrestricted preferences should not be conflated with welfare. Others who have made the same point include SUMNER, supra note 71, at 134-35; John Broome, Choice and Value in Economics, 30 OXFORD ECON. PAPERS 313 (1978); Allan Gibbard, Interpersonal Comparisons: Preference, Good, and the Intrinsic Reward of a Life, in FOUNDATIONS OF SOCIAL CHOICE THEORY 165, 173-75 (Jon Elster & Aanund Hylland eds., 1986); Mark Carl Overvold, Self-interest and the Concept of Self-Sacrifice, 10 CANADIAN J. PHIL. 105 (1980); Amartya K. Sen, Rational Fools: A Critique of the Behavioral Foundations of Economic Theory, 6 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 317 (1977); and David Sobel, On the Subjectivity of Welfare, 107 ETHICS 501 (1997). See also David Sobel, Well-Being as the Object of Moral Consideration, 14 ECON. & PHIL. 249, 250 (1998) [hereinafter Sobel Well-Being] ("The second [preference-based] model [of well-being], now dominant in philosophy . . . typically allows that some of one's informed preferences, for example, moral preferences, have no special connection to one's well-being." (citations omitted)).
    • (1978) Oxford Econ. Papers , vol.30 , pp. 313
    • Broome, J.1
  • 153
    • 0011961849 scopus 로고
    • Interpersonal comparisons: Preference, good, and the intrinsic reward of a life
    • Jon Elster & Aanund Hylland eds.
    • We are hardly the first to articulate the point that the satisfaction of unrestricted preferences should not be conflated with welfare. Others who have made the same point include SUMNER, supra note 71, at 134-35; John Broome, Choice and Value in Economics, 30 OXFORD ECON. PAPERS 313 (1978); Allan Gibbard, Interpersonal Comparisons: Preference, Good, and the Intrinsic Reward of a Life, in FOUNDATIONS OF SOCIAL CHOICE THEORY 165, 173-75 (Jon Elster & Aanund Hylland eds., 1986); Mark Carl Overvold, Self-interest and the Concept of Self-Sacrifice, 10 CANADIAN J. PHIL. 105 (1980); Amartya K. Sen, Rational Fools: A Critique of the Behavioral Foundations of Economic Theory, 6 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 317 (1977); and David Sobel, On the Subjectivity of Welfare, 107 ETHICS 501 (1997). See also David Sobel, Well-Being as the Object of Moral Consideration, 14 ECON. & PHIL. 249, 250 (1998) [hereinafter Sobel Well-Being] ("The second [preference-based] model [of well-being], now dominant in philosophy . . . typically allows that some of one's informed preferences, for example, moral preferences, have no special connection to one's well-being." (citations omitted)).
    • (1986) Foundations of Social Choice Theory , pp. 165
    • Gibbard, A.1
  • 154
    • 0039685899 scopus 로고
    • Self-interest and the concept of self-sacrifice
    • We are hardly the first to articulate the point that the satisfaction of unrestricted preferences should not be conflated with welfare. Others who have made the same point include SUMNER, supra note 71, at 134-35; John Broome, Choice and Value in Economics, 30 OXFORD ECON. PAPERS 313 (1978); Allan Gibbard, Interpersonal Comparisons: Preference, Good, and the Intrinsic Reward of a Life, in FOUNDATIONS OF SOCIAL CHOICE THEORY 165, 173-75 (Jon Elster & Aanund Hylland eds., 1986); Mark Carl Overvold, Self-interest and the Concept of Self-Sacrifice, 10 CANADIAN J. PHIL. 105 (1980); Amartya K. Sen, Rational Fools: A Critique of the Behavioral Foundations of Economic Theory, 6 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 317 (1977); and David Sobel, On the Subjectivity of Welfare, 107 ETHICS 501 (1997). See also David Sobel, Well-Being as the Object of Moral Consideration, 14 ECON. & PHIL. 249, 250 (1998) [hereinafter Sobel Well-Being] ("The second [preference-based] model [of well-being], now dominant in philosophy . . . typically allows that some of one's informed preferences, for example, moral preferences, have no special connection to one's well-being." (citations omitted)).
    • (1980) Canadian J. Phil. , vol.10 , pp. 105
    • Overvold, M.C.1
  • 155
    • 79959682688 scopus 로고
    • Rational fools: A critique of the behavioral foundations of economic theory
    • We are hardly the first to articulate the point that the satisfaction of unrestricted preferences should not be conflated with welfare. Others who have made the same point include SUMNER, supra note 71, at 134-35; John Broome, Choice and Value in Economics, 30 OXFORD ECON. PAPERS 313 (1978); Allan Gibbard, Interpersonal Comparisons: Preference, Good, and the Intrinsic Reward of a Life, in FOUNDATIONS OF SOCIAL CHOICE THEORY 165, 173-75 (Jon Elster & Aanund Hylland eds., 1986); Mark Carl Overvold, Self-interest and the Concept of Self-Sacrifice, 10 CANADIAN J. PHIL. 105 (1980); Amartya K. Sen, Rational Fools: A Critique of the Behavioral Foundations of Economic Theory, 6 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 317 (1977); and David Sobel, On the Subjectivity of Welfare, 107 ETHICS 501 (1997). See also David Sobel, Well-Being as the Object of Moral Consideration, 14 ECON. & PHIL. 249, 250 (1998) [hereinafter Sobel Well-Being] ("The second [preference-based] model [of well-being], now dominant in philosophy . . . typically allows that some of one's informed preferences, for example, moral preferences, have no special connection to one's well-being." (citations omitted)).
    • (1977) Phil. & Pub. Aff. , vol.6 , pp. 317
    • Sen, A.K.1
  • 156
    • 84937265229 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the subjectivity of welfare
    • We are hardly the first to articulate the point that the satisfaction of unrestricted preferences should not be conflated with welfare. Others who have made the same point include SUMNER, supra note 71, at 134-35; John Broome, Choice and Value in Economics, 30 OXFORD ECON. PAPERS 313 (1978); Allan Gibbard, Interpersonal Comparisons: Preference, Good, and the Intrinsic Reward of a Life, in FOUNDATIONS OF SOCIAL CHOICE THEORY 165, 173-75 (Jon Elster & Aanund Hylland eds., 1986); Mark Carl Overvold, Self-interest and the Concept of Self-Sacrifice, 10 CANADIAN J. PHIL. 105 (1980); Amartya K. Sen, Rational Fools: A Critique of the Behavioral Foundations of Economic Theory, 6 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 317 (1977); and David Sobel, On the Subjectivity of Welfare, 107 ETHICS 501 (1997). See also David Sobel, Well-Being as the Object of Moral Consideration, 14 ECON. & PHIL. 249, 250 (1998) [hereinafter Sobel Well-Being] ("The second [preference-based] model [of well-being], now dominant in philosophy . . . typically allows that some of one's informed preferences, for example, moral preferences, have no special connection to one's well-being." (citations omitted)).
    • (1997) Ethics , vol.107 , pp. 501
    • Sobel, D.1
  • 157
    • 79956660320 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Well-being as the object of moral consideration
    • We are hardly the first to articulate the point that the satisfaction of unrestricted preferences should not be conflated with welfare. Others who have made the same point include SUMNER, supra note 71, at 134-35; John Broome, Choice and Value in Economics, 30 OXFORD ECON. PAPERS 313 (1978); Allan Gibbard, Interpersonal Comparisons: Preference, Good, and the Intrinsic Reward of a Life, in FOUNDATIONS OF SOCIAL CHOICE THEORY 165, 173-75 (Jon Elster & Aanund Hylland eds., 1986); Mark Carl Overvold, Self-interest and the Concept of Self-Sacrifice, 10 CANADIAN J. PHIL. 105 (1980); Amartya K. Sen, Rational Fools: A Critique of the Behavioral Foundations of Economic Theory, 6 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 317 (1977); and David Sobel, On the Subjectivity of Welfare, 107 ETHICS 501 (1997). See also David Sobel, Well-Being as the Object of Moral Consideration, 14 ECON. & PHIL. 249, 250 (1998) [hereinafter Sobel Well-Being] ("The second [preference-based] model [of well-being], now dominant in philosophy . . . typically allows that some of one's informed preferences, for example, moral preferences, have no special connection to one's well-being." (citations omitted)).
    • (1998) Econ. & Phil. , vol.14 , pp. 249
    • Sobel, D.1
  • 158
    • 0039685908 scopus 로고
    • Morality, self-interest, and reasons for being moral
    • As Overvold puts it: [S]uppose we accept the prevailing account of self-interest or personal welfare. Then we will have to say that any act that is voluntary and informed is thereby in the agent's self-interest. But self-sacrifice requires that the act be voluntary, informed, and contrary to the agent's self-interest. Thus accepting the prevailing account of self-interest makes the concept of self-sacrifice incoherent by making it logically impossible that there are ever genuine instances of self-sacrifice. Mark Carl Overvold, Morality, Self-Interest, and Reasons for Being Moral, 44 PHIL. & PHENOMENOLOGICAL RES. 493, 499 (1984).
