메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 4, Issue , 1999, Pages 17-59

Towards a Theory of Metonymy

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 85114945977     PISSN: 13876724     EISSN: None     Source Type: Book Series    
DOI: 10.1075/hcp.4.03rad     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (391)

References (50)
  • 1
    • 85190676636 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We
    • This paper elaborates upon an earlier version which appeared in Cognitive Linguistics 9–1 are grateful to our anonymous reviewers for their insightful and helpful comments. wish to express our thanks to Elizabeth Mathis and Gary Palmer for their valuable linguistic contributions to this paper
    • This paper elaborates upon an earlier version which appeared in Cognitive Linguistics 9–1 (1998). We are grateful to our anonymous reviewers for their insightful and helpful comments. We also wish to express our thanks to Elizabeth Mathis and Gary Palmer for their valuable linguistic contributions to this paper.
    • (1998) We also
  • 2
    • 85190685725 scopus 로고
    • This view corresponds to Dirven’s 14) characterization of metonymy as opposed to metaphor: “[... in metonymy the two domains both remain intact, but they are seen to be in line, whereas in metaphor only one domain, viz. the target domain is kept, and the other domain, viz. the source domain disappears, so to speak
    • This view corresponds to Dirven’s (1993: 14) characterization of metonymy as opposed to metaphor: “[...] in metonymy the two domains both remain intact, but they are seen to be in line, whereas in metaphor only one domain, viz. the target domain is kept, and the other domain, viz. the source domain disappears, so to speak.”
    • (1993)
  • 3
    • 85190640630 scopus 로고
    • The attraction of Langacker’s cognitive explanation of metonymy lies in the pervasiveness of reference-point phenomena in language structure, in particular possessive expressions. The view of metonymy as a reference-point phenomenon is, however, not unproblematic. The process of first making mental contact to a reference point before accessing the target should take longer than that of accessing a conceptual entity directly, which, however, has not been confirmed experimentally in terms of processing time Gibbs
    • The attraction of Langacker’s cognitive explanation of metonymy lies in the pervasiveness of reference-point phenomena in language structure, in particular possessive expressions. The view of metonymy as a reference-point phenomenon is, however, not unproblematic. The process of first making mental contact to a reference point before accessing the target should take longer than that of accessing a conceptual entity directly, which, however, has not been confirmed experimentally in terms of processing time (Gibbs 1993).
    • (1993)
  • 4
    • 85190691908 scopus 로고
    • the discussion of the notion of ‘contiguity’ in Koch (this. 347) definition of metonymy as “a shift of a word meaning from the entity it stands for to a ‘contiguous’ entity
    • See the discussion of the notion of ‘contiguity’ in Koch (this volume). The notion of contiguity is also present in cognitive definitions as in Croft’s (1993: 347) definition of metonymy as “a shift of a word meaning from the entity it stands for to a ‘contiguous’ entity.”
    • (1993) The notion of contiguity is also present in cognitive definitions as in Croft’s
  • 5
    • 85190660914 scopus 로고
    • For similar views Lakoff (1987, 1993) and Blank (this
    • For similar views see Lakoff and Johnson (1980), Lakoff (1987), Croft (1993) and Blank (this volume).
    • (1980) Croft
    • Lakoff1    Johnson2
  • 6
    • 85190713283 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The word hearse derives from Latin (h)irpicem ‘large rake used as a harrow’ and Samnite (h)irpus ‘wolf,’ i.e., the pins of the harrow were metaphorically related to the wolf’s teeth
    • The word hearse derives from Latin (h)irpicem ‘large rake used as a harrow’ and Samnite (h)irpus ‘wolf,’ i.e., the pins of the harrow were metaphorically related to the wolf’s teeth.
