메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 4, Issue , 1999, Pages 333-357

The Potentiality for Actuality Metonymy in English and Hungarian

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 85190675142     PISSN: 13876724     EISSN: None     Source Type: Book Series    
DOI: 10.1075/hcp.4.19pan     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (89)

References (26)
  • 1
    • 85190658331 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note that in this case the propositional content also changes
    • Note that in this case the propositional content also changes.
  • 2
    • 85190641900 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For reasons yet to be determined the POTENTIALITY FOR ACTUALITY seems to be excluded from the referential domain
    • For reasons yet to be determined the POTENTIALITY FOR ACTUALITY seems to be excluded from the referential domain.
  • 3
    • 85190684977 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One anonymous reviewer pointed out that our use of ‘part’ does not coincide with the traditional sense of metonymy based on referential contiguity and that we confuse conceptual contiguity (as a metalinguistic concept) with referential contiguity. We claim, however, that even referential (spatial) contiguities, e.g., the set of body parts are themselves conceptual constructs. As such they are also entities in conceptual space. Just as a prototypical body is conceptualized as having a head, trunk, arms, legs, etc., we propose that a prototypical directive speech act has the components listed in (7). In this sense it seems perfectly legitimate to refer to the felicity conditions of a speech act as ‘parts’ of the speech act scenario
    • One anonymous reviewer pointed out that our use of ‘part’ does not coincide with the traditional sense of metonymy based on referential contiguity and that we confuse conceptual contiguity (as a metalinguistic concept) with referential contiguity. We claim, however, that even referential (spatial) contiguities, e.g., the set of body parts are themselves conceptual constructs. As such they are also entities in conceptual space. Just as a prototypical body is conceptualized as having a head, trunk, arms, legs, etc., we propose that a prototypical directive speech act has the components listed in (7). In this sense it seems perfectly legitimate to refer to the felicity conditions of a speech act as ‘parts’ of the speech act scenario.
  • 5
    • 85190656441 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • collecting our data, we presented native speakers of Hungarian with English sentences which instantiate the POTENTIALITY FOR ACTUALITY metonymy and asked them to give a natural translation in Hungarian. With one exception — the sentence in (38) with be able — the English data occur with the modal auxiliary can; the Hungarian translations contain, where possible, either the affix hat-/-het-, which denotes possibility in a general sense, or the verb tud, which is roughly equivalent to ‘be able, know how.’ In particular, we wanted to know whether the ‘possibility’ and ‘ability’ modality markers hat-/-het- and tud conveyed the same metonymic effect (i.e., implicating actuality) as in the English examples. We would like to thank various friends, colleagues and students for their time and assistance in providing most of the Hungarian data: especially Rita Brdar-Szabó, who supplied many helpful grammatical points
    • In collecting our data, we presented native speakers of Hungarian with English sentences which instantiate the POTENTIALITY FOR ACTUALITY metonymy and asked them to give a natural translation in Hungarian. With one exception — the sentence in (38) with be able — the English data occur with the modal auxiliary can; the Hungarian translations contain, where possible, either the affix -hat-/-het-, which denotes possibility in a general sense, or the verb tud, which is roughly equivalent to ‘be able, know how.’ In particular, we wanted to know whether the ‘possibility’ and ‘ability’ modality markers -hat-/-het- and tud conveyed the same metonymic effect (i.e., implicating actuality) as in the English examples. We would like to thank various friends, colleagues and students for their time and assistance in providing most of the Hungarian data: Andrea Szirmai, Éva Szabó, Balazs Lövenberg, Zoltán Kövecses, and especially Rita Brdar-Szabó, who supplied many helpful grammatical points.
    • Szirmai, A.1    Szabó, É.2    Lövenberg, B.3    Kövecses, Z.4
  • 6
    • 85190661561 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For the glosses of the Hungarian examples the following conventions will be used: words are separated by a space; morpheme boundaries are indicated by a hyphen; grammatical functions are indicated in small capitals. The abbreviations used are: ACC = accusative, ADJ = adjectival suffix, COND = conditional, PRES = present tense, PRT = particle, SG = singular
    • For the glosses of the Hungarian examples the following conventions will be used: words are separated by a space; morpheme boundaries are indicated by a hyphen; grammatical functions are indicated in small capitals. The abbreviations used are: ACC = accusative, ADJ = adjectival suffix, COND = conditional, DEF = definite conjugation, IMP = imperative, IND = indicative, INDEF = indefinite conjugation, PART = participle, PL = plural, POSS = possibitity, POSSESS = possessive, PRES = present tense, PRT = particle, SG = singular.
  • 8
    • 85190678232 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • examples (15) and (16) the ható complex may be regarded as an adjective-forming suffix deriving ‘possibility-passive’ adjectives from verbal bases. We are grateful to Rita Brdar-Szabó for providing the arguments in support of this claim and regard this analysis as additional support for ours
