메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 114, Issue 4, 2004, Pages 790-805

Terrorism, justification, and illusion

(1)  Smilansky, Saul a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 8644290797     PISSN: 00141704     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1086/383443     Document Type: Conference Paper
Times cited : (37)

References (21)
  • 1
    • 0013117933 scopus 로고
    • Harmondsworth: Penguin
    • Bernard Williams, Morality (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1973), p. 9.
    • (1973) Morality , pp. 9
    • Williams, B.1
  • 2
    • 8744265642 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Terrorism
    • ed. Lawrence C. Becker and Charlotte B. Becker, 2d ed. (New York: Routledge)
    • C. A. J. Coady, "Terrorism," in Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Lawrence C. Becker and Charlotte B. Becker, 2d ed. (New York: Routledge, 2001), p. 1697.
    • (2001) Encyclopedia of Ethics , pp. 1697
    • Coady, C.A.J.1
  • 3
    • 84928308138 scopus 로고
    • The morality of terrorism
    • C. A. J. Coady, "The Morality of Terrorism," Philosophy 60 (1985): 58; see also Jeffrie G. Murphy, "The Killing of the Innocent," Monist 57 (1973): 547-48.
    • (1985) Philosophy , vol.60 , pp. 58
    • Coady, C.A.J.1
  • 4
    • 84928308138 scopus 로고
    • The killing of the innocent
    • C. A. J. Coady, "The Morality of Terrorism," Philosophy 60 (1985): 58; see also Jeffrie G. Murphy, "The Killing of the Innocent," Monist 57 (1973): 547-48.
    • (1973) Monist , vol.57 , pp. 547-548
    • Murphy, J.G.1
  • 5
    • 0004083066 scopus 로고
    • Harmondsworth: Penguin
    • See, e.g., Michael Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1978); R. G. Frey and Christopher W. Morris, "Violence, Terrorism and Justice," in Violence, Terrorism and Justice, ed. R. G. Frey and Christopher W. Morris (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 1-17; Virginia Held, "Terrorism, Rights and Political Goals," in Frey and Morris, eds., pp. 59-85. To avoid misunderstanding, the type of deontological view I refer to is that which poses absolute constraints on intentionally harming noncombatants. Thomas Nagel, in his influential "War and Massacre," in War and Moral Responsibility, ed. Marshall Cohen, Thomas Nagel, and Thomas Scanlon (Princeton, NJ.: Princeton University Press, 1974), calls deontology "absolutism," thereby capturing this feature.
    • (1978) Just and Unjust Wars
    • Walzer, M.1
  • 6
    • 0008705934 scopus 로고
    • Violence, terrorism and justice
    • ed. R. G. Frey and Christopher W. Morris (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
    • See, e.g., Michael Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1978); R. G. Frey and Christopher W. Morris, "Violence, Terrorism and Justice," in Violence, Terrorism and Justice, ed. R. G. Frey and Christopher W. Morris (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 1-17; Virginia Held, "Terrorism, Rights and Political Goals," in Frey and Morris, eds., pp. 59-85. To avoid misunderstanding, the type of deontological view I refer to is that which poses absolute constraints on intentionally harming noncombatants. Thomas Nagel, in his influential "War and Massacre," in War and Moral Responsibility, ed. Marshall Cohen, Thomas Nagel, and Thomas Scanlon (Princeton, NJ.: Princeton University Press, 1974), calls deontology "absolutism," thereby capturing this feature.
    • (1991) Violence, Terrorism and Justice , pp. 1-17
    • Frey, R.G.1    Morris, C.W.2
  • 7
    • 85039486711 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Frey and Morris, eds.
    • See, e.g., Michael Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1978); R. G. Frey and Christopher W. Morris, "Violence, Terrorism and Justice," in Violence, Terrorism and Justice, ed. R. G. Frey and Christopher W. Morris (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 1-17; Virginia Held, "Terrorism, Rights and Political Goals," in Frey and Morris, eds., pp. 59-85. To avoid misunderstanding, the type of deontological view I refer to is that which poses absolute constraints on intentionally harming noncombatants. Thomas Nagel, in his influential "War and Massacre," in War and Moral Responsibility, ed. Marshall Cohen, Thomas Nagel, and Thomas Scanlon (Princeton, NJ.: Princeton University Press, 1974), calls deontology "absolutism," thereby capturing this feature.
    • Terrorism, Rights and Political Goals , pp. 59-85
    • Held, V.1
  • 8
    • 0039255717 scopus 로고
    • War and massacre
    • ed. Marshall Cohen, Thomas Nagel, and Thomas Scanlon (Princeton, NJ.: Princeton University Press)
    • See, e.g., Michael Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1978); R. G. Frey and Christopher W. Morris, "Violence, Terrorism and Justice," in Violence, Terrorism and Justice, ed. R. G. Frey and Christopher W. Morris (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 1-17; Virginia Held, "Terrorism, Rights and Political Goals," in Frey and Morris, eds., pp. 59-85. To avoid misunderstanding, the type of deontological view I refer to is that which poses absolute constraints on intentionally harming noncombatants. Thomas Nagel, in his influential "War and Massacre," in War and Moral Responsibility, ed. Marshall Cohen, Thomas Nagel, and Thomas Scanlon (Princeton, NJ.: Princeton University Press, 1974), calls deontology "absolutism," thereby capturing this feature.
    • (1974) War and Moral Responsibility
    • Nagel, T.1
  • 9
    • 85039486173 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Murphy, pp. 547-48