  • 7
    • 85190680495 scopus 로고
    • distinguishing metaphor from metonymy, Lakoff and Johnson (1980: 36) and Lakoff and Turner 103) view metonymy as primarily having a referential function, as opposed to the function of understanding associated with metaphor. But this view of metonymy is at odds with the many other areas in which metonymy is found
    • In distinguishing metaphor from metonymy, Lakoff and Johnson (1980: 36) and Lakoff and Turner (1989: 103) view metonymy as primarily having a referential function, as opposed to the function of understanding associated with metaphor. But this view of metonymy is at odds with the many other areas in which metonymy is found.
    • (1989)
  • 8
    • 85190648191 scopus 로고
    • 19–20) illustrates the difference between the extensional world and the mentally projected world by the well-known case of tautologies as in George Bush is George Bush. This sentence is meaningfully interpretable in an attitudinal sense, which may be made explicit by attitude predicates such as wonder, doubt, be uncertain, etc. as in I wonder if George Bush is George Bush
    • 1994: has shown that such tautologies are metonymic in that a category is used to refer to specific salient parts or attributes. This analysis is also adopted here cf. 3.1.(vi
    • Frawley (1992: 19–20) illustrates the difference between the extensional world and the mentally projected world by the well-known case of tautologies as in George Bush is George Bush. This sentence is meaningfully interpretable in an attitudinal sense, which may be made explicit by attitude predicates such as wonder, doubt, be uncertain, etc. as in I wonder if George Bush is George Bush. Gibbs (1994: 345–351) has shown that such tautologies are metonymic in that a category is used to refer to specific salient parts or attributes. This analysis is also adopted here (cf. 3.1.(vi)).
    • (1992) Gibbs , pp. 345-351
    • Frawley1
  • 9
    • 85190661208 scopus 로고
    • it [the active-zone/profile discrepancy] has to be regarded as natural and expected rather than pathological
    • Cf. Langacker 31 Similarly, Herskovits (1985: 363) points out in her discussion of the salience principle that the metonymic shift to a salient part “has come to be so natural that it is hard to think that it involves any special process such as metonymy.” Langacker (1991: 191) even argues that “It is in fact quite difficult to find convincing examples where all aspects of the designated entity participate equally in a relationship
    • Cf. Langacker (1993: 31): “it [the active-zone/profile discrepancy] has to be regarded as natural and expected rather than pathological.” Similarly, Herskovits (1985: 363) points out in her discussion of the salience principle that the metonymic shift to a salient part “has come to be so natural that it is hard to think that it involves any special process such as metonymy.” Langacker (1991: 191) even argues that “It is in fact quite difficult to find convincing examples [...] where all aspects of the designated entity participate equally in a relationship.”
    • (1993)
  • 10
    • 85190676047 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. the careful distinction between metonymy and synecdoche made by Seto this
    • Cf. the careful distinction between metonymy and synecdoche made by Seto (this volume).
  • 13
    • 85190691875 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a more general distinction between metonymies based on co-presence and succession, Blank this
    • For a more general distinction between metonymies based on co-presence and succession, see Blank (this volume).
  • 14
    • 85190680406 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The metonymy ACTUAL FOR POTENTIAL also accounts for the development of the possibility sense of the modals can and may. The epistemic sense of can may have developed from the original sense of ‘know’ via ‘knowledge how to do X’ and ‘being able to act’ to ‘increased possibility of acting.’ In a similar chain of sense development, the original sense of may ‘might, power’ may have led to the modal sense of possibility. Studies on grammaticalization have convincingly explained the steps involved in these semantic changes by implicature and pragmatic strengthening
    • The metonymy ACTUAL FOR POTENTIAL also accounts for the development of the possibility sense of the modals can and may. The epistemic sense of can may have developed from the original sense of ‘know’ via ‘knowledge how to do X’ and ‘being able to act’ to ‘increased possibility of acting.’ In a similar chain of sense development, the original sense of may ‘might, power’ may have led to the modal sense of possibility. Studies on grammaticalization have convincingly explained the steps involved in these semantic changes by implicature and pragmatic strengthening.
