-
1
-
-
85064024477
-
-
For further discussion of these problems from within the context of a probabilistic theory of causation, Synthese 97 (1993,–64; ‘The Mishap at Reichenbach Fall: Singular vs. General Causation,’ Philosophical Studies781995 257–91; and ‘The Role of Contrast Causal and Explanatory Claims,’ Synthese (forthcoming). The current paper complements these earlier papers at least three ways: it presents the problems divested of the technical garb that makes them inaccessible to some readers; it emphasizes the common thread that is easily lost the more technical treatments; and it argues that these problems are not unique to the probabilistic theory of causation, but arise within any theory that characterizes causation as a binary relation
-
see my ‘A Generalized Probabilistic Theory of Causal Relevance,’. 335 For further discussion of these problems from within the context of a probabilistic theory of causation, Synthese 97 (1993,–64; ‘The Mishap at Reichenbach Fall: Singular vs. General Causation,’ Philosophical Studies781995 257–91; and ‘The Role of Contrast in Causal and Explanatory Claims,’ Synthese (forthcoming). The current paper complements these earlier papers in at least three ways: it presents the problems divested of the technical garb that makes them inaccessible to some readers; it emphasizes the common thread that is easily lost in the more technical treatments; and it argues that these problems are not unique to the probabilistic theory of causation, but arise within any theory that characterizes causation as a binary relation.
-
-
-
-
2
-
-
85064027575
-
-
‘Causal Laws and Effective Strategies,’ Noûs 13 1979–37
-
419 ‘Causal Laws and Effective Strategies,’ Noûs 13 1979–37
-
-
-
-
3
-
-
0004152755
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
1991. Probabilistic Causality Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (
-
(1991)
Probabilistic Causality
-
-
-
7
-
-
85064026836
-
-
Recall that we are assuming background conditions to be held fixed.
-
Recall that we are assuming background conditions to be held fixed.
-
-
-
-
8
-
-
85064025000
-
-
‘Statistics and Causal Inference,’ Journal of the American Statistical Association 81 (1986,–60
-
945 ‘Statistics and Causal Inference,’ Journal of the American Statistical Association 81 (1986,–60
-
-
-
-
9
-
-
58149417330
-
-
‘Estimating Causal Effects of Treatments Randomized and Nonrandomized Studies,’ Journal of Educational Psychology 66 (1974,–701. The view is also anticipated by I.J. Good (‘A Causal Calculus I,’ 11 [1961] 309), who has suggested that claims about the causal relevance of B for A are relative to probability distributions over the alternatives to B. Other theories of causation have taken the causal relation to involve more than two argument places; what is essential to the solution sketched here, however, is not merely the number of argument places, but the relativity of causation to an alternative causal factor
-
688 ‘Estimating Causal Effects of Treatments in Randomized and Nonrandomized Studies,’ Journal of Educational Psychology 66 (1974,–701. The view is also anticipated by I.J. Good (‘A Causal Calculus I,’ British Journal for the Philosophy of Science11 [1961] 309), who has suggested that claims about the causal relevance of B for A are relative to probability distributions over the alternatives to B. Other theories of causation have taken the causal relation to involve more than two argument places; what is essential to the solution sketched here, however, is not merely the number of argument places, but the relativity of causation to an alternative causal factor.
-
British Journal for the Philosophy of ScienceBAB
, pp. 688
-
-
-
10
-
-
85064028142
-
-
This presents a slight technical problem. Since will be zero for all but countably many values of x, it seems as though the values of the function f will be undefined almost everywhere. There are, however, generalizations of the standard definition of conditional probability that will allow us to have well-defined functions such as f. I prefer Kolmogorovs treatment of conditional probabilities as Radon-Nikodym derivatives. See the appendix to ‘A Generalized Probabilistic Theory of Causal Relevance’ for an overview
-
P(X = x) This presents a slight technical problem. Since will be zero for all but countably many values of x, it seems as though the values of the function f will be undefined almost everywhere. There are, however, generalizations of the standard definition of conditional probability that will allow us to have well-defined functions such as f. I prefer Kolmogorov's treatment of conditional probabilities as Radon-Nikodym derivatives. See the appendix to ‘A Generalized Probabilistic Theory of Causal Relevance’ for an overview.
