메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 27, Issue , 1997, Pages 25-65

Quinus ab omni nævo vindicatus

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 85063703054     PISSN: 00455091     EISSN: 19110820     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1080/00455091.1997.10715961     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (31)

References (54)
  • 1
    • 85063703605 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This paper is a completely rewritten version of an unpublished paper, ‘The Varied Sorrows of Modality, Part II.’ I am indebted to several colleagues for information used writing that paper, and for advice given on it once written, and I would like to thank them all—Gil Harman, Dick Jeffrey, David Lewis—even if the portions of the paper with which some of them were most helpful have disappeared from the final version. But I would especially like to thank Scott Soames, who was most helpful with the portions that have, not, disappeared
    • This paper is a completely rewritten version of an unpublished paper, ‘The Varied Sorrows of Modality, Part II.’ I am indebted to several colleagues for information used in writing that paper, and for advice given on it once written, and I would like to thank them all—Gil Harman, Dick Jeffrey, David Lewis—even if the portions of the paper with which some of them were most helpful have disappeared from the final version. But I would especially like to thank Scott Soames, who was most helpful with the portions that have not disappeared.
  • 2
    • 23844525470 scopus 로고
    • Is Alethic Modal Logic Possible?
    • opening paragraph. context it is clear this is a description, not an endorsement, of a widespread impression
    • Hintikka, J., 1982. ‘Is Alethic Modal Logic Possible?’. Acta Philosophica Fennica, 35: 89–105., opening paragraph. In context it is clear this is a description, not an endorsement, of a widespread impression.
    • (1982) Acta Philosophica Fennica , vol.35 , pp. 89-105
    • Hintikka, J.1
  • 3
    • 85063698799 scopus 로고
    • The most important of Quines presentations is ‘Reference and Modality,’ (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, three editions, 1953, 1961, 1980). Citations of this twice-revised work here will be by internal section and paragraph divisions, the same from edition to edition. This work supersedes the earlier ‘The Problem of Interpreting Modal Logic,’ Journal of Symbolic Logic12 43–8. For commentary see Linsky, editors introduction to Reference and Modality (Oxford: University Press 1971), and ‘Reference, Essentialism, and Modality,’ therein 88–100. See also D. Føllesdal, ‘Quine on Modality,’ D. Davidson and J. Hintikka, eds., Words and Objections: Essays on the Work of W. V. Quine (Dordrecht: Reidel 1969), 175–85; and ‘Essentialism and Reference,’ L. E. Hahn and P. A. Schilpp, eds., The Philosophy of W. V. Quine (La Salle: Open Court 1986
    • 1947. From a Logical Point of View,: 97–113. The most important of Quine's presentations is ‘Reference and Modality,’ in (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, three editions, 1953, 1961, 1980). Citations of this twice-revised work here will be by internal section and paragraph divisions, the same from edition to edition. This work supersedes the earlier ‘The Problem of Interpreting Modal Logic,’ Journal of Symbolic Logic12 43–8. For commentary see Linsky, editor's introduction to Reference and Modality (Oxford: University Press 1971), and ‘Reference, Essentialism, and Modality,’ therein 88–100. See also D. Føllesdal, ‘Quine on Modality,’ in D. Davidson and J. Hintikka, eds., Words and Objections: Essays on the Work of W. V. Quine (Dordrecht: Reidel 1969), 175–85; and ‘Essentialism and Reference,’ in L. E. Hahn and P. A. Schilpp, eds., The Philosophy of W. V. Quine (La Salle: Open Court 1986)
    • (1947) From a Logical Point of View , pp. 97-113
  • 4
    • 85063700411 scopus 로고
    • A theme his reviews the (1946) 96–7 and 12
    • 1947. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 11: 95–6. A theme in his reviews in the (1946) 96–7 and 12
    • (1947) Journal of Symbolic Logic , vol.11 , pp. 95-96
  • 7
    • 0004243667 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press, For a contemporary account deploring such tendencies, see W. Kneale and M. Kneale, 628ff. Such tendencies are exemplified by the usage of all the participants the exchange discussed section II below
    • 1962. The Development of Logic Oxford: Clarendon Press. For a contemporary account deploring such tendencies, see W. Kneale and M. Kneale, 628ff. Such tendencies are exemplified by the usage of all the participants in the exchange discussed in section II below.