  • 15
    • 85190683171 scopus 로고
    • Lakoff in the discussion Semantic Accommodation
    • Cf. on May 7
    • Cf. Lakoff in the discussion on “Semantic Accommodation” in Cogling, May 7, 1994.
    • (1994) Cogling
  • 16
    • 85190654940 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Objects and animals may, of course, also be associated with a place. A nice example of metonymic association is the proper name Canary Islands, which goes back to the name Canaria given to it by the Romans on account of the many dogs seen there and which later on provided the name for the bird canary, which the Spanish found on the islands
    • Objects and animals may, of course, also be associated with a place. A nice example of metonymic association is the proper name Canary Islands, which goes back to the name Canaria given to it by the Romans on account of the many dogs seen there and which later on provided the name for the bird canary, which the Spanish found on the islands.
  • 17
    • 85190658454 scopus 로고
    • The following semantic constraints identified by Cooper and Ross correspond to the cognitive principles as used here: Here and Now correspond to IMMEDIATE OVER NON-IMMEDIATE, Singular corresponds to SPECIFIC OVER GENERIC, Animate and Agentive correspond to HUMAN OVER NON-HUMAN, and Count corresponds to BOUNDED OVER UNBOUNDED
    • The following semantic constraints identified by Cooper and Ross (1975) correspond to the cognitive principles as used here: Here and Now correspond to IMMEDIATE OVER NON-IMMEDIATE, Singular corresponds to SPECIFIC OVER GENERIC, Animate and Agentive correspond to HUMAN OVER NON-HUMAN, and Count corresponds to BOUNDED OVER UNBOUNDED. Possibly also the remaining semantic constraints are relevant for metonymy.
    • (1975) Possibly also the remaining semantic constraints are relevant for metonymy
  • 19
    • 85190690019 scopus 로고
    • Cf. Morgan 263), who analyzes this example, which goes back to Robin Lakoff, as conventionalized conversational implicature
    • Cf. Morgan (1978: 263), who analyzes this example, which goes back to Robin Lakoff, as conventionalized conversational implicature.
    • (1978)
  • 21
    • 0010864951 scopus 로고
    • The role of domains in the interpretation of metaphors and metonymies
    • Croft, William 1993 The role of domains in the interpretation of metaphors and metonymies. Cognitive Linguistics 4: 335–370.
    • (1993) Cognitive Linguistics , vol.4 , pp. 335-370
    • Croft, W.1
  • 22
    • 84936824220 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Cruse, D. Alan 1986 Lexical Semantics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    • (1986) Lexical Semantics
    • Cruse, D.A.1
  • 23
    • 85050168731 scopus 로고
    • Metonymy and metaphor: different mental strategies of conceptualization
    • Dirven, René 1993 Metonymy and metaphor: different mental strategies of conceptualization. Leuvense Bijdragen 82: 1–28.
    • (1993) Leuvense Bijdragen , vol.82 , pp. 1-28
    • Dirven, R.1
  • 24
  • 25
    • 0002689074 scopus 로고
    • Processes and products in making sense of tropes
    • A. Ortony ed, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Second edition
    • Gibbs, Raymond W., Jr. 1993 Processes and products in making sense of tropes. In A. Ortony (ed.), Metaphor and Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Second edition. 252–276.
    • (1993) Metaphor and Thought , pp. 252-276
    • Gibbs, R.W.1
  • 27
    • 0000534475 scopus 로고
    • Logic and conversation
    • Cole, J.L. Morgan eds, New York: Academic Press
    • Grice, H. Paul 1975 Logic and conversation. In P. Cole, J.L. Morgan (eds.), Syntax and Semantics. Vol. 3: Speech Acts. New York: Academic Press, 41–58.
    • (1975) Syntax and Semantics. Vol. 3: Speech Acts , pp. 41-58
    • Grice, H.P.1
  • 28
    • 0007235712 scopus 로고
    • Semantics and pragmatics of locative expressions
    • Herskovits, Annette 1985 Semantics and pragmatics of locative expressions. Cognitive Science 9: 341–378.