    • (1984) Phil. & Phenomenological Res. , vol.44 , pp. 493
    • Overvold, M.C.1
  • 159
    • 84923752454 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SUMNER, supra note 71, at 106; see also KIM, supra note 89, at 13
    • SUMNER, supra note 71, at 106; see also KIM, supra note 89, at 13 (distinguishing between "sensations" and "prepositional attitudes").
  • 160
    • 84923752453 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The sophisticated hedonist might try to solve these counterexamples by specifying mixes of pleasures so as to take account of considerations of balance, excessiveness, and so forth: Three parts gustatory pleasure and three parts sexual arousal are better than ten parts gustatory pleasure and two parts sexual arousal. Yet this more refined hedonic theory is still open to the objection that it fails to respect A's point of view. Imagine that A better realizes the specified mix of pleasures in the project world, but he nonetheless prefers, judges, endorses, and otherwise desires the status quo. (This is a conceptual possibility because, again, "pleasures" are nonpropositional. For the pleasures that go into a hedonic theory, it is no entailment of A's experiencing such pleasures that he also desire them.) In this sort of case, we propose, A is not better off with the project. Perhaps he would be better off if the project also brought with it an adaptive desire, a desire for the project-induced mix of pleasures; but if it does not, then the project does not improve A's welfare. At most he is comparatively neither better nor worse off, as between the project and status quo.
  • 161
    • 84923752452 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • By "project," here, we mean technically a complete world history rather than merely a discrete state of affairs that is one part of a complete world history. If project is taken in the first sense, then it is plausible that A's actually desiring the project over the status quo, at some point in time, is a necessary condition for the project to benefit her. Alternatively, if "project" is understood as a discrete state of affairs that is one component of a larger world history, then our claim concerns intrinsic rather than instrumental benefit: It is a necessary condition for A to be intrinsically benefited by a project (thus understood) that she actually desire the project at some point in time. (By contrast, discrete projects can be of instrumental benefit even without a matching desire by A. For example the discrete project of depriving A of a poison pill, which she desires because she mistakenly believes it to be a vitamin tablet that will bring her health, can benefit A by leading to the satisfaction of her desire for health even if she never comes to realize that the pill was poisonous.)
  • 162
    • 84923752451 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Overvold, supra note 94, at 499-501
    • Mark Overvold has made a sustained attempt to provide a noncircular account of the restriction. See Overvold, supra note 94, at 499-501; Mark Carl Overvold, Self-interest and Getting What You Want, in THE LIMITS OF UTILITARIANISM 186 (Harlan Miller & William Williams eds., 1982); Overvold, supra note 93, at 117-18 n.10. It is far from clear whether he succeeds. See Sobel, Well-Being, supra note 93, at 266-69 (criticizing Overvold's account).
  • 163
    • 0039093684 scopus 로고
    • Self-interest and getting what you want
    • Harlan Miller & William Williams eds.
    • Mark Overvold has made a sustained attempt to provide a noncircular account of the restriction. See Overvold, supra note 94, at 499-501; Mark Carl Overvold, Self-interest and Getting What You Want, in THE LIMITS OF UTILITARIANISM 186 (Harlan Miller & William Williams eds., 1982); Overvold, supra note 93, at 117-18 n.10. It is far from clear whether he succeeds. See Sobel, Well-Being, supra note 93, at 266-69 (criticizing Overvold's account).
    • (1982) The Limits of Utilitarianism , pp. 186
    • Overvold, M.C.1
  • 164
    • 84923752450 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Overvold, supra note 93, at 117-18 n.10
    • Mark Overvold has made a sustained attempt to provide a noncircular account of the restriction. See Overvold, supra note 94, at 499-501; Mark Carl Overvold, Self-interest and Getting What You Want, in THE LIMITS OF UTILITARIANISM 186 (Harlan Miller & William Williams eds., 1982); Overvold, supra note 93, at 117-18 n.10. It is far from clear whether he succeeds. See Sobel, Well-Being, supra note 93, at 266-69 (criticizing Overvold's account).
  • 165
    • 84923752449 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sobel, Well-Being, supra note 93, at 266-69
    • Mark Overvold has made a sustained attempt to provide a noncircular account of the restriction. See Overvold, supra note 94, at 499-501; Mark Carl Overvold, Self-interest and Getting What You Want, in THE LIMITS OF UTILITARIANISM 186 (Harlan Miller & William Williams eds., 1982); Overvold, supra note 93, at 117-18 n.10. It is far from clear whether he succeeds. See Sobel, Well-Being, supra note 93, at 266-69 (criticizing Overvold's account).
  • 166
    • 84923752448 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SUMNER, supra note 71, at 128
    • See SUMNER, supra note 71, at 128 (discussing the importance of experience).
  • 167
    • 84937310574 scopus 로고
    • Full information accounts of well-being
    • n.15
    • See David Sobel, Full Information Accounts of Well-Being, 104 ETHICS 784, 792 n.15 (1994) (noting that "[a] truly impressive and diverse list of contemporary ethicists have found [a] full information [desire-based] account of well-being congenial," and citing Brandt, Hare, Griffin, Rawls, Gauthier, Darwall, and Harsanyi).
    • (1994) Ethics , vol.104 , pp. 784
    • Sobel, D.1
  • 168
    • 84923752447 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SUMNER, supra note 71, at 138-56
    • See SUMNER, supra note 71, at 138-56 (discussing the importance of affect).
  • 169
    • 84923752446 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 163-64
    • Cf. id. at 163-64 (discussing, but not endorsing, a hybrid view that includes objective values).
  • 170
    • 84923752445 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 47
    • See supra note 47 and accompanying text (providing traditional definitions of CV and WTP/WTA).
  • 171
    • 84923752444 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra text accompanying notes 71-78
    • See supra text accompanying notes 71-78.
  • 173
    • 0040872005 scopus 로고
    • The impossibility of interpersonal utility comparisons
    • See. e.g., Daniel Hausman, The Impossibility of Interpersonal Utility Comparisons, 104 MIND 473, 475-77 (1995).
    • (1995) Mind , vol.104 , pp. 473
    • Hausman, D.1
  • 174
    • 84923752443 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra text accompanying notes 73-74
    • See supra text accompanying notes 73-74.
  • 175
    • 84923752442 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hausman, supra note 106, at 474. Id. at 489
    • Hausman, supra note 106, at 474. For "interpersonal comparisons are an ineliminable part of human life." Id. at 489; see also John C. Harsanyi, Morality and the Theory of Rational Behaviour, in UTILITARIANISM AND BEYOND 39, 49 (Amartya Sen & Bernard Williams eds., 1982) ("In everyday life we make, or at least attempt to make, interpersonal utility comparisons all the time."); Ruth Weintraub, Do Utility Comparisons Pose a Problem?, 92 PHIL. STUD. 307, 307 (1998) ("[C]an we find ourselves being persuaded of the ethical need to compare utilities of different individuals, yet unable to do so because the comparisons cannot be warranted? I shall argue that the problem cannot arise: no plausible moral principle will invoke magnitudes which are inscrutable.").
  • 176
    • 0003214842 scopus 로고
    • Morality and the theory of rational behaviour
    • Amartya Sen & Bernard Williams eds.
    • Hausman, supra note 106, at 474. For "interpersonal comparisons are an ineliminable part of human life." Id. at 489; see also John C. Harsanyi, Morality and the Theory of Rational Behaviour, in UTILITARIANISM AND BEYOND 39, 49 (Amartya Sen & Bernard Williams eds., 1982) ("In everyday life we make, or at least attempt to make, interpersonal utility comparisons all the time."); Ruth Weintraub, Do Utility Comparisons Pose a Problem?, 92 PHIL. STUD. 307, 307 (1998) ("[C]an we find ourselves being persuaded of the ethical need to compare utilities of different individuals, yet unable to do so because the comparisons cannot be warranted? I shall argue that the problem cannot arise: no plausible moral principle will invoke magnitudes which are inscrutable.").
    • (1982) Utilitarianism and Beyond , pp. 39
    • Harsanyi, J.C.1
  • 177
    • 54649084615 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Do utility comparisons pose a problem?
    • Hausman, supra note 106, at 474. For "interpersonal comparisons are an ineliminable part of human life." Id. at 489; see also John C. Harsanyi, Morality and the Theory of Rational Behaviour, in UTILITARIANISM AND BEYOND 39, 49 (Amartya Sen & Bernard Williams eds., 1982) ("In everyday life we make, or at least attempt to make, interpersonal utility comparisons all the time."); Ruth Weintraub, Do Utility Comparisons Pose a Problem?, 92 PHIL. STUD. 307, 307 (1998) ("[C]an we find ourselves being persuaded of the ethical need to compare utilities of different individuals, yet unable to do so because the comparisons cannot be warranted? I shall argue that the problem cannot arise: no plausible moral principle will invoke magnitudes which are inscrutable.").