    • (1962) The Development of Logic
  • 8
    • 85063699613 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a less rough formulation, see Parsons, ‘Essentialism and Quantified Modal Logic,’ 35–52, reprinted Linsky
    • The Philosophical Review, 7873–87. For a less rough formulation, see Parsons, ‘Essentialism and Quantified Modal Logic,’ 35–52, reprinted in Linsky
    • The Philosophical Review , vol.78 , pp. 73-87
  • 9
    • 85063705335 scopus 로고
    • It may be worth digressing to mention that Quines one and only contribution to the formal side of modal logic occurred connection with this law, though the history does not always emerge clearly from textbook presentations. The earliest derivations of the law took an old-fashioned approach on which identity is a defined second-order notion, and on such an approach the derivation was anything but straightforward, and only went through for systems at least as strong as the second-strongest Lewis system Quine was one of the first to note that on a modern approach with identity a primitive first-order notion, the derivation becomes trivial, and goes through for all systems at least as strong as the minimal normal system K. This is alluded to passing the penultimate paragraph of the third section of ‘Reference and Modality.’ For the original presentation see R. Barcan (Marcus), ‘Identity of Individuals a Strict Functional Calculus of Second Order,’ 12 3–23. For a modern textbook presentation see G. E. Hughes and M. J. Creswell, An Introduction to Modal Logic (London: Methuen 1968), 190
    • 1947. Journal of Symbolic Logic, S4 It may be worth digressing to mention that Quine's one and only contribution to the formal side of modal logic occurred in connection with this law, though the history does not always emerge clearly from textbook presentations. The earliest derivations of the law took an old-fashioned approach on which identity is a defined second-order notion, and on such an approach the derivation was anything but straightforward, and only went through for systems at least as strong as the second-strongest Lewis system Quine was one of the first to note that on a modern approach with identity a primitive first-order notion, the derivation becomes trivial, and goes through for all systems at least as strong as the minimal normal system K. This is alluded to in passing in the penultimate paragraph of the third section of ‘Reference and Modality.’ For the original presentation see R. Barcan (Marcus), ‘Identity of Individuals in a Strict Functional Calculus of Second Order,’ 12 3–23. For a modern textbook presentation see G. E. Hughes and M. J. Creswell, An Introduction to Modal Logic (London: Methuen 1968), 190.
    • (1947) Journal of Symbolic Logic , vol.S4
  • 10
    • 0004327725 scopus 로고
    • Reidel: Dordrecht, the original paper where (17) was derived there were no singular terms but variables, and nothing was said about application to natural language. For an idea of the range of options formally available, see the taxonomy J. Garson, ‘Quantification Modal Logic,’ II, and, eds
    • Gabbay, D., and Guenthner, F., eds. 1984. Handbook of Philosophical Logic 249–308. Reidel: Dordrecht. In the original paper where (17) was derived there were no singular terms but variables, and nothing was said about application to natural language. For an idea of the range of options formally available, see the taxonomy in J. Garson, ‘Quantification in Modal Logic,’ in II
    • (1984) Handbook of Philosophical Logic , pp. 249-308
    • Gabbay, D.1    Guenthner, F.2
  • 11
    • 85063702138 scopus 로고
    • See Ackerman, Prepositional Attitudes Toward Integers/in Essays on the Philosophy of W. V. Quine (Norman: University of Oklahoma Press. Lectures of Kripke have brought this formerly underappreciated paper to the attention of a wider audience. See also S. Shapiro, ed., Intensional Mathematics (Amsterdam: North Holland 1985); and especially G. Boolos, The Logic of Provability (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1993), xxxiv and 226., and, eds
    • Shahan, R. W., and Swoyer, C., eds. 1979. ‘De Re See Ackerman, Prepositional Attitudes Toward Integers/in Essays on the Philosophy of W. V. Quine (Norman: University of Oklahoma Press. Lectures of Kripke have brought this formerly underappreciated paper to the attention of a wider audience. See also S. Shapiro, ed., Intensional Mathematics (Amsterdam: North Holland 1985); and especially G. Boolos, The Logic of Provability (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1993), xxxiv and 226.