    • In examples (15) and (16) the -ható complex may be regarded as an adjective-forming suffix deriving ‘possibility-passive’ adjectives from verbal bases. We are grateful to Rita Brdar-Szabó for providing the arguments in support of this claim and regard this analysis as additional support for ours.
  • 9
    • 85190638520 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The factors that determine whether a hedged performative can actually be used to perform the illocutionary act denoted by the performative verb are complex and will not be dealt with in any detail. Suffice it to say that I can ask you to leave does not constitute an act of asking nor does I must promise to be there constitute a promise
    • The factors that determine whether a hedged performative can actually be used to perform the illocutionary act denoted by the performative verb are complex and will not be dealt with in any detail. Suffice it to say that I can ask you to leave does not constitute an act of asking nor does I must promise to be there constitute a promise.
  • 10
    • 85190641211 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • With indirect commissives (offers) like (30), our Hungarian language consultants often preferred the more indirect conditional over the plainer indicative mood for reasons of politeness. This preference also holds for indirect directives
    • With indirect commissives (offers) like (30), our Hungarian language consultants often preferred the more indirect conditional over the plainer indicative mood for reasons of politeness. This preference also holds for indirect directives.
  • 11
    • 85190672285 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We are grateful to Rita Brdar-Szabó for making this point clear to us
    • We are grateful to Rita Brdar-Szabó for making this point clear to us.
  • 12
    • 85190664373 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is an example of what Sweetser calls ‘speech act modality.’ Unlike (46), utterance (49) is not available as a topic-introducing or discourse-initiating device and seems to be restricted to a reactive slot in a discourse
    • This is an example of what Sweetser calls ‘speech act modality.’ Unlike (46), utterance (49) is not available as a topic-introducing or discourse-initiating device and seems to be restricted to a reactive slot in a discourse.
  • 14
    • 0010864951 scopus 로고
    • The role of domains in the interpretation of metaphors and metonymies
    • Croft, William 1993 The role of domains in the interpretation of metaphors and metonymies. Cognitive Linguistics 4: 335–370.
    • (1993) Cognitive Linguistics , vol.4 , pp. 335-370
    • Croft, W.1
  • 15
    • 0001268943 scopus 로고
    • Hedged performatives
    • Cole, J. Morgan eds, New York: Academic Press
    • Fraser, Bruce 1975 Hedged performatives. In P. Cole, J. Morgan (eds.), Syntax and Semantics. Vol. 3: Speech Acts. New York: Academic Press, 187–210.
    • (1975) Syntax and Semantics. Vol. 3: Speech Acts , pp. 187-210
    • Fraser, B.1
  • 16
    • 0000534475 scopus 로고
    • Logic and conversation
    • Cole, J. Morgan eds, New York: Academic Press
    • Grice, H. Paul 1975 Logic and conversation. In P. Cole, J. Morgan (eds.), Syntax and Semantics. Vol. 3: Speech Acts. New York: Academic Press, 41–58.
    • (1975) Syntax and Semantics. Vol. 3: Speech Acts , pp. 41-58
    • Grice, H.P.1
  • 19
    • 85026077659 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Metonymy: developing a cognitive linguistic view
    • Kövecses, Zoltán, Günter Radden 1998 Metonymy: developing a cognitive linguistic view. Cognitive Linguistics 9: 37–77.
    • (1998) Cognitive Linguistics , vol.9 , pp. 37-77
    • Kövecses, Z.1    Radden, G.2
  • 21
    • 84935201581 scopus 로고
    • Indirect speech act markers or why some linguistic signs are non-arbitrary
    • R.A. Hendricks et al. eds, Chicago Linguistic Society, April 30 May 1, 1981. Chicago: Chicago Linguistic Society
    • Panther, Klaus-Uwe 1981 Indirect speech act markers or why some linguistic signs are non-arbitrary. In R.A. Hendricks et al. (eds.), Papers from the Seventeenth Regional Meeting. Chicago Linguistic Society, April 30 - May 1, 1981. Chicago: Chicago Linguistic Society, 295–302.
    • (1981) Papers from the Seventeenth Regional Meeting , pp. 295-302
    • Panther, K.-U.1
  • 22
    • 0032337605 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A cognitive approach to inferencing in conversation
    • Panther, Klaus-Uwe, Linda Thornburg 1998 A cognitive approach to inferencing in conversation. Journal of Pragmatics 30: 755–769.
    • (1998) Journal of Pragmatics , vol.30 , pp. 755-769
    • Panther, K.-U.1    Thornburg, L.2
  • 24
    • 0001819160 scopus 로고
    • Indirect speech acts
    • Cole, J. Morgan eds, New York: Academic Press
    • Searle, John 1975 Indirect speech acts. In P. Cole, J. Morgan (eds.), Syntax and Semantics. Vol. 3: Speech Acts . New York: Academic Press, 59–82.
    • (1975) Syntax and Semantics. Vol. 3: Speech Acts , pp. 59-82
    • Searle, J.1
  • 26
    • 0010065767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Speech act metonymies
    • W.A. Liebert et al. eds, Amsterdam and Philadelphia: Benjamins
    • Thornburg, Linda, Klaus-Uwe Panther 1997 Speech act metonymies. In W.A. Liebert et al. (eds.), Discourse and Perspectives in Cognitive Linguistics. Amsterdam and Philadelphia: Benjamins, 205–219.
    • (1997) Discourse and Perspectives in Cognitive Linguistics , pp. 205-219
    • Thornburg, L.1    Panther, K.-U.2


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.