    • (1998) Phil. Stud. , vol.92 , pp. 307
    • Weintraub, R.1
  • 178
    • 84923752441 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • More precisely, the agency would need to sort all persons into Winners, Losers, and Neutrals, where Neutrals are those who are neither better off nor worse off. This in turn means either that they are precisely as well off in both world-states or that they are incomparably well off as between the states. Neutrals would then be ignored at the second stage of the interpersonal comparison. The possibility of Neutrals is a technical issue that need not be further discussed here because that possibility does not bear on the key problem of interpersonal comparisons, namely, how to compare Winners' gains to Losers' losses.
  • 179
    • 0040720539 scopus 로고
    • Interpersonal comparisons of utility: Why and how they are and should be made
    • Jon Elster & John E. Roemer eds.
    • See generally Peter J. Hammond, Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility: Why and How They Are and Should Be Made, in INTERPERSONAL COMPARISONS OF WELL-BEING 200 (Jon Elster & John E. Roemer eds., 1991); Hausman, supra note 106.
    • (1991) Interpersonal Comparisons of Well-being , pp. 200
    • Hammond, P.J.1
  • 180
    • 84923752440 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hausman, supra note 106
    • See generally Peter J. Hammond, Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility: Why and How They Are and Should Be Made, in INTERPERSONAL COMPARISONS OF WELL-BEING 200 (Jon Elster & John E. Roemer eds., 1991); Hausman, supra note 106.
  • 181
    • 84923752439 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hausman, supra note 106
    • For an overview of such constructs, see Hausman, supra note 106.
  • 182
    • 84923752438 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Harsanyi, supra note 108
    • l, is quite simple: Determine the numerical difference between the two outcomes on each person's zero-one index, and aggregate. Isbell's proposal is discussed in Hammond, supra note 110, at 215-16; Hausman, supra note 106, at 479-82; and Weintraub, supra note 108, at 317-118. See also 1 KEN BINMORE, GAME THEORY AND THE SOCIAL CONTRACT: PLAYING FAIR 282-96 (1994) (providing an overview of interpersonal comparisons of utility).
  • 183
    • 0002789980 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A reconsideration of the Harsanyi-Sen debate on utilitarianism
    • supra note 110
    • l, is quite simple: Determine the numerical difference between the two outcomes on each person's zero-one index, and aggregate. Isbell's proposal is discussed in Hammond, supra note 110, at 215-16; Hausman, supra note 106, at 479-82; and Weintraub, supra note 108, at 317-118. See also 1 KEN BINMORE, GAME THEORY AND THE SOCIAL CONTRACT: PLAYING FAIR 282-96 (1994) (providing an overview of interpersonal comparisons of utility).
    • Interpersonal Comparisons of Well-being , pp. 255
    • Weymark, J.A.1
  • 184
    • 84923752437 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hammond, supra note 110, at 215-16; Hausman, supra note 106, at 479-82; and Weintraub, supra note 108, at 317-118
    • l, is quite simple: Determine the numerical difference between the two outcomes on each person's zero-one index, and aggregate. Isbell's proposal is discussed in Hammond, supra note 110, at 215-16; Hausman, supra note 106, at 479-82; and Weintraub, supra note 108, at 317-118. See also 1 KEN BINMORE, GAME THEORY AND THE SOCIAL CONTRACT: PLAYING FAIR 282-96 (1994) (providing an overview of interpersonal comparisons of utility).
  • 185
    • 84923703326 scopus 로고
    • l, is quite simple: Determine the numerical difference between the two outcomes on each person's zero-one index, and aggregate. Isbell's proposal is discussed in Hammond, supra note 110, at 215-16; Hausman, supra note 106, at 479-82; and Weintraub, supra note 108, at 317-118. See also 1 KEN BINMORE, GAME THEORY AND THE SOCIAL CONTRACT: PLAYING FAIR 282-96 (1994) (providing an overview of interpersonal comparisons of utility).
    • (1994) Ken Binmore, Game Theory and the Social Contract: Playing Fair , vol.1 , pp. 282-296
  • 187
    • 84923752347 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hausman, supra note 106, at 477-78
    • l with certainty.
  • 188
    • 84923752344 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • GRIFFIN, supra note 86, at 116-17
    • GRIFFIN, supra note 86, at 116-17 (emphasis added). For a similar construct, albeit within the context of a more objectivist view of well-being, see Thomas M. Scanlon, The Moral Basis of Interpersonal Comparisons, in INTERPERSONAL COMPARISONS OF WELL-BEING, supra note 110, at 17, 39-44.
  • 189
    • 0002622280 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The moral basis of interpersonal comparisons
    • supra note 110
    • GRIFFIN, supra note 86, at 116-17 (emphasis added). For a similar construct, albeit within the context of a more objectivist view of well-being, see Thomas M. Scanlon, The Moral Basis of Interpersonal Comparisons, in INTERPERSONAL COMPARISONS OF WELL-BEING, supra note 110, at 17, 39-44.
    • Interpersonal Comparisons of Well-being , pp. 17
    • Scanlon, T.M.1
  • 190
    • 84923752341 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • GRIFFIN, supra note 86, at 7-72; SUMNER, supra note 71, at 122-37
    • See GRIFFIN, supra note 86, at 7-72; SUMNER, supra note 71, at 122-37 (identifying Griffin as a prominent informed-desire theorist and discussing Griffin's views).
  • 191
    • 84923752339 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Neutrals, see supra note 109
    • On Neutrals, see supra note 109.
  • 193
    • 84923752337 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 64-70
    • See id. at 64-70 (distinguishing between moral reasons and moral requirements).
  • 195
    • 0003701071 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The constraint against killing, as proposed by the libertarian, is not a consequentialist requirement, because it violates the constraint even if that violation serves to prevent more killings. For an accessible overview of the consequentialism/deontology distinction, see SHELLY KAGAN, NORMATIVE ETHICS 59-77 (1998). For a more technical discussion, see, for example, David McNaughton & Piers Rawling, Agent-Relativity and the Doing-Happening Distinction, 63 PHIL. STUD. 167 (1991).
    • (1998) Normative Ethics , pp. 59-77
    • Kagan, S.1
  • 196
    • 0039093654 scopus 로고
    • Agent-relativity and the doing-happening distinction
    • The constraint against killing, as proposed by the libertarian, is not a consequentialist requirement, because it violates the constraint even if that violation serves to prevent more killings. For an accessible overview of the consequentialism/deontology distinction, see SHELLY KAGAN, NORMATIVE ETHICS 59-77 (1998). For a more technical discussion, see, for example, David McNaughton & Piers Rawling, Agent-Relativity and the Doing-Happening Distinction, 63 PHIL. STUD. 167 (1991).
    • (1991) Phil. Stud. , vol.63 , pp. 167
    • McNaughton, D.1    Rawling, P.2
  • 197
    • 84923752336 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KAGAN, supra note 117, at 16
    • See KAGAN, supra note 117, at 16.
  • 198
    • 84923752334 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Why does it matter that minimalism is inconsistent with the scope of modern government? Arguably, this bolsters the intuitive case against minimalism: It is counterintuitive that the scope of modern government would need to change radically, as minimalism requires. Further, the inconsistency between minimalism and the scope of modern government means that anyone who launches a critique of CBA without advocating a radical change in the scope of modern government cannot persuasively rely upon minimalism as the basis for his critique.
  • 199
    • 0030530625 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The deontology of negligence
    • Cf. Heidi M. Hurd, The Deontology of Negligence, 76 B.U. L. REV. 249, 262-66 (1996) (arguing that risk imposition is not deontologically wrongful).
    • (1996) B.U. L. Rev. , vol.76 , pp. 249
    • Hurd, H.M.1
  • 200
    • 84923752333 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NOZICK, supra note 119, at 119
    • Cf. NOZICK, supra note 119, at 119 (arguing that in the case of a "dominant protective association" - a contractual association for protective services in the state of nature, with a monopoly element - "[t]he dominant protective association . . . is morally required to compensate for the disadvantages it imposes upon those it prohibits from self-help activities against its clients").
  • 201
    • 0040871981 scopus 로고
    • rev. ed.
    • The distinction between consequentialism and utilitarianism has been drawn very clearly in the recent philosophical literature. See, e.g., SAMUEL SCHEFFLER, THE REJECTION OF CONSEQUENTIALISM 1-40 (rev. ed. 1994). The position that overall well-being lacks even moral relevance, let alone moral decisiveness, is the limiting point of nonutilitarian consequentialism.
    • (1994) The Rejection of Consequentialism , pp. 1-40
    • Scheffler, S.1
  • 203
    • 0000791830 scopus 로고
    • What is equality? Part 2: Equality of resources
    • See Ronald Dworkin, What is Equality? Part 2: Equality of Resources, 10 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 283 (1981).
    • (1981) Phil. & Pub. Aff. , vol.10 , pp. 283
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 204
    • 84937266898 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Where the action is: On the site of distributive justice
    • See G.A. Cohen, Where the Action Is: On the Site of Distributive Justice, 26 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 3 (1997).