    • (1979) ‘De Re
    • Shahan, R.W.1    Swoyer, C.2
  • 13
    • 85063697535 scopus 로고
    • Whose published proceedings make up one issue of and include not only Kripkes ‘Semantical Considerations on Modal Logic,’ 83–94, but also Hintikkas ‘Modes of Modality,’
    • 1963. Acta Philosophical Fennica, 16: 65–82. Whose published proceedings make up one issue of and include not only Kripke's ‘Semantical Considerations on Modal Logic,’ 83–94, but also Hintikka's ‘Modes of Modality,’
    • (1963) Acta Philosophical Fennica , vol.16 , pp. 65-82
  • 14
    • 85063702002 scopus 로고
    • Reidel: Dordrecht, ‘Naming and Necessity: Lectures Given to the Princeton University Philosophy Colloquium, January,’ 1972), 253–355 and 763–9; reprinted with a new preface (Cambridge: Harvard University Press 1980)., and, eds
    • Davidson, D., and Harman, G., eds. 1970. Semantics of Natural Language Reidel: Dordrecht. ‘Naming and Necessity: Lectures Given to the Princeton University Philosophy Colloquium, January,’ in 1972), 253–355 and 763–9; reprinted with a new preface (Cambridge: Harvard University Press 1980).
    • (1970) Semantics of Natural Language
    • Davidson, D.1    Harman, G.2
  • 15
    • 85063704075 scopus 로고
    • ‘Modalities and Quantification,’ 33–64; Meaning and Necessity: A Study Semantics and Modal Logic (Chicago: University of Chicago Press 1947
    • 1946. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 11 ‘Modalities and Quantification,’ 33–64; Meaning and Necessity: A Study in Semantics and Modal Logic (Chicago: University of Chicago Press 1947).
    • (1946) Journal of Symbolic Logic , vol.11
  • 16
    • 33751174199 scopus 로고
    • with elaboration his paper ‘Modality and Description,’ Journal of Symbolic Logic13 (1948) 31–7. Smullyans priority for his particular response to Quine has been recognized by all competent and responsible commentators. See note 15 Linsky, ‘Reference, Essentialism, and Modality,’ and Føllesdal, ‘Quine on Modality,’ 183
    • 1947. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 12: 139–41.; with elaboration in his paper ‘Modality and Description,’ Journal of Symbolic Logic13 (1948) 31–7. Smullyan's priority for his particular response to Quine has been recognized by all competent and responsible commentators. See note 15 in Linsky, ‘Reference, Essentialism, and Modality,’ and Føllesdal, ‘Quine on Modality,’ 183.
    • (1947) Journal of Symbolic Logic , vol.12 , pp. 139-141
  • 17
    • 85063703121 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reidel: Dordrecht, Thus the items are: (i) the compendium, ‘Modalities and Intensional Languages’; (ii) the ‘Comments’ later retitled ‘Reply to Professor Marcus’; and (iii) the edited ‘Discussion.’ They appear together the official proceedings volume, 1963), 77–96 (compendium), 97–104 (commentary), 105–16 (edited discussion). The same publisher had printed them 1962 Synthese a version that is textually virtually identical down to the placement of page breaks, (i) and (ii) a belated issue of the volume for 1961, and (iii) an issue of the volume for 1962. (There have been several later, separate reprintings of the different items, but these incorporate revisions, often substantial.) Two of the present editors of Synthese, J. Fetzer and P. Humphreys, have proposed publishing the unedited, verbatim transcript of the discussion, with a view to shedding light on some disputed issues of interpretation; but according to their account, one of the participants, Professor Marcus, has objected to circulation of copies of the transcript or the tape., ed
    • Wartofsky, M. W., ed. Proceedings of the Boston Colloquium for the Philosophy of Science 1961/1962 Reidel: Dordrecht. Thus the items are: (i) the compendium, ‘Modalities and Intensional Languages’; (ii) the ‘Comments’ later retitled ‘Reply to Professor Marcus’; and (iii) the edited ‘Discussion.’ They appear together in the official proceedings volume, 1963), 77–96 (compendium), 97–104 (commentary), 105–16 (edited discussion). The same publisher had printed them in 1962 in Synthese in a version that is textually virtually identical down to the placement of page breaks, (i) and (ii) in a belated issue of the volume for 1961, and (iii) in an issue of the volume for 1962. (There have been several later, separate reprintings of the different items, but these incorporate revisions, often substantial.) Two of the present editors of Synthese, J. Fetzer and P. Humphreys, have proposed publishing the unedited, verbatim transcript of the discussion, with a view to shedding light on some disputed issues of interpretation; but according to their account, one of the participants, Professor Marcus, has objected to circulation of copies of the transcript or the tape.