    • (1985) Cognitive Science , vol.9 , pp. 341-378
    • Herskovits, A.1
  • 29
    • 33745187266 scopus 로고
    • Polysemy, tropes and cognition or the non-Magrittian art of closing curtains whilst opening them
    • W. Paprotté, R. Dirven eds, Amsterdam and Philadelphia: Benjamins
    • Jongen, René 1985 Polysemy, tropes and cognition or the non-Magrittian art of closing curtains whilst opening them. In W. Paprotté, R. Dirven (eds.), The Ubiquity of Metaphor (Current Issues in Linguistic Theory 29). Amsterdam and Philadelphia: Benjamins, 121–139.
    • (1985) The Ubiquity of Metaphor (Current Issues in Linguistic Theory 29) , pp. 121-139
    • Jongen, R.1
  • 30
    • 0011587810 scopus 로고
    • Lewisburgh: Associated University Press
    • Kövecses, Zoltán 1988 The Language of Love. Lewisburgh: Associated University Press.
    • (1988) The Language of Love
    • Kövecses, Z.1
  • 32
    • 0040749548 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Idioms: A view from cognitive semantics
    • Kövecses, Zoltán, Péter Szabó 1996 Idioms: A view from cognitive semantics. Applied Linguistics 17: 326–355.
    • (1996) Applied Linguistics , vol.17 , pp. 326-355
    • Kövecses, Z.1    Szabó, P.2
  • 33
    • 85026077659 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Metonymy: Developing a cognitive linguistic view
    • Kövecses, Zoltán, Günter Radden 1998 Metonymy: Developing a cognitive linguistic view. Cognitive Linguistics 9: 37–77.
    • (1998) Cognitive Linguistics , vol.9 , pp. 37-77
    • Kövecses, Z.1    Radden, G.2
  • 38
    • 0010056011 scopus 로고
    • Reference-point constructions
    • Langacker, Ronald W. 1993 Reference-point constructions. Cognitive Linguistics 4: 1–38.
    • (1993) Cognitive Linguistics , vol.4 , pp. 1-38
    • Langacker, R.W.1
  • 39
    • 0000949281 scopus 로고
    • Two types of convention in indirect speech acts
    • Cole ed, Pragmatics. San Diego: Academic Press
    • Morgan, Jerry L. 1978 Two types of convention in indirect speech acts. In P. Cole (ed.), Syntax and Semantics. Vol. 9: Pragmatics. San Diego: Academic Press, 261–280.
    • (1978) Syntax and Semantics , vol.9 , pp. 261-280
    • Morgan, J.L.1
  • 43
    • 85190648272 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Günter in print How metonymic are metaphors?
    • A. Barcelona ed, Berlin, New York: Mouton de Gruyter
    • Radden, Günter in print How metonymic are metaphors? In A. Barcelona (ed.), Metaphor and Metonymy at the Crossroads. Berlin, New York: Mouton de Gruyter.
    • Metaphor and Metonymy at the Crossroads
    • Radden1
  • 44
    • 0001768989 scopus 로고
    • Lexicalization patterns: semantic structure in lexical forms
    • T. Shopen ed, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Talmy, Leonard 1985 Lexicalization patterns: semantic structure in lexical forms. In T. Shopen (ed.), Language Typology and Syntactic Description. Vol 3. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 36–149.
    • (1985) Language Typology and Syntactic Description , vol.3 , pp. 36-149
    • Talmy, L.1
  • 46
    • 0010065767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Speech act metonymies
    • W.-A. Liebert et al. eds, Amsterdam and Philadelphia: Benjamins
    • Thornburg, Linda, Klaus-Uwe Panther 1997 Speech act metonymies. In W.-A. Liebert et al. (eds.), Discourse and Perspective in Cognitive Linguistics. Amsterdam and Philadelphia: Benjamins, 205–219.
    • (1997) Discourse and Perspective in Cognitive Linguistics , pp. 205-219
    • Thornburg, L.1    Panther, K.-U.2


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.