    • (1997) Phil. & Pub. Aff. , vol.26 , pp. 3
    • Cohen, G.A.1
  • 205
    • 0004295144 scopus 로고
    • See LARRY S. TEMKIN, INEQUALITY (1993). Strictly speaking, Temkin is not an egalitarian theorist, but rather someone who has developed a very rich account of what equality involves See id. at 5 (denying an intention to defend or attack the ideal of equality).
    • (1993) Inequality
    • Temkin, L.S.1
  • 206
    • 84923752332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 5
    • See LARRY S. TEMKIN, INEQUALITY (1993). Strictly speaking, Temkin is not an egalitarian theorist, but rather someone who has developed a very rich account of what equality involves See id. at 5 (denying an intention to defend or attack the ideal of equality).
  • 207
    • 0003895407 scopus 로고
    • See PHILIPPE VAN PARIJS, REAL FREEDOM FOR ALL: WHAT (IF ANYTHING) CAN JUSTIFY CAPITALISM? (1995). These modern philosophical egalitarians might not describe themselves as consequentialists, but our use of the term "consequentialist" is a fairly thin one. An egalitarian counts as proposing a "consequentialist" standard of equality, in our usage, if that standard has agent-neutral force within the egalitarian's theory - if all agents have (to the same extent) a moral reason to promote the standard. This is in contrast to deontological or agent-relative maxims, which have differential force for the particular referenced agent as opposed to others. (The deontologist thinks you have greater reason that you not directly and intentionally kill than I have that you not directly and intentionally kill.) See KAGAN, supra note 120, at 48-59 (discussing equality as one factor that arguably goes to the moral goodness of outcomes); supra note 120 (citing sources discussing the consequentialism/deontology distinction). A parallel point holds for our description below of the resourcist as proposing a kind of consequentialist standard.
    • (1995) Real Freedom for All: What (If Anything) Can Justify Capitalism?
    • Van Parijs, P.1
  • 208
    • 84923752331 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KAGAN, supra note 120, at 48-59
    • See PHILIPPE VAN PARIJS, REAL FREEDOM FOR ALL: WHAT (IF ANYTHING) CAN JUSTIFY CAPITALISM? (1995). These modern philosophical egalitarians might not describe themselves as consequentialists, but our use of the term "consequentialist" is a fairly thin one. An egalitarian counts as proposing a "consequentialist" standard of equality, in our usage, if that standard has agent-neutral force within the egalitarian's theory - if all agents have (to the same extent) a moral reason to promote the standard. This is in contrast to deontological or agent-relative maxims, which have differential force for the particular referenced agent as opposed to others. (The deontologist thinks you have greater reason that you not directly and intentionally kill than I have that you not directly and intentionally kill.) See KAGAN, supra note 120, at 48-59 (discussing equality as one factor that arguably goes to the moral goodness of outcomes); supra note 120 (citing sources discussing the consequentialism/deontology distinction). A parallel point holds for our description below of the resourcist as proposing a kind of consequentialist standard.
  • 209
    • 84923752318 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 120
    • See PHILIPPE VAN PARIJS, REAL FREEDOM FOR ALL: WHAT (IF ANYTHING) CAN JUSTIFY CAPITALISM? (1995). These modern philosophical egalitarians might not describe themselves as consequentialists, but our use of the term "consequentialist" is a fairly thin one. An egalitarian counts as proposing a "consequentialist" standard of equality, in our usage, if that standard has agent-neutral force within the egalitarian's theory - if all agents have (to the same extent) a moral reason to promote the standard. This is in contrast to deontological or agent-relative maxims, which have differential force for the particular referenced agent as opposed to others. (The deontologist thinks you have greater reason that you not directly and intentionally kill than I have that you not directly and intentionally kill.) See KAGAN, supra note 120, at 48-59 (discussing equality as one factor that arguably goes to the moral goodness of outcomes); supra note 120 (citing sources discussing the consequentialism/deontology distinction). A parallel point holds for our description below of the resourcist as proposing a kind of consequentialist standard.
  • 210
    • 84923752315 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, supra note 127
    • See Dworkin, supra note 127.
  • 211
    • 84923752312 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scanlon, supra note 114
    • See Scanlon, supra note 114.
  • 212
    • 0039572864 scopus 로고
    • Autonomy and deontology
    • Samuel Scheffler ed.
    • See Thomas Nagel, Autonomy and Deontology, in CONSEQUENTIALISM AND ITS CRITICS 142, 145-50 (Samuel Scheffler ed., 1988).
    • (1988) Consequentialism and Its Critics , pp. 142
    • Nagel, T.1
  • 213
    • 0001639815 scopus 로고
    • Equality of what? On welfare, goods and capabilities
    • Martha Nussbaum & Amartya Sen eds.
    • See G.A. Cohen, Equality of What? On Welfare, Goods and Capabilities, in THE QUALITY OF LIFE 9, 18-28 (Martha Nussbaum & Amartya Sen eds., 1993).
    • (1993) The Quality of Life , pp. 9
    • Cohen, G.A.1
  • 214
    • 0004274013 scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., AMARTYA SEN, INEQUALITY REEXAMINED 39-55 (1992); Amartya Sen, Capability and Well-Being, in THE QUALITY OF LIFE, supra note 134, at 30, 30-42.
    • (1992) Inequality Reexamined , pp. 39-55
    • Sen, A.1
  • 215
    • 0003110930 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Capability and well-being
    • supra note 134
    • See, e.g., AMARTYA SEN, INEQUALITY REEXAMINED 39-55 (1992); Amartya Sen, Capability and Well-Being, in THE QUALITY OF LIFE, supra note 134, at 30, 30-42.
    • The Quality of Life , pp. 30
    • Sen, A.1
  • 216
    • 84923752310 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • To be sure, some of the just-cited resourcists are also egalitarians, but it is conceptually possible, and for our purposes useful, to distinguish between the resourcist and egalitarian elements in philosophical critiques of welfarism and utilitarianism.
  • 217
    • 84923752308 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nagel, supra note 133, at 145-46
    • Nagel, supra note 133, at 145-46.
  • 218
    • 84923752306 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • To put the point another way: On the resourcist view, the fact that a project increases overall well-being without increasing (or otherwise properly distributing) the specified prerequisites or elements of well-being, gives government no reason whatsoever to approve the project.
  • 219
    • 84923752304 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • We say "roughly" because the project might cause such a large improvement to A's welfare and such a large setback to B's that A is better off than B in the project world, and by an amount sufficient to make the distribution of welfare in the project world less equal than the distribution in the status quo.
  • 220
    • 0004282258 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One standard variant on maximin is so-called "leximin," which compares P and S by comparing, first, the welfare level of the worst-off group in each world, then the welfare level of the next worst-off group, and so on. See, e.g., JOHN E. ROEMER, THEORIES OF DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE 136-37 (1996). For the leximin theorist, as for the maximin theorist, the goodness or badness of a project that increases overall well-being by benefiting A more than it harms B will depend upon the welfare levels of A and B.
    • (1996) Theories of Distributive Justice , pp. 136-137
    • Roemer, J.E.1
  • 221
    • 84923752303 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 122
    • This inconsistency is relevant, here, for the same reasons that the inconsistency between minimalism and the scope of modern government is relevant. See supra note 122.
  • 223
    • 84923752302 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KAGAN, supra note 120, at 25-69
    • See, e.g., KAGAN, supra note 120, at 25-69.
  • 224
    • 84923752301 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • GRIFFIN, supra note 86, at 45
    • GRIFFIN, supra note 86, at 45.
  • 225
    • 84923752289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sobel, Well-Being, supra note 93
    • Libertarianism, egalitarianism, and resourcism strike us as the most salient ways to contest the moral relevance of overall well-being, given the state of the modern philosophical literature, but they are not the only ways. Two other possible lines of attack that should be mentioned here are (1) the view that the overall satisfaction of persons' interests or goals (taken to be distinct from persons' well-being) is what bears the moral weight typically given to overall well-being, see, e.g., Sobel, Well-Being, supra note 93, and (2) the view that overall well-being must be refined to incorporate considerations of desert - for example, that a welfare loss to a person has no moral bearing if he deserves or is responsible for it, see FRED FELDMAN, UTILITARIANISM, HEDONISM AND DESERT 151-92 (1997). For criticism of the focus on interests or goals as opposed to welfare, see Andrew Moore & Roger Crisp, Welfarism in Moral Theory, 74 AUSTRALASIAN J. PHIL. 598 (1996). For criticism of the idea of desert-adjusted welfare, see Ingmar Persson, Feldman's Justicized Act Utilitarianism, 9 RATIO 39 (1996).