    • Proceedings of the Boston Colloquium for the Philosophy of Science 1961/1962
    • Wartofsky, M.W.1
  • 18
    • 85063700664 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press, These are the closing words of Kripke, ‘Is There a Problem about Substitutional Quantification?’ in. The fallacy recurs again and again other contexts the literature. See B. J. Copeland, ‘On When a Semantics Is Not a Semantics: Some Reasons for Disliking the Routley-Meyer Semantics for Relevance Logic,’ Journal of Philosophical Logic8 (1979), and, eds
    • Evans, G., and McDowell, J., eds. 1976. Essays in Semantics 399–413. Oxford: Oxford University Press. These are the closing words of Kripke, ‘Is There a Problem about Substitutional Quantification?’ in. The fallacy recurs again and again in other contexts in the literature. See B. J. Copeland, ‘On When a Semantics Is Not a Semantics: Some Reasons for Disliking the Routley-Meyer Semantics for Relevance Logic,’ Journal of Philosophical Logic8 (1979)
    • (1976) Essays in Semantics , pp. 399-413
    • Evans, G.1    McDowell, J.2
  • 19
    • 0004327725 scopus 로고
    • Reidel: Dordrecht, Notably the Barcan or Carnap-Barcan formulas, which give formal expression to F. P. Ramseys odd idea that whatever possibly exists actually exists, and whatever actually exists necessarily exists. (The ‘Barcan’ label is the more customary, the ‘Carnap-Barcan’ label the more historically accurate according to N. Cocchiarella, ‘Philosophical Perspectives on Quantification Tense and Modal Logic,’ II 309–53, which also explains the connection with Ramsey.) If these formulas are rejected, one must distinguish a things having a property necessarily (for every possible world it exists there and has the property there) from its having the property essentially (for every possible world, if it exists there, then it has the property there). I have slurred over this distinction so far, and will for the most part continue to do so., and, eds
    • Gabbay, D., and Guenthner, F., eds. 1984. Handbook of Philosophical Logic Reidel: Dordrecht. Notably the Barcan or Carnap-Barcan formulas, which give formal expression to F. P. Ramsey's odd idea that whatever possibly exists actually exists, and whatever actually exists necessarily exists. (The ‘Barcan’ label is the more customary, the ‘Carnap-Barcan’ label the more historically accurate according to N. Cocchiarella, ‘Philosophical Perspectives on Quantification in Tense and Modal Logic,’ in II 309–53, which also explains the connection with Ramsey.) If these formulas are rejected, one must distinguish a thing's having a property necessarily (for every possible world it exists there and has the property there) from its having the property essentially (for every possible world, if it exists there, then it has the property there). I have slurred over this distinction so far, and will for the most part continue to do so.
    • (1984) Handbook of Philosophical Logic
    • Gabbay, D.1    Guenthner, F.2
  • 20
    • 85063698032 scopus 로고
    • As shown by examples the opening section of ‘Reference and Modality.’ This point seems to be conceded even by some who otherwise take an uncritically positive view of the compendium, as the review by G. Forbes, 336–9. The last sections of ‘Is There a Problem about Substitutional Quantification?’ effect point out that the claim that the ordinary language ‘there is’ its typical uses is a ‘substitutional quantifier’ devoid of ‘ontological commitment’ is absurd, since ‘ontological commitment’ is by definition whatever it is that the ordinary language ‘there is’ its typical uses conveys
    • 1995. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 36 As shown by examples in the opening section of ‘Reference and Modality.’ This point seems to be conceded even by some who otherwise take an uncritically positive view of the compendium, as in the review by G. Forbes, 336–9. The last sections of ‘Is There a Problem about Substitutional Quantification?’ in effect point out that the claim that the ordinary language ‘there is’ in its typical uses is a ‘substitutional quantifier’ devoid of ‘ontological commitment’ is absurd, since ‘ontological commitment’ is by definition whatever it is that the ordinary language ‘there is’ in its typical uses conveys.
    • (1995) Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic , vol.36
  • 22
    • 85063697291 scopus 로고
    • ‘Essentialism Modal Logic,’ 90–6. And about the same time we find even the usually acute Linsky (editorial introduction, 9) writing: Terence Parsons bases his search for the essentialist commitments of modal logic on Kripkes semantics, and he comes up (happily) empty-handed. He finds modal logic uncontaminated. The continuation of this passage better agrees with Parsons’ own account of his work and its bearing on Quines critique
    • 1967. Noûs, 1 ‘Essentialism in Modal Logic,’ 90–6. And about the same time we find even the usually acute Linsky (editorial introduction, 9) writing: “Terence Parsons bases his search for the essentialist commitments of modal logic on Kripke's semantics, and he comes up (happily) empty-handed. He finds modal logic uncontaminated.” The continuation of this passage better agrees with Parsons’ own account of his work and its bearing on Quine's critique.