    • See, e.g., Murphy, pp. 547-48. This is sometimes grounded in the principle of self-defense: see, e.g., Robert K. Fullinwider, "War and Innocence," in International Ethics, ed. Charles R. Beitz, Marshall Cohen, Thomas Scanlon, and A. John Simmons (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1985), p. 94.
  • 10
    • 84925893947 scopus 로고
    • War and innocence
    • ed. Charles R. Beitz, Marshall Cohen, Thomas Scanlon, and A. John Simmons (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press)
    • See, e.g., Murphy, pp. 547-48. This is sometimes grounded in the principle of self-defense: see, e.g., Robert K. Fullinwider, "War and Innocence," in International Ethics, ed. Charles R. Beitz, Marshall Cohen, Thomas Scanlon, and A. John Simmons (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1985), p. 94.
    • (1985) International Ethics , pp. 94
    • Fullinwider, R.K.1
  • 11
    • 8644247775 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Can deontologists be moderate?
    • Such a view is sometimes called "moderate deontology" or "threshold deontology," but this seems to me misleading. On the need for conceptual clarity here, see my "Can Deontologists Be Moderate?" Utilitas 15 (2003): 71-75.
    • (2003) Utilitas , vol.15 , pp. 71-75
  • 12
    • 3142682745 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Innocence, self-defense, and killing in war
    • For an extreme view on this, see Jeff McMahan, "Innocence, Self-Defense, and Killing in War," Journal of Political Philosophy 2 (1994): 193-221, and his article, "The Ethics of Killing in War," in this issue.
    • (1994) Journal of Political Philosophy , vol.2 , pp. 193-221
    • McMahan, J.1
  • 13
    • 3142682745 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • in this issue
    • For an extreme view on this, see Jeff McMahan, "Innocence, Self-Defense, and Killing in War," Journal of Political Philosophy 2 (1994): 193-221, and his article, "The Ethics of Killing in War," in this issue.
    • The Ethics of Killing in War
  • 14
    • 85039488800 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This was suggested to me by Jeff McMahan.
  • 15
    • 85039494754 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • It might be thought that by limiting my discussion to post-World War II events I have avoided the pertinent grievances that might justify terrorism. Since I think that the intentional targeting of noncombatants is morally so bad, very strong justification is required to overcome the constraint against it. It is hard to see why old historical grievances lying generations away, even if substantial, canjustify killing noncombatants in the present. To do so would open the door to virtually unlimited worldwide violence, for historically nearly every national territorial holding has been acquired unjustly (and imagine, e.g., any effort to address slavery, colonialism, or the Holocaust through terrorism!). This has interesting implications that limit the role of considerations of justice within moral justification, but this matter cannot be pursued here. In any case, I do not see that in our three cases the grievances are now morally salient, although a footnote is not the place for a thorough defense of this claim. The Protestants have been in Northern Ireland for hundreds of years, and one cannot seriously think of current Protestants as invaders or upstarts. Jews have been in what the Romans (seeking to eliminate Jewish national identity) called Palestine for longer, of course, and even before the modern Zionist movement of the 1870s had a significant presence there (there was a Jewish majority in Jerusalem, e.g.). The return of Jews to their ancient homeland was a way of reestablishing political and cultural self-determination, as other peoples had, with the hopes for security in a dangerous world. Zionist immigration was nonviolent and made into a politically undefined place (at the beginning of the process the local Arabs saw themselves as part of the larger Arab entity, and Palestinian national identity itself developed as a response to the Jewish immigration, which of course does not imply that it is not now morally legitimate or important). I cannot begin to imagine how a serious argument for historical justification of terrorism is supposed to work with Al-Oaida; judging from the rhetoric perhaps the Crusaders are the main culprits.
  • 16
    • 0742334759 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Oxford: Oxford University Press), chap. 7
    • On this notion, see Saul Smilansky, Free Will and Illusion (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), chap. 7. The usefulness of a "positive illusion" typically depends on its not being recognized as such.
    • (2000) Free Will and Illusion
    • Smilansky, S.1
  • 17
    • 8644238951 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The ethical dangers of ethical sensitivity
    • See Saul Smilansky, "The Ethical Dangers of Ethical Sensitivity," Journal of Applied Philosophy 13 (1996): 13-20.
    • (1996) Journal of Applied Philosophy , vol.13 , pp. 13-20
    • Smilansky, S.1
  • 19
    • 85039500596 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • the revised ethical code of the Israeli army; Israeli Defense Force official publication, accepted September
    • This quotation is from "The Spirit of the IDF" (the revised ethical code of the Israeli army; Israeli Defense Force official publication, accepted September 2001), available at the Israeli Defense Forces's official Web site, "Doctrine of Ethics," http://www1.idf.il/ DOVER/site/mainpage. asp?s1=en&id=23.
    • (2001) Doctrine of Ethics


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.