  • 226
    • 0039093592 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Libertarianism, egalitarianism, and resourcism strike us as the most salient ways to contest the moral relevance of overall well-being, given the state of the modern philosophical literature, but they are not the only ways. Two other possible lines of attack that should be mentioned here are (1) the view that the overall satisfaction of persons' interests or goals (taken to be distinct from persons' well-being) is what bears the moral weight typically given to overall well-being, see, e.g., Sobel, Well-Being, supra note 93, and (2) the view that overall well-being must be refined to incorporate considerations of desert - for example, that a welfare loss to a person has no moral bearing if he deserves or is responsible for it, see FRED FELDMAN, UTILITARIANISM, HEDONISM AND DESERT 151-92 (1997). For criticism of the focus on interests or goals as opposed to welfare, see Andrew Moore & Roger Crisp, Welfarism in Moral Theory, 74 AUSTRALASIAN J. PHIL. 598 (1996). For criticism of the idea of desert-adjusted welfare, see Ingmar Persson, Feldman's Justicized Act Utilitarianism, 9 RATIO 39 (1996).
    • (1997) Utilitarianism, Hedonism and Desert , pp. 151-192
    • Feldman, F.1
  • 227
    • 0039093658 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Welfarism in moral theory
    • Libertarianism, egalitarianism, and resourcism strike us as the most salient ways to contest the moral relevance of overall well-being, given the state of the modern philosophical literature, but they are not the only ways. Two other possible lines of attack that should be mentioned here are (1) the view that the overall satisfaction of persons' interests or goals (taken to be distinct from persons' well-being) is what bears the moral weight typically given to overall well-being, see, e.g., Sobel, Well-Being, supra note 93, and (2) the view that overall well-being must be refined to incorporate considerations of desert - for example, that a welfare loss to a person has no moral bearing if he deserves or is responsible for it, see FRED FELDMAN, UTILITARIANISM, HEDONISM AND DESERT 151-92 (1997). For criticism of the focus on interests or goals as opposed to welfare, see Andrew Moore & Roger Crisp, Welfarism in Moral Theory, 74 AUSTRALASIAN J. PHIL. 598 (1996). For criticism of the idea of desert-adjusted welfare, see Ingmar Persson, Feldman's Justicized Act Utilitarianism, 9 RATIO 39 (1996).
    • (1996) Australasian J. Phil. , vol.74 , pp. 598
    • Moore, A.1    Crisp, R.2
  • 228
    • 0040871989 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Feldman's justicized act utilitarianism
    • Libertarianism, egalitarianism, and resourcism strike us as the most salient ways to contest the moral relevance of overall well-being, given the state of the modern philosophical literature, but they are not the only ways. Two other possible lines of attack that should be mentioned here are (1) the view that the overall satisfaction of persons' interests or goals (taken to be distinct from persons' well-being) is what bears the moral weight typically given to overall well-being, see, e.g., Sobel, Well-Being, supra note 93, and (2) the view that overall well-being must be refined to incorporate considerations of desert - for example, that a welfare loss to a person has no moral bearing if he deserves or is responsible for it, see FRED FELDMAN, UTILITARIANISM, HEDONISM AND DESERT 151-92 (1997). For criticism of the focus on interests or goals as opposed to welfare, see Andrew Moore & Roger Crisp, Welfarism in Moral Theory, 74 AUSTRALASIAN J. PHIL. 598 (1996). For criticism of the idea of desert-adjusted welfare, see Ingmar Persson, Feldman's Justicized Act Utilitarianism, 9 RATIO 39 (1996).
    • (1996) Ratio , vol.9 , pp. 39
    • Persson, I.1
  • 230
    • 21144468370 scopus 로고
    • Rules versus standards: An economic analysis
    • See generally Louis Kaplow, Rules Versus Standards: An Economic Analysis, 42 DUKE L.J. 557 (1992) (analyzing whether legal commands should be promulgated as rules or standards).
    • (1992) Duke L.J. , vol.42 , pp. 557
    • Kaplow, L.1
  • 231
    • 84923752286 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BOADWAY & BRUCE, supra note 45, at 262-72
    • See, e.g., BOADWAY & BRUCE, supra note 45, at 262-72; JULES L. COLEMAN, MARKETS, MORALS AND THE LAW 95-132 (1988); HAUSMAN & MCPHERSON, supra note 91, at 93-99; Blackorby & Donaldson, supra note 17; Copp, supra note 16; Dworkin, supra note 69.
  • 232
    • 0004230791 scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., BOADWAY & BRUCE, supra note 45, at 262-72; JULES L. COLEMAN, MARKETS, MORALS AND THE LAW 95-132 (1988); HAUSMAN & MCPHERSON, supra note 91, at 93-99; Blackorby & Donaldson, supra note 17; Copp, supra note 16; Dworkin, supra note 69.
    • (1988) Markets, Morals and the Law , pp. 95-132
    • Coleman, J.L.1
  • 233
    • 84923752283 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HAUSMAN & MCPHERSON, supra note 91, at 93-99; Blackorby & Donaldson, supra note 17; Copp, supra note 16; Dworkin, supra note 69
    • See, e.g., BOADWAY & BRUCE, supra note 45, at 262-72; JULES L. COLEMAN, MARKETS, MORALS AND THE LAW 95-132 (1988); HAUSMAN & MCPHERSON, supra note 91, at 93-99; Blackorby & Donaldson, supra note 17; Copp, supra note 16; Dworkin, supra note 69.
  • 234
    • 84974487449 scopus 로고
    • The moral justification of benefit/cost analysis
    • That CBA is best understood as a decision procedure is emphasized in Donald C. Hubin, The Moral Justification of Benefit/Cost Analysis, 10 ECON. & PHIL. 169 (1994).
    • (1994) Econ. & Phil. , vol.10 , pp. 169
    • Hubin, D.C.1
  • 235
    • 84923752281 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra text accompanying note 34
    • See supra text accompanying note 34.
  • 236
    • 84923752279 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 47 and accompanying text
    • See supra note 47 and accompanying text.
  • 237
    • 0003490113 scopus 로고
    • Indeed, this phenomenon - the deviation between a person's traditionally defined CV and her true welfare equivalent for a project that has a small welfare effect on her, but to which she has a strong moral objection - seems to arise frequently in agency practice. Respondents often react to contingent valuation surveys in ways that seem to reflect their moral views, for example, by providing a very large or small number, or by simply refusing to answer. See ROBERT CAMERON MITCHELL & RICHARD T. CARSON, USING SURVEYS To VALUE PUBLIC GOODS: THE CONTINGENT VALUATION METHOD 30-38 (1989).
    • (1989) Using Surveys to Value Public Goods: The Contingent Valuation Method , pp. 30-38
    • Mitchell, R.C.1    Carson, R.T.2
  • 238
    • 0009067665 scopus 로고
    • Legal paternalism
    • Rolf Sartorius ed.
    • Cf. Joel Feinberg, Legal Paternalism, in PATERNALISM 3 (Rolf Sartorius ed., 1983) (conceding that paternalist interventions can improve welfare, but arguing against paternalism on grounds of autonomy).
    • (1983) Paternalism , pp. 3
    • Feinberg, J.1
  • 239
    • 0000296056 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Benefit-cost analysis as a source of information about welfare
    • supra note 14
    • As we briefly mentioned in the text above and in the introduction to this Part, the concept of welfare equivalent is an appropriate foundation for CBA even if the correct theory of well-being turns out to be a hedonic or objective-list theory. CBA is no less coherent on these theories than on a desire-based theory, although of course the specific amount of A's welfare equivalent will be different. On a hedonic theory, this amount is the amount that, paid to or by A in the project world, makes her level of hedonic tone there just the same as in the status quo; on an objective-list theory, it is the amount that, paid to or by A in the project world, makes her overall realization of objective welfarist values just the same as in the status quo world. Because we argue in this Article for a desire-based view of well-being, however, we do not further pursue this point. The point that A's WTP/WTA is distinct from her welfare equivalent has been made by Peter Railton Benefit-Cost Analysis as a Source of Information About Welfare, in VALUING HEALTH RISKS, COSTS, AND BENEFITS FOR ENVIRONMENTAL DECISION MAKING, supra note 14, at 55, 71-72. Cf. Pildes & Sunstein, supra note 2, at 82 ("[C]ontingent valuation methods still suffer from the private/public valuation distinction. What people would be willing to pay to eliminate certain conditions for themselves, and how they think public resources should be allocated, remain distinct questions. . . . [W]hat matters are lay valuations about public choices, not those about self-regarding, private choices."). We disagree: In the context of determining overall welfare, what matters are just the "self-regarding," that is, welfare-relevant, impacts of the project on each person. For a recent contribution on all-things-considered versus self-regarding ("citizen" versus "consumer") preferences, with citations to the literature, see Daphna Lewinsohn-Zamir, Consumer Preferences, Citizen Preferences, and the Provision of Public Goods, 108 YALE L.J. 377 (1998).