    • (1967) Noûs , vol.1
  • 23
    • 85063700622 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Wartofsky, 90–2. It is just conceivable that this is deliberate exaggeration for effect, a rhetorical flourish rather than a serious exegetical hypothesis. ‘Essentialism Modal Logic’ cites some other authors who have written a similar vein about the example
    • See Wartofsky, 90–2. It is just conceivable that this is deliberate exaggeration for effect, a rhetorical flourish rather than a serious exegetical hypothesis. ‘Essentialism in Modal Logic’ cites some other authors who have written in a similar vein about the example.
  • 25
    • 85063703352 scopus 로고
    • An earlier paper by the author of the compendium, ‘Extensionality,’ 55–62, reprinted Linsky, ed., gives a more concise statement of the response its last paragraph, where a footnote acknowledges the authors teacher Frederic Fitch. The latter, his ‘The Problem of the Morning Star and the Evening Star,’ Philosophy of Science16 (1949) 137–41, and ‘Attribute and Class,’ M. Farber, ed., Philosophic Thought France and the United States (Buffalo: University Press 1950), 640–7, acknowledges Smullyan. (See footnote 4 the former, footnote 12 the latter, and the text to which they are attached
    • 1960. Mind, 69 An earlier paper by the author of the compendium, ‘Extensionality,’ 55–62, reprinted in Linsky, ed., gives a more concise statement of the response in its last paragraph, where a footnote acknowledges the author's teacher Frederic Fitch. The latter, in his ‘The Problem of the Morning Star and the Evening Star,’ Philosophy of Science16 (1949) 137–41, and ‘Attribute and Class,’ in M. Farber, ed., Philosophic Thought in France and the United States (Buffalo: University Press 1950), 640–7, acknowledges Smullyan. (See footnote 4 in the former, footnote 12 in the latter, and the text to which they are attached.)
    • (1960) Mind , vol.69
  • 26
    • 0004221781 scopus 로고
    • New York: MacMillan, The major one being P. Weiss, ed., six volumes, and the minor one the collection of survey articles, Contemporary Philosophy, four volumes (Firenze: Editrice Nuova Italia 1968). The former contains Prior, ‘Logic, Modal,’ V 5–12; while the latter contains Marcus, ‘Modal Logic,’ 87–101. The conference talks are to be found the previously cited proceedings, Marcus’ ‘Classes and Attributes Extended Modal Systems,’ 123–36, and Priors ‘Is the Concept of Referential Opacity Really Necessary?,’ 189–99. Another advocate of closely related ideas has been J. Myhill., ed
    • Klibansky, R., ed. 1967. The Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol. I, New York: MacMillan. The major one being P. Weiss, ed., six volumes, and the minor one the collection of survey articles, Contemporary Philosophy, four volumes (Firenze: Editrice Nuova Italia 1968). The former contains Prior, ‘Logic, Modal,’ V 5–12; while the latter contains Marcus, ‘Modal Logic,’ 87–101. The conference talks are to be found in the previously cited proceedings, Marcus’ ‘Classes and Attributes in Extended Modal Systems,’ 123–36, and Prior's ‘Is the Concept of Referential Opacity Really Necessary?,’ 189–99. Another advocate of closely related ideas has been J. Myhill.
    • (1967) The Encyclopedia of Philosophy , vol.1
    • Klibansky, R.1
  • 27
    • 85063700459 scopus 로고
    • La Salle: Open Court, Let me not fail to cite chapter and verse myself. For the most relevant pages of the most recently reprinted work, see
    • 1985. The Philosophy of Logical Atomism 113–5. La Salle: Open Court. Let me not fail to cite chapter and verse myself. For the most relevant pages of the most recently reprinted work, see
    • (1985) The Philosophy of Logical Atomism , pp. 113-115
  • 28
    • 85063702888 scopus 로고
    • Reply to Sellare, Davidson and Hintikka, 338. This formulation is the earliest adequate one known to me, the rebuttal even the 1961 version of ‘Reference and Modality’ being inadequate
    • 1969. Reply to Sellare, in Davidson and Hintikka, 338. This formulation is the earliest adequate one known to me, the rebuttal even in the 1961 version of ‘Reference and Modality’ being inadequate.
