메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 28, Issue , 1998, Pages 203-225

Doubt: Affective states and the regulation of inquiry

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 85063703159     PISSN: 00455091     EISSN: 19110820     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1080/00455091.1998.10717500     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (29)

References (13)
  • 1
    • 84985846632 scopus 로고
    • Mimicking Foundationalism: On Sentiments and Self-control
    • 1993. European Journal of Philosophy, 1: 156–74. “Mimicking Foundationalism: On Sentiments and Self-control,”
    • (1993) European Journal of Philosophy , vol.1 , pp. 156-174
  • 2
    • 0007678458 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, For an interesting exception to this, see Catherine Elgins Chapter 5
    • 1996. Considered Judgment Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. For an interesting exception to this, see Catherine Elgin's Chapter 5.
    • (1996) Considered Judgment
  • 3
    • 0004110142 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press, See, for example, Stanley Cavell, and Michael Williams, Unnatural Doubts (Oxford: Blackwell, 1991), passim
    • 1979. The Claim of Reason Oxford: Oxford University Press. See, for example, Stanley Cavell, and Michael Williams, Unnatural Doubts (Oxford: Blackwell, 1991), passim.
    • (1979) The Claim of Reason
  • 4
    • 85063702061 scopus 로고
    • If this is correct, then it suggests that there are rational limits to how reflective we should be assessing our beliefs and inquiries; rational reflection is often fundamentally shallow. Mapping the limits of responsible or rational reflection was the main concern of my Cognitive Virtues and Epistemic Evaluations,: 211–27. I discuss the topic further Part 2 of Scepticism (London: Routledge, 1990) and Naturalised Epistemology and Epistemic Evaluation, Inquiry 37 (1994
    • 1994. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 2: 465–85. If this is correct, then it suggests that there are rational limits to how reflective we should be in assessing our beliefs and inquiries; rational reflection is often fundamentally shallow. Mapping the limits of responsible or rational reflection was the main concern of my “Cognitive Virtues and Epistemic Evaluations,”: 211–27. I discuss the topic further in Part 2 of Scepticism (London: Routledge, 1990) and in “Naturalised Epistemology and Epistemic Evaluation,” Inquiry 37 (1994)
    • (1994) International Journal of Philosophical Studies , vol.2 , pp. 465-485
  • 5
    • 0037617226 scopus 로고
    • Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, References to Peirces work employ two sources: they take the following standard forms. (Volumes 2 and 3), (–86) is referred to the text as W followed by volume and page. References to Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, ed. C. Hartshorne, P. Weiss, and A. Burks (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1931–58) identify volume and numbered paragraph., eds
    • Fisch, M., eds. 1984. Writings of Charles S. Peirce: A Chronological Edition Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press. References to Peirce's work employ two sources: they take the following standard forms. (Volumes 2 and 3), (–86) is referred to in the text as “W” followed by volume and page. References to Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, ed. C. Hartshorne, P. Weiss, and A. Burks (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1931–58) identify volume and numbered paragraph.
    • (1984) Writings of Charles S. Peirce: A Chronological Edition
    • Fisch, M.1
  • 7
    • 85063704471 scopus 로고
    • The final sentence was added to this passage 1903 5.376
    • 1877. Collected Papers The final sentence was added to this passage in 1903 5.376).
    • (1877) Collected Papers
  • 8
    • 0003396614 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press, The epistemic importance of the idea of self-trust has recently been emphasized by Keith Lehrer in
    • 1997. Self-Trust: A Study of Reason, Knowledge and Autonomy Oxford: Oxford University Press. The epistemic importance of the idea of self-trust has recently been emphasized by Keith Lehrer in
    • (1997) Self-Trust: A Study of Reason, Knowledge and Autonomy
  • 9
    • 85063703336 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I shall not discuss detail exactly why the sort of self-trust described here is rational. At least two strategies suggest themselves, both familiar from pragmatist writings. First: it could be defended as a regulative presumption. If it is not warranted, then responsible rationality would be impossible, so it is rational to proceed on the, hope, that it is warranted. Second: appeal could be made to the fact that it is natural and, indeed, unavoidable much of the time. If my behaviour shows that I endorse it, then, the absence of a positive reason for doubting it, I am warranted relying upon it
    • I shall not discuss in detail exactly why the sort of self-trust described here is rational. At least two strategies suggest themselves, both familiar from pragmatist writings. First: it could be defended as a regulative presumption. If it is not warranted, then responsible rationality would be impossible, so it is rational to proceed on the hope that it is warranted. Second: appeal could be made to the fact that it is “natural” and, indeed, unavoidable much of the time. If my behaviour shows that I endorse it, then, in the absence of a positive reason for doubting it, I am warranted in relying upon it.
  • 10
    • 33746596655 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Toronto: Toronto University Press, I have done so elsewhere: see Mimicking Foundationalism and Sentiment and Self-control, 201–22. Also relevant is Cognitive Virtues and Epistemic Evaluations, International journal of Philosophical Studies 2 (1994):, and, eds
    • Brunning, Jacqueline, and Forster, Paul, eds. 1997. The Rule of Reason: The Philosophy of Charles Sanders Peirce 211–27. Toronto: Toronto University Press. I have done so elsewhere: see “Mimicking Foundationalism” and “Sentiment and Self-control,” in 201–22. Also relevant is “Cognitive Virtues and Epistemic Evaluations,” International journal of Philosophical Studies 2 (1994)
    • (1997) The Rule of Reason: The Philosophy of Charles Sanders Peirce , pp. 211-227
    • Brunning, J.1    Forster, P.2
  • 11
    • 85063697445 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This example is discussed by Catherine Elgin Chapter 5; see esp
    • Considered Judgment 146–47. This example is discussed by Catherine Elgin in Chapter 5; see esp.
    • Considered Judgment , pp. 146-147


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.