    • Valuing Health Risks, Costs, and Benefits for Environmental Decision Making , pp. 55
    • Railton, P.1
  • 240
    • 0000296056 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pildes & Sunstein, supra note 2, at 82
    • As we briefly mentioned in the text above and in the introduction to this Part, the concept of welfare equivalent is an appropriate foundation for CBA even if the correct theory of well-being turns out to be a hedonic or objective-list theory. CBA is no less coherent on these theories than on a desire-based theory, although of course the specific amount of A's welfare equivalent will be different. On a hedonic theory, this amount is the amount that, paid to or by A in the project world, makes her level of hedonic tone there just the same as in the status quo; on an objective-list theory, it is the amount that, paid to or by A in the project world, makes her overall realization of objective welfarist values just the same as in the status quo world. Because we argue in this Article for a desire-based view of well-being, however, we do not further pursue this point. The point that A's WTP/WTA is distinct from her welfare equivalent has been made by Peter Railton Benefit-Cost Analysis as a Source of Information About Welfare, in VALUING HEALTH RISKS, COSTS, AND BENEFITS FOR ENVIRONMENTAL DECISION MAKING, supra note 14, at 55, 71-72. Cf. Pildes & Sunstein, supra note 2, at 82 ("[C]ontingent valuation methods still suffer from the private/public valuation distinction. What people would be willing to pay to eliminate certain conditions for themselves, and how they think public resources should be allocated, remain distinct questions. . . . [W]hat matters are lay valuations about public choices, not those about self-regarding, private choices."). We disagree: In the context of determining overall welfare, what matters are just the "self-regarding," that is, welfare-relevant, impacts of the project on each person. For a recent contribution on all-things-considered versus self-regarding ("citizen" versus "consumer") preferences, with citations to the literature, see Daphna Lewinsohn-Zamir, Consumer Preferences, Citizen Preferences, and the Provision of Public Goods, 108 YALE L.J. 377 (1998).
  • 241
    • 0000296056 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Consumer preferences, citizen preferences, and the provision of public goods
    • As we briefly mentioned in the text above and in the introduction to this Part, the concept of welfare equivalent is an appropriate foundation for CBA
    • (1998) Yale L.J. , vol.108 , pp. 377
    • Lewinsohn-Zamir, D.1
  • 242
    • 0346934153 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Incommensurability and cost-benefit analysis
    • The issue is treated at greater length in Matthew Adler, Incommensurability and Cost-Benefit Analysis, 146 U. PA. L. REV. 1371, 1391-98 (1998).
    • (1998) U. Pa. L. Rev. , vol.146 , pp. 1371
    • Adler, M.1
  • 243
    • 84923752275 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 1401-08
    • See id. at 1401-08 (discussing incomparability).
  • 244
    • 84923752274 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • By "rough substitute," we mean this: $Y is a rough substitute, for A, for the move from 5 to P if, paid or paying $Y in P, A is incomparably well off there, as compared to S. "Rough substitute" is the analogue to "welfare equivalent," with incomparability substituted for precise equality: Again, $X is a welfare equivalent, for A, for the move from S to P if, paid or paying $X in P, A is precisely equally well off there, as compared to S.
  • 245
    • 84923752273 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Copp, supra note 16, at 77-79; supra notes 79-80 and accompanying text
    • See, e.g., Copp, supra note 16, at 77-79; supra notes 79-80 and accompanying text.
  • 246
    • 84923752272 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • infra text accompanying notes 181-182
    • See infra text accompanying notes 181-182 (describing multidimensional assessment).
  • 247
    • 84923752260 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Trade Expansion Act of 1962, Pub. L. No. 87-794, tit. II, § 232, 76 Stat. 877 (codified as amended at 19 U.S.C. § 1862 (1994))
    • Congress can reduce the endowment dependence of projects by arranging for compensation of the Losers. An example is the Trade Expansion Act of 1962, Pub. L. No. 87-794, tit. II, § 232, 76 Stat. 877 (codified as amended at 19 U.S.C. § 1862 (1994)), which lowered tariffs but also provided benefits to workers who lost their jobs as a result of trade liberalization. See ROBERT J. BRENT, APPLIED COST-BENEFIT ANALYSIS 40 (1996). Note that the Act did not produce a Pareto-superior outcome because the workers were paid from general tax revenues, not from the gains to the exporters. By spreading the losses over a larger population, the Act reduced the extent to which WTPs understated welfare losses.
  • 248
    • 0003706386 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Congress can reduce the endowment dependence of projects by arranging for compensation of the Losers. An example is the Trade Expansion Act of 1962, Pub. L. No. 87-794, tit. II, § 232, 76 Stat. 877 (codified as amended at 19 U.S.C. § 1862 (1994)), which lowered tariffs but also provided benefits to workers who lost their jobs as a result of trade liberalization. See ROBERT J. BRENT, APPLIED COST-BENEFIT ANALYSIS 40 (1996). Note that the Act did not produce a Pareto-superior outcome because the workers were paid from general tax revenues, not from the gains to the exporters. By spreading the losses over a larger population, the Act reduced the extent to which WTPs understated welfare losses.
    • (1996) Applied Cost-Benefit Analysis , pp. 40
    • Brent, R.J.1
  • 249
    • 84923752257 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra text accompanying note 150
    • For the remainder of this Article, we use "CBA" broadly, to include both traditional CBA and the various refinements to traditional CBA discussed in Section IV.D. See supra text accompanying note 150 (offering a broad definition of CBA).
  • 250
    • 0039685880 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dec.
    • One procedure that we do not discuss in this Part is the procedure proposed by Stephen Coate Coate argues that a project should be approved only if there is no Pareto-superior project that would produce the same distribution as the project under consideration. See Stephen Coate Welfare Economics and the Evaluation of Policy Changes 2-3 (Dec. 1997) (unpublished manuscript on file with The Yale Law Journal). This approach avoids the endowment dependence of CBA but would provide an agency with no guidance for choosing a project in the first place.
    • (1997) Welfare Economics and the Evaluation of Policy Changes , pp. 2-3
    • Coate, S.1
  • 251
    • 84923752254 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • More precisely, these are the procedures typically employed or proposed as background procedures for use by agencies when statutory and other legal requirements become indeterminate.
  • 252
    • 84923752252 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This stipulation is crucial. We are trying to draw a clean line between direct implementation and procedures that sacrifice accuracy (more precisely, the accuracy that would be achieved by a perfectly reliable and faithful agent) for the sake of reduction in decisional cost, transparency, reliability, and so on. The cleanest way to do this is to define "direct implementation" as the procedure whereby the agent tolerates no sacrifice in epistemic gain for the sake of reduction in decisional cost or other values. The agent takes whatever steps are warranted, by her lights, to produce the most accurate measurement of overall well-being. What about the variant of direct implementation (call it "direct implementation*") in which agencies do not gather information up to the point of zero epistemic gain, but rather are enjoined (1) to take additional epistemic steps, such as information-gathering, only if the agency believes that more likely than not those steps are welfare-improving; and (2) if not, to choose the outcome, project or status quo, that the agency believes, more likely than not, will lead to higher overall well-being? Direct implementation* is more likely to be a welfare-justified decision procedure than direct implementation, and perhaps should be grouped with CBA, direct multidimensional assessment, and QUALY-based assessment as a possible multidimensional procedure for agencies to employ. See infra Subsection V.A.3 (comparing multidimensional procedures). We doubt, however, that direct implementation* will turn out to be attractive - given the difficulty of monitoring agency choices both at the threshold, information-gathering stage and at the stage of project choice - and, unlike CBA, neither direct multidimensional assessment nor QUALY-based assessment has been seriously proposed for agencies. We therefore ignore it in this Article.
  • 253
    • 84923752250 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra text accompanying notes 110-116
    • See supra text accompanying notes 110-116 (discussing these constructs).
  • 254
    • 84923752248 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HURLEY, supra note 90, at 103-10: Griffin, supra note 113, at 52-56; Hausman, supra note 106, at 477-78; and Scanlon, supra note 114, at 22-38. BINMORE, supra note 112
    • Discussions in the philosophical literature include HURLEY, supra note 90, at 103-10: Griffin, supra note 113, at 52-56; Hausman, supra note 106, at 477-78; and Scanlon, supra note 114, at 22-38. Discussions in the economic literature include BINMORE, supra note 112.
  • 255
    • 84923752246 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 88
    • See supra note 88 (citing sources that provide and defend lists of objective values); cf. THOMAS HURKA, PERFECTIONISM 84-98 (1993) (recognizing the multidimensional cast of the assessment of overall human "perfection"): SEN, supra note 135, at 23-26 (recognizing the multidimensional cast of the assessment of equality).
  • 256
    • 0003478473 scopus 로고
    • See supra note 88 (citing sources that provide and defend lists of objective values); cf. THOMAS HURKA, PERFECTIONISM 84-98 (1993) (recognizing the multidimensional cast of the assessment of overall human "perfection"): SEN, supra note 135, at 23-26 (recognizing the multidimensional cast of the assessment of equality).
    • (1993) Perfectionism , pp. 84-98
    • Hurka, T.1
  • 257
    • 84923752245 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • SEN, supra note 135, at 23-26
    • See supra note 88 (citing sources that provide and defend lists of objective values); cf. THOMAS HURKA, PERFECTIONISM 84-98 (1993) (recognizing the multidimensional cast of the assessment of overall human "perfection"): SEN, supra note 135, at 23-26 (recognizing the multidimensional cast of the assessment of equality).
