메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 3, Issue 4, 1999, Pages 341-350

Moral responsibility, determinism, and the ability to do otherwise

Author keywords

Compatibilism; Determinism; Free will; Harry G. Frankfurt; Moral responsibility; Principle of alternate possibilities

Indexed keywords


EID: 8644242018     PISSN: 13824554     EISSN: 15728609     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (14)

References (14)
  • 1
    • 77449104465 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Among the philosophers I have mentioned, only John Stuart Mill would have known the word "determinism," which was coined by Sir William Hamilton.
    • Among the philosophers I have mentioned, only John Stuart Mill would have known the word "determinism," which was coined by Sir William Hamilton.
  • 2
    • 77449123678 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I believe it was Keith Lehrer who coined the term "compatibilism. "
    • I believe it was Keith Lehrer who coined the term "compatibilism. "
  • 3
    • 77449096439 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • But the need for them is very small, and they are almost always better avoided. As for "contra-causal freedom" and "freedom in the libertarian sense," they must be consigned to the dustbin of philosophical history. Unfortunately, the latter turns up with some frequency in current writings on free will. To my mind, seeing that the phrase "freedom in the libertarian sense" has no possible use is the pons asinorum of the problem of free will, for compatibilists and incompatibilists use "is able to do otherwise" in exactly the same sense. The reader who doubts this should consult my essay "When Is the Will Free?" Philosophical Perspectives Volume 3: Philosophy of Mind and Action Theory (1989), pp. 394-122 [reprinted in Timothy O'Connor (ed.), Agents, Causes, and Events: Essays on Indeterminism and Free Will (New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995), pp. 219-238)]. This reader should consult particularly the long paragraph that runs from page 402 to page 404 (O'Connor, pp. 222-223) and begins "Before going further ⋯" I regard this paragraph as the single most important paragraph I have ever written about the free-will problem. I wish people would pay more attention to it.
  • 4
    • 0009280816 scopus 로고
    • The principle of alternate possibilities
    • Harry G. Frankfurt, "The Principle of Alternate Possibilities," The Journal of Philosophy LXVI (1969), pp. 829-839.
    • (1969) The Journal of Philosophy LXVI , pp. 829-839
    • Frankfurt, H.G.1
  • 5
    • 0004227030 scopus 로고
    • Reprinted in John Martin Fischer (ed.), Ithaca: Cornell University Press
    • Reprinted in John Martin Fischer (ed.), Moral Responsibility (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1986), pp. 143-152.
    • (1986) Moral Responsibility , pp. 143-152
  • 6
    • 77449121973 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • More properly, the Principle of Alternative Possibilities.
    • More properly, the Principle of Alternative Possibilities.
  • 7
    • 77449137961 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Frankfurt, "The Principle of Alternate Possibilities," p. 829. In this principle, "could have" must not be taken to mean "might have"; it means "was able to." The ambiguity of "could have" - the "might have"/"was able to" ambiguity - has caused an immense amount of confusion in discussions of PAP and in discussions of the free will problem in general. Here is a pair of examples (adapted from Austin) that illustrates this ambiguity. "You could have exposed me this morning. For God's sake, watch what you're saying when you talk to the press." "You could have exposed me this morning. I want you to know that I'm grateful you didn't.
  • 8
    • 77449144729 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • It is consistent with the way we have told the story that there was a time earlier than t at which Gunnar was able not to shoot Ridley. It should be obvious that a more elaborate example could have been constructed according to which there was no point in Gunnar's life at which he was able not to shoot Ridley.
  • 9
    • 80054144639 scopus 로고
    • Ability and responsibility
    • Reprinted in Fischer, pp. 153-173.
    • Peter van Inwagen, "Ability and Responsibility," The Philosophical Review LXXXVII (1978), pp. 201-224. Reprinted in Fischer, pp. 153-173.
    • (1978) The Philosophical Review LXXXVII , pp. 201-224
    • Van, I.P.1
  • 10
    • 77449106123 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: at the Clarendon Press, 1983. See pp. 161-182.
    • Oxford: at the Clarendon Press, 1983. See pp. 161-182.
  • 11
    • 61449285941 scopus 로고
    • What we are morally responsible for
    • Leigh S. Cauman, Isaac Levi, Charles Parsons, and Robert Schwartz (eds.), Indianapolis: Hackett
    • Harry G. Frankfurt, "What We Are Morally Responsible For," in Leigh S. Cauman, Isaac Levi, Charles Parsons, and Robert Schwartz (eds.), How Many Questions? Essays in Honor of Sydney Morgenbesser (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1982).
    • (1982) How Many Questions? Essays in Honor of Sydney Morgenbesser
    • Frankfurt Harry, G.1
  • 12
    • 77449156490 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • John Martin Fischer and Mark Ravizza (eds.), Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1993)
    • John Martin Fischer and Mark Ravizza (eds.), Perspectives on Moral Responsibility (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1993), pp. 286-295.
    • Perspectives on Moral Responsibility , pp. 286-295
  • 13
    • 77449116027 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fischer and Ravizza, p. 294.
    • Fischer and Ravizza, p. 294.
  • 14
    • 77449132135 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See "Ability and Responsibility," or Chapter V of An Essay on Free Will.
    • See "Ability and Responsibility," or Chapter V of An Essay on Free Will.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.