    • (1969)
  • 30
    • 85063705742 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fitch, ‘The Problem of the Morning Star and the Evening Star,’ explicitly claims that Quines contention is clearly false if the key expression are taken to be names
    • Fitch, ‘The Problem of the Morning Star and the Evening Star,’ explicitly claims that Quine's contention is “clearly” false if the key expression are taken to be names.
  • 35
    • 85063700311 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Quine surely means that (12a’) is not just a linguistic empirical discovery but a properly astronomical empirical discovery. By contrast, Marcus Wartofsky, distinguishes such linguistic inquiry as leads to discoveries like (12a’) from properly empirical methods such as lead to discoveries about orbits
    • Wartofsky. 115101 Quine surely means that (12a’) is not just a linguistic empirical discovery but a properly astronomical empirical discovery. By contrast, Marcus in Wartofsky, distinguishes “such linguistic” inquiry as leads to discoveries like (12a’) from “properly empirical” methods such as lead to discoveries about orbits.
    • , vol.115 , pp. 101
    • Wartofsky1
  • 36
    • 0346748226 scopus 로고
    • New York: Humanities Press, The quotation from Quine is from ‘Reference and Modality,’ antepenultimate paragraph. The work of Føllesdal where it is quoted is ‘Quantification into Causal Contexts,’ II 263–74; reprinted Linsky, ed., 52–62. Føllesdals final footnote suggests that causal essentialism is better off than logical essentialism, and that Quines own proposal to treat dispositions as inhering structural traits of objects is a form of causal essentialism. and, eds
    • Cohen, R. S., and Wartofsky, M. W., eds. 1965. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science New York: Humanities Press. The quotation from Quine is from ‘Reference and Modality,’ antepenultimate paragraph. The work of Føllesdal where it is quoted is ‘Quantification into Causal Contexts,’ in II 263–74; reprinted in Linsky, ed., 52–62. Føllesdal's final footnote suggests that “causal essentialism” is better off than “logical essentialism,” and that Quine's own proposal to treat dispositions as inhering structural traits of objects is a form of “causal essentialism.
    • (1965) Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science
    • Cohen, R.S.1    Wartofsky, M.W.2
  • 37
    • 85063699433 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 91ff. This echoes Fitch, ‘Attribute and Class,’ where it is said (553) that: Smullyan has shown that there is no real difficulty if the phrase [sic] ‘the Morning Star’ and ‘the Evening Star’ are regarded either as proper names or as descriptive phrases Russells sense. The syntactic ambiguity this last formulation as to whether Russells sense is supposed to modify proper names as well as descriptive phrases matches the ambiguity the formulation quoted earlier as to whether Russellian is supposed to modify the distinction between proper names and descriptions as well as theory of descriptions. The ambiguity is appropriate, since the theory of names question is neo-Russellian
    • Klibansky. 91ff. This echoes Fitch, ‘Attribute and Class,’ where it is said (553) that: “Smullyan has shown that there is no real difficulty if the phrase [sic] ‘the Morning Star’ and ‘the Evening Star’ are regarded either as proper names or as descriptive phrases in Russell's sense.” The syntactic ambiguity in this last formulation as to whether “in Russell's sense” is supposed to modify “proper names” as well as “descriptive phrases” matches the ambiguity in the formulation quoted earlier as to whether “Russellian” is supposed to modify “the distinction between proper names and descriptions” as well as “theory of descriptions.” The ambiguity is appropriate, since the theory of names in question is neo-Russellian.
    • Klibansky1
  • 39
    • 78649795317 scopus 로고
    • See Follesdal, §17,96ff. of doctoral dissertation, Harvard, reprinted as Filosofiske Problemer (Oslo: Universitets- forlaget 1966). Church, review the Journal of Symbolic Logic 15 (1950) 63. Both address Smullyan and Fitch
    • 1961. Referential Opacity and Modal Logic, 32 See Follesdal, §17,96ff. of doctoral dissertation, Harvard, reprinted as Filosofiske Problemer (Oslo: Universitets- forlaget 1966). Church, review in the Journal of Symbolic Logic 15 (1950) 63. Both address Smullyan and Fitch.