  • 258
    • 84923752244 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • GRIFFIN, supra note 86, at 58; HURKA, supra note 167, at 97-98
    • See GRIFFIN, supra note 86, at 58 ("Nor is there a single right balance [of objective goods]. The right balance is very likely to vary from person to person."); HURKA, supra note 167, at 97-98 (making a similar argument with respect to an account of human perfection rather than of welfare).
  • 259
    • 0002281368 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note, rethinking regulatory reform: Toxics, politics, and ethics
    • See, e.g., Jay Michaelson, Note, Rethinking Regulatory Reform: Toxics, Politics, and Ethics, 105 YALE L.J. 1891, 1896-1901 (1996) (distinguishing between zero risk and de minimis risk, and discussing EPA's use of a de minimis standard).
    • (1996) Yale L.J. , vol.105 , pp. 1891
    • Michaelson, J.1
  • 260
    • 84923752243 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • LAVE, supra note 142, at 14-15
    • More precisely, this constraint is not a full decision procedure itself but will lend a nonaggregative element to whatever procedure is employed. On the feasibility constraint, see LAVE, supra note 142, at 14-15.
  • 261
    • 84923752231 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 15-17
    • See, e.g., id. at 15-17; Cass R. Sunstein, Health-Health Tradeoffs, 63 U. CHI. L. REV. 1533 (1996); W. Kip Viscusi, Economic Foundations of the Current Regulatory Reform Efforts, 10 J. ECON. PERSP. 119, 129-31 (1996).
  • 262
    • 0347934819 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Health-health tradeoffs
    • See, e.g., id. at 15-17; Cass R. Sunstein, Health-Health Tradeoffs, 63 U. CHI. L. REV. 1533 (1996); W. Kip Viscusi, Economic Foundations of the Current Regulatory Reform Efforts, 10 J. ECON. PERSP. 119, 129-31 (1996).
    • (1996) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.63 , pp. 1533
    • Sunstein, C.R.1
  • 263
    • 0000626788 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Economic foundations of the current regulatory reform efforts
    • See, e.g., id. at 15-17; Cass R. Sunstein, Health-Health Tradeoffs, 63 U. CHI. L. REV. 1533 (1996); W. Kip Viscusi, Economic Foundations of the Current Regulatory Reform Efforts, 10 J. ECON. PERSP. 119, 129-31 (1996).
    • (1996) J. Econ. Persp. , vol.10 , pp. 119
    • Kip Viscusi, W.1
  • 264
    • 84923752228 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • infra text accompanying notes 181-182
    • See infra text accompanying notes 181-182 (describing different kinds of direct multidimensional assessment).
  • 265
    • 0002641760 scopus 로고
    • The qualy approach
    • George Tolley et al. eds.
    • See Robert Fabian, The Qualy Approach, in VALUING HEALTH FOR POLICY: AN ECONOMIC APPROACH 118 (George Tolley et al. eds., 1994); Arti Kaur Rai, Rationing Through Choice: A New Approach to Cost-Effectiveness Analysis in Health Care, 72 IND. L.J. 1015, 1048-52 (1997).
    • (1994) Valuing Health for Policy: An Economic Approach , pp. 118
    • Fabian, R.1
  • 266
    • 1542638561 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rationing through choice: A new approach to cost-effectiveness analysis in health care
    • See Robert Fabian, The Qualy Approach, in VALUING HEALTH FOR POLICY: AN ECONOMIC APPROACH 118 (George Tolley et al. eds., 1994); Arti Kaur Rai, Rationing Through Choice: A New Approach to Cost-Effectiveness Analysis in Health Care, 72 IND. L.J. 1015, 1048-52 (1997).
    • (1997) Ind. L.J. , vol.72 , pp. 1015
    • Kaur Rai, A.1
  • 267
    • 84923752225 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • GRIFFIN, supra note 86, at 26-31
    • See, e.g., GRIFFIN, supra note 86, at 26-31.
  • 268
    • 0012286960 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Comparing harms: Headaches and human lives
    • Project gains along even a relatively unimportant dimension of human well-being, if large enough, can outweigh the welfare cost of premature death. See Alastair Norcross, Comparing Harms: Headaches and Human Lives, 26 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 135 (1997). And, of course, sometimes longevity is simply not at issue. The project and status quo could involve the same number of premature deaths - and be counted by risk-risk as equally good - but differ along various other dimensions.
    • (1997) Phil. & Pub. Aff. , vol.26 , pp. 135
    • Norcross, A.1
  • 269
    • 84928222734 scopus 로고
    • The role of constitutional and political theory in administrative law
    • A more sophisticated approach would be to assign different unidimensional procedures to different agencies or statutory schemes. But multiple dimensions, other than the dimension tracked by the assigned procedure, might still be implicated by each agency's choices. Cf. Richard J. Pierce, Jr., The Role of Constitutional and Political Theory in Administrative Law, 64 TEX. L. REV. 469, 473-81 (1985) (describing how statutes typically authorize or require agencies to consider multiple values).
    • (1985) Tex. L. Rev. , vol.64 , pp. 469
    • Pierce R.J., Jr.1
  • 271
    • 0347141502 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Law, economics, and inefficient norms
    • But see Eric A. Posner, Law, Economics, and Inefficient Norms, 144 U. PA. L. REV. 1697 (1996).
    • (1996) U. Pa. L. Rev. , vol.144 , pp. 1697
    • Posner, E.A.1
  • 272
    • 84923752224 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This need not be generally true of nonaggregative procedures. For example, we doubt that the elastic criteria of "customary practice" and "technological feasibility" are cheaper, more transparent, and easier to implement correctly than CBA.
  • 273
    • 84867664213 scopus 로고
    • Presidents and the politics of structure
    • Spring
    • On the President's ability to monitor agencies, including through the use of oversight bureaus, see, for example, Terry M. Moe & Scott Wilson, Presidents and the Politics of Structure, LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS., Spring 1994, at 1. For a somewhat more skeptical view of OMB, see MCGARITY, supra note 38, at 271-91.
    • (1994) Law & Contemp. Probs. , pp. 1
    • Moe, T.M.1    Wilson, S.2
  • 274
    • 84923752223 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MCGARITY, supra note 38, at 271-91
    • On the President's ability to monitor agencies, including through the use of oversight bureaus, see, for example, Terry M. Moe & Scott Wilson, Presidents and the Politics of Structure, LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS., Spring 1994, at 1. For a somewhat more skeptical view of OMB, see MCGARITY, supra note 38, at 271-91.
  • 275
    • 84923752222 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scanlon, supra note 114, at 41
    • Scanlon, supra note 114, at 41 (footnote omitted).
  • 276
    • 84923752220 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pildes & Sunstein, supra note 2, at 65 (footnote omitted); see also LAVE, supra note 142, at 18
    • Pildes & Sunstein, supra note 2, at 65 (footnote omitted); see also LAVE, supra note 142, at 18 ("[R]egulators would be enjoined to balance the general benefits of a proposed regulation against its general risks. This framework is intended to be somewhat vague, with all effects being enumerated, but with full quantification and valuation being left to the general wisdom of the regulators.").
  • 277
    • 84923752219 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Copp, supra note 16, at 75
    • See Copp, supra note 16, at 75 ("If Rachel and Paula are equally afflicted with asthma, then the clean air project might be of equal medical benefit to them, and this fact could be expressed in terms of the equal breathing efficiency they can expect if the project is implemented. Yet if Rachel is rich while Paula is poor, she may be willing to pay more than Paula for this benefit . . . .").
  • 278
    • 84923752218 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • CBA avoids the problem sketched here because its basic building block is the individual CV, not units of overall value or hedonic tone. Decisionmakers can draw a demand curve for the recreational boat market without specifying, or fully specifying, what it is about the boat that makes it good. If CVs are defined in terms of WTP/WTA, then the relevant demand curve is simply the observed market demand curve. If CVs are defined in terms of welfare equivalents, then decisionmakers will need to supplement market data - for example, they may need to provide boat buyers with more information, and determine how much money makes self-regarding buyers indifferent between having and not having the fully described boat-but a complete specification of welfare dimensions may still be unnecessary.
  • 279
    • 84923752217 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pildes & Sunstein, supra note 2, at 83-85
    • See Pildes & Sunstein, supra note 2, at 83-85.
  • 280
    • 84923752208 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fabian, supra note 173; Rai, supra note 173, at 1048-52. See generally LAVE, supra note 142, at 19-23
    • See Fabian, supra note 173; Rai, supra note 173, at 1048-52. See generally LAVE, supra note 142, at 19-23 (discussing cost-effectiveness analysis).
  • 281
    • 84923752206 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fabian, supra note 173, at 125-27, 133-35
    • For example, if the $400 million difference in the above hypothetical were spent on a one-year arts program in the status quo, such that each of 100,000 viewers would experience a .005 increase in the quality of her year, the $400 million difference could be translated into an increment of 500 quality-adjusted life-years for the status quo, relative to the project. Alternately, as some suggest, see Fabian, supra note 173, at 125-27, 133-35, a standard quality year could be monetized, along with other non-health benefits; but this is then just a kind of CBA.