    • (1961) Referential Opacity and Modal Logic , vol.32
  • 40
    • 85063697903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See the discussion in ‘Naming and Necessity,’ and J. Searle's article on ‘Proper Names and Descriptions’ in Weiss, VI 487–91. The doctrines in ‘Naming and Necessity’ were first presented in seminars in 1963–64, and whereas that work apologizes for being spotty in its coverage of the literature of the succeeding years, it is pretty thorough in its discussion of the relevant literature (work of P. Geach, P. Strawson, P. Ziff, and others) from the immediately preceding years
    • Searle discusses work of yet another contributor, Elizabeth Anscombe
    • 1960. For work on difficulties with the Fregean theory in the 1950s and early s, see the discussion in ‘Naming and Necessity,’ and J. Searle's article on ‘Proper Names and Descriptions’ in Weiss, VI 487–91. The doctrines in ‘Naming and Necessity’ were first presented in seminars in 1963–64, and whereas that work apologizes for being spotty in its coverage of the literature of the succeeding years, it is pretty thorough in its discussion of the relevant literature (work of P. Geach, P. Strawson, P. Ziff, and others) from the immediately preceding years. (Searle discusses work of yet another contributor, Elizabeth Anscombe.)
    • 1960. For work on difficulties with the Fregean theory in the 1950s and early s
  • 41
    • 0040196904 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Basil Blackwell, chapter 3. Field also cites several expressions of the same or related views from the earlier literature, and such citations could a sense be carried all the way back to the ‘principle of predication’ G. H. von Wright, An Essay Modal Logic (Amsterdam: North Holland 1951
    • 1989. Realism, Mathematics and Modality Oxford: Basil Blackwell. In, chapter 3. Field also cites several expressions of the same or related views from the earlier literature, and such citations could in a sense be carried all the way back to the ‘principle of predication’ in G. H. von Wright, An Essay in Modal Logic (Amsterdam: North Holland 1951).
    • (1989) Realism, Mathematics and Modality
  • 42
    • 1642603993 scopus 로고
    • Dordrecht: Kluwer, In. Cresswell also cites several expressions of the same or related views from the earlier literature, and such citations could a sense be carried all the way back to D. K. Lewis, ‘Anselm and Actuality,’ Nous 4 (1970) 175–88. This is the earliest relevant publication known to me, but its author has suggested that there was very early unpublished work on the topic by A. P. Hazen and by D. Kaplan. The parallel phenomenon for tense place of mood was noted even earlier by P. Geach
    • 1990. Entities and Indices Dordrecht: Kluwer. In. Cresswell also cites several expressions of the same or related views from the earlier literature, and such citations could in a sense be carried all the way back to D. K. Lewis, ‘Anselm and Actuality,’ Nous 4 (1970) 175–88. This is the earliest relevant publication known to me, but its author has suggested that there was very early unpublished work on the topic by A. P. Hazen and by D. Kaplan. The parallel phenomenon for tense in place of mood was noted even earlier by P. Geach.
    • (1990) Entities and Indices
  • 43
    • 0004131117 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press, See Prior, chapter VII, and among later work R. H. Thomason, ‘Combinations of Tense and Modality,’ Gabbay and Guenthner, 135–65. The purely modal part is also for virtually all the workers there cited, as well as later ones like A. Zanardo
    • 1967. Past, Present, and Future Vol. S5, Oxford: Clarendon Press. See Prior, chapter VII, and among later work R. H. Thomason, ‘Combinations of Tense and Modality,’ in Gabbay and Guenthner, 135–65. The purely modal part is also for virtually all the workers there cited, as well as later ones like A. Zanardo.
    • (1967) Past, Present, and Future , vol.S5
  • 44
    • 0041879834 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Basil Blackwell, ‘A Theory of Conditionals,’ 98–112. This feature becomes even more prominent later work on the same topic by D. K. Lewis and others., ed
    • Rescher, N., ed. 1968. Studies in Logical Theory Oxford: Basil Blackwell. ‘A Theory of Conditionals,’ in 98–112. This feature becomes even more prominent in later work on the same topic by D. K. Lewis and others.
    • (1968) Studies in Logical Theory
    • Rescher, N.1
  • 45
    • 85063705238 scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press, Unfortunately this comes the form of a review of a book by a third party, and is subject to the limitations of such a form. The third party is Linsky; the book is his; the review is by Marcus, Philosophical Review87 497–504. The three quotations to follow come from 498, 501, and
    • 1977. Names and Descriptions 502–3. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Unfortunately this comes in the form of a review of a book by a third party, and is subject to the limitations of such a form. The third party is Linsky; the book is his; the review is by Marcus, Philosophical Review87 497–504. The three quotations to follow come from 498, 501, and
    • (1977) Names and Descriptions , pp. 502-503
  • 46
    • 85063702648 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • this connection mention may be made of one serious historical inaccuracy—of a kind extremely common when authors quote themselves from memory decades after the fact—to be found the book review, where it is said that the compendium maintained that unlike different but coreferential descriptions, two proper names of the same object were intersubstitutable modal contexts (502). actual fact, the compendium it is, repeatedly, asserted that two proper names of the same object are intersubstitutable all, contexts
    • In this connection mention may be made of one serious historical inaccuracy—of a kind extremely common when authors quote themselves from memory decades after the fact—to be found in the book review, where it is said that the compendium maintained “that unlike different but coreferential descriptions, two proper names of the same object were intersubstitutable in modal contexts” (502). In actual fact, in the compendium it is repeatedly asserted that two proper names of the same object are intersubstitutable in all contexts.
  • 47
    • 0003459945 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Ma: MIT Press, While the early Marcus followed Smullyan, the later Marcus has developed response to Kripke an idiosyncratic theory that may be described as intermediate degree of Russellianism between Salmons and Smullyans. See her ‘Some Revisionary Proposals about Belief and Believing,’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research50 (Supplement
    • 1986. Frege's Puzzle 133–53. Cambridge, Ma: MIT Press. While the early Marcus followed Smullyan, the later Marcus has developed in response to Kripke an idiosyncratic theory that may be described as intermediate in degree of Russellianism between Salmon's and Smullyan's. See her ‘Some Revisionary Proposals about Belief and Believing,’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research50 (Supplement)
    • (1986) Frege's Puzzle , pp. 133-153
  • 49
    • 85063704461 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ‘Basic Modal Logic,’ Gabbay and Guenthner, 1- 88. Other articles the same work, some of which I have already cited, do recognize the importance of the distinction
    • Bull, R. A., and Segerberg, K., ‘Basic Modal Logic,’ in Gabbay and Guenthner, 1- 88. Other articles in the same work, some of which I have already cited, do recognize the importance of the distinction.
    • Bull, R.A.1    Segerberg, K.2
  • 50
    • 0012537417 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press, It would be out of place to enter into technicalities here. See J. Burgess and G. Rosen
    • 1997. A Subject with No Object Oxford: Oxford University Press. It would be out of place to enter into technicalities here. See J. Burgess and G. Rosen,.
    • (1997) A Subject with No Object
  • 51
    • 85063706165 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • actual fact, on Kripkes theory, for instance, a name can be given to any object that can be described, not excluding mathematical objects. But again see Burgess and Rosen. (The theory of R Geach probably deserves and the theory of M. Devitt certainly deserves the label ‘causal,’ and does have nominalistic implications
    • In actual fact, on Kripke's theory, for instance, a name can be given to any object that can be described, not excluding mathematical objects. But again see Burgess and Rosen. (The theory of R Geach probably deserves and the theory of M. Devitt certainly deserves the label ‘causal,’ and does have nominalistic implications.)
  • 52
    • 84928286064 scopus 로고
    • For comparatively moderate instance see the review by S. Lavine
    • 1995. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 46: 267–74. For comparatively moderate instance see the review by S. Lavine
    • (1995) British Journal for the Philosophy of Science , vol.46 , pp. 267-274
  • 53
    • 33748188403 scopus 로고
    • For an extreme instance see J. Hintikka and G. Sandu, ‘The Fallacies of the New Theory of Reference,’ 245–83. This work acknowledges no important differences among: (i) the neo-Russellian theory of Smullyan as expounded by the early Marcus (which incidentally is erroneously attributed to Marcus as something original, ignoring the real authors Smullyan and Russell); (ii) theories adopted reaction to Kripke by the later Marcus; and (iii) the theory of Kripke
    • 1995. Synthese, 104 For an extreme instance see J. Hintikka and G. Sandu, ‘The Fallacies of the New Theory of Reference,’ 245–83. This work acknowledges no important differences among: (i) the neo-Russellian theory of Smullyan as expounded by the early Marcus (which incidentally is erroneously attributed to Marcus as something original, ignoring the real authors Smullyan and Russell); (ii) theories adopted in reaction to Kripke by the later Marcus; and (iii) the theory of Kripke.
    • (1995) Synthese , vol.104


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.