  • 282
    • 0003617101 scopus 로고
    • On the use of so-called "contingent valuation" surveys to determine CVs, see CONTINGENT VALUATION: A CRITICAL ASSESSMENT (Jerry A. Hausman ed., 1993); MITCHELL & CARSON, supra note 152; and Symposium, Contingent Valuation, J. ECON. PERSP., Fall 1994, at 3, 3-64.
    • (1993) Contingent Valuation: A Critical Assessment
    • Hausman, J.A.1
  • 283
    • 84923752204 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MITCHELL & CARSON, supra note 152
    • On the use of so-called "contingent valuation" surveys to determine CVs, see CONTINGENT VALUATION: A CRITICAL ASSESSMENT (Jerry A. Hausman ed., 1993); MITCHELL & CARSON, supra note 152; and Symposium, Contingent Valuation, J. ECON. PERSP., Fall 1994, at 3, 3-64.
  • 284
    • 0040277646 scopus 로고
    • Symposium, contingent valuation
    • Fall
    • On the use of so-called "contingent valuation" surveys to determine CVs, see CONTINGENT VALUATION: A CRITICAL ASSESSMENT (Jerry A. Hausman ed., 1993); MITCHELL & CARSON, supra note 152; and Symposium, Contingent Valuation, J. ECON. PERSP., Fall 1994, at 3, 3-64.
    • (1994) J. Econ. Persp. , pp. 3
  • 285
    • 84923752203 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra text accompanying note 184
    • A partial solution to this transparency problem is for Congress, the President, or OMB to pre-specify the dimensions that agencies should employ - but, as already noted, there are other serious difficulties with pre-specification. See supra text accompanying note 184.
  • 286
    • 84923752202 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 161
    • Again, throughout this Section "CBA" is used in a broad sense to include refinements. See supra note 161.
  • 287
    • 84923752201 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Exec. Order No. 12,866, § (3)(f)(1), 3 C.F.R. 638, 639 (1993), reprinted in 5 U.S.C. § 601 (1994)
    • Exec. Order No. 12,866, § (3)(f)(1), 3 C.F.R. 638, 639 (1993), reprinted in 5 U.S.C. § 601 (1994).
  • 288
    • 84923752200 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Adler, supra note 155, at 1409-17. id. at 1401-08, 1411-12
    • What about the objection that CBA runs afoul of the "incommensurability" of disparate goods? This objection, if good, would weigh in favor of qualitative multidimensional assessment and other procedures that (unlike CBA, QUALY-based assessment, and quantitative multidimensional assessment) do not numerically commensurate different dimensions of welfare. For reasons that one of us has articulated elsewhere, however, we think the incommensurability objection unpersuasive - more precisely, insofar as that objection purports to argue against agency use of CBA even though it is the otherwise best-justified procedure in light ot the welfarist considerations mooted in this Part, that is, accuracy, error costs, shirking costs, direct costs, and other procedural costs. See Adler, supra note 155, at 1409-17. Although it remains possible that CBA is truly welfare-incomparable with other decision procedures, for certain choice situations, see id. at 1401-08, 1411-12, we think it implausible that CBA is globally weltare-incomparable with (or precisely equally good as) the other decision procedures discussed here. The directive "use CBA to assess projects" is not welfare-incomparable with the directive "use qua itative multidimensional assessment" (or any other procedure), but better or worse for overall well-being.
  • 289
    • 84923752199 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MCGARITY, supra note 38, at 285-88
    • Somewhat less clear is whether OMB has genuinely tried to maximize net project benefits, as opposed to pursuing some other presidential agenda (for example, satisfying large campaign contributors or pushing through deregulation at all costs). See MCGARITY, supra note 38, at 285-88 (describing the view of regulatory beneficiaries and others that OMB uses regulatory review to advance substantive policy goals).
  • 290
    • 84923752198 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Morgenstern & Landy, supra note 4, at 461-62
    • An additional category of procedural cost, not discussed here, is delay cost: the difference in value between the best option available later (after CBA is performed) and the best option now. See Morgenstern & Landy, supra note 4, at 461-62. Delay costs could warrant an additional exception to our recommended cost-benefit directive; whether they do depends on the size and prevalence of these costs and on whether such an exception can be drafted without giving too much discretion to agencies.
  • 291
    • 84923752197 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • We do not recommend an exception for cost-effectiveness analysis, given the difficulties in specifying what counts as a single dimension that should be maximized within the fixed budget. (For example, in QUALY-based cost-effectiveness analysis, there are really multiple dimensions at play - different types of health effects, plus time - that are "single" in the sense that they are feasibly reducible to the single dimension of quality-adjusted life-years.) But this is obviously a point for further debate.
  • 292
    • 84923752196 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra Section IV.D
    • See supra Section IV.D.
  • 293
    • 84923752195 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra text accompanying notes 25-34
    • It appears that some agencies are already sensitive to the dependence of CVs on wealth. For example, in the agricultural pesticide case study, EPA refused to conclude that more resources should be devoted to protecting the lives of rich people than the lives of poor people. See supra text accompanying notes 25-34.
  • 294
    • 84923752194 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra text accompanying notes 155-157
    • See supra text accompanying notes 155-157.
  • 295
    • 84923752193 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra text accompanying notes 52-53
    • See supra text accompanying notes 52-53.
  • 296
    • 84923752192 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ECONOMIC ANALYSES AT EPA, supra note 4
    • For example, in none of the case studies contained in a recent study of EPA's use of CBA did that agency end up concluding that the project and status quo could not be ranked by CBA. See ECONOMIC ANALYSES AT EPA, supra note 4.
  • 297
    • 84923752191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Deck, supra note 35, at 277-82
    • See Deck, supra note 35, at 277-82 (describing how EPA determined CVs for various air-quality levels over the Grand Canyon by using photographs to inform persons of the visibility that would result from a given air-quality level).
  • 298
    • 84923752190 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BRENT, supra note 160, at 38
    • See BRENT, supra note 160, at 38.
  • 300
    • 84923752189 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lave, supra note 18, at 104, 113-15
    • See, e.g., Lave, supra note 18, at 104, 113-15.
  • 302
    • 84923752188 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BRINK, supra note 146, at 14-36
    • On ethical conventionalism, see, for example, BRINK, supra note 146, at 14-36. At best, moral facts reduce to facts about ideally informed preferences, which are still different from facts about what the majority or all of us actually prefer. For an argument that moral facts do reduce to facts about ideally informed preferences, see MICHAEL SMITH, THE MORAL PROBLEM 151-81 (1994).
  • 303
    • 0003742241 scopus 로고
    • On ethical conventionalism, see, for example, BRINK, supra note 146, at 14-36. At best, moral facts reduce to facts about ideally informed preferences, which are still different from facts about what the majority or all of us actually prefer. For an argument that moral facts do reduce to facts about ideally informed preferences, see MICHAEL SMITH, THE MORAL PROBLEM 151-81 (1994).
    • (1994) The Moral Problem , pp. 151-181
    • Smith, M.1
  • 304
    • 84923752187 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Harsanyi, supra note 108, at 56
    • See, e.g., Harsanyi, supra note 108, at 56.
  • 305
    • 84923752186 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra text accompanying notes 93-94, 97-98
    • See supra text accompanying notes 93-94, 97-98 (arguing for a restricted-desire account of welfare).
  • 306
    • 84923752185 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DARWALL ET AL., supra note 105, at 15-19
    • On cognitivism, see DARWALL ET AL., supra note 105, at 15-19.
  • 307
    • 0001895023 scopus 로고
    • A critique of utilitarianism
    • J.J.C. SMART & BERNARD WILLIAMS
    • See Bernard Williams, A Critique of Utilitarianism, in J.J.C. SMART & BERNARD WILLIAMS, UTILITARIANISM: FOR AND AGAINST 77 (1973).
    • (1973) Utilitarianism: For and Against , pp. 77
    • Williams, B.1
  • 308
    • 84923752184 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 120 and accompanying text
    • See supra note 120 and accompanying text.
  • 309
    • 84923752183 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra text accompanying notes 126-130, 139-140
    • See supra text accompanying notes 126-130, 139-140.
  • 310
    • 84923752182 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • GEORGE SHER, DESERT (1987)
    • See GEORGE SHER, DESERT (1987).
  • 311
    • 84923752181 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HURKA, supra note 167
    • See HURKA, supra note 167; HOLMES ROLSTON III, ENVIRONMENTAL ETHICS: DUTIES TO AND VALUES IN THE NATURAL WORLD 126-59 (1988).
  • 313
    • 84923752180 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra text accompanying notes 25-33
    • See supra text accompanying notes 25-33.
  • 314
    • 84923752179 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 201 and accompanying text
    • See supra note 201 and accompanying text.
  • 315
    • 84923752178 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra text accompanying notes 20-24.Adler & Posner, supra note 203
    • See supra text accompanying notes 20-24. For additional examples of departure from textbook CBA, see Adler & Posner, supra note 203.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.