-
P(X = x)
-
-
-
12
-
-
0004234303
-
-
Amsterdam: North-Holland, Other versions of this argument can be found P. Suppes, (E. Eells and E. Sober, ‘Probabilistic Causality and the Problem of Transitivity,’ Philosophy of Science50 (1983) 35–57; W. Salmon, Scientific Explanation and the Causal Structure of the World (Princeton: Princeton University Press 1984); and Eells
-
1970. A Probabilistic Theory of Causality Amsterdam: North-Holland. Other versions of this argument can be found in P. Suppes, (E. Eells and E. Sober, ‘Probabilistic Causality and the Problem of Transitivity,’ Philosophy of Science50 (1983) 35–57; W. Salmon, Scientific Explanation and the Causal Structure of the World (Princeton: Princeton University Press 1984); and Eells.
-
(1970)
A Probabilistic Theory of Causality
-
-
-
14
-
-
85064031080
-
-
I appeal to Eells, chapter six, interpreting ‘despite’ as describing negative causation at the singular level
-
I appeal to Eells, chapter six, in interpreting ‘despite’ as describing negative causation at the singular level.
-
-
-
-
15
-
-
3843100161
-
-
‘Referring to Events,’ Midwest Studies Philosophy 2 (1977,–9
-
90 ‘Referring to Events,’ Midwest Studies in Philosophy 2 (1977,–9
-
-
-
-
16
-
-
85064031053
-
6
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press, (chapter) applies modus tollens where Dretske applies modus ponens, concluding that causal contexts are not extensional. Note that the problem described by Dretske is somewhat different from the problem of the contrast class explanation, which receives its most well-known discussion chapter five of Bas van Fraassens The Scientific Image (Oxford: Clarendon Press 1980). the examples discussed by van Fraassen, the locus of contrast is the explanandum, or effect, rather than the explanans, or cause. For a discussion of the connection between the two problems, see my ‘The Role of Contrast Causal and Explanatory Claims.’,. In
-
Achinstein, Peter. 1983. “ 6 ”. In The Nature of Explanation Oxford: Oxford University Press. (chapter) applies modus tollens where Dretske applies modus ponens, concluding that causal contexts are not extensional. Note that the problem described by Dretske is somewhat different from the problem of the contrast class in explanation, which receives its most well-known discussion in chapter five of Bas van Fraassen's The Scientific Image (Oxford: Clarendon Press 1980). In the examples discussed by van Fraassen, the locus of contrast is the explanandum, or effect, rather than the explanans, or cause. For a discussion of the connection between the two problems, see my ‘The Role of Contrast in Causal and Explanatory Claims.’
-
(1983)
The Nature of Explanation
-
-
Achinstein, P.1
-
17
-
-
0004264817
-
-
Indianapolis: Hackett, The literature on this topic is vast, and I cannot even scratch the surface here. To my mind the best account of facts and events is J. Bennett
-
1988. Events and Their Names Indianapolis: Hackett. The literature on this topic is vast, and I cannot even scratch the surface here. To my mind the best account of facts and events is J. Bennett
-
(1988)
Events and Their Names
-
-
-
18
-
-
26444615966
-
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press, One exception is David Lewiss theory of events (‘Events,’ in); see the discussion section V below
-
1986. Philosophical Papers, Volume II 241–69. Oxford: Oxford University Press. One exception is David Lewis's theory of events (‘Events,’ in); see the discussion in section V below.
-
(1986)
Philosophical Papers, Volume II
, pp. 241-269
-
-
-
19
-
-
26444615966
-
-
‘Causation’ and ‘Postscripts to Causation’ 159–213
-
Philosophical Papers, Volume II ‘Causation’ and ‘Postscripts to “Causation”,’ 159–213
-
Philosophical Papers, Volume II
-
-
-
22
-
-
85064023437
-
-
‘Postscripts to Causation’ 211
-
Lewis. ‘Postscripts to “Causation”,’ 211
-
-
-
Lewis1
-
24
-
-
85064025129
-
-
Noûs 13 (1979,–76
-
455 Noûs 13 (1979,–76
-
-
-
-
26
-
-
85064025076
-
-
‘Events’
-
Lewis. ‘Events’
-
-
-
Lewis1
-
27
-
-
85064022973
-
Lewis does offer an ingenious account of cases such as Good's where a cause appears to lower the probability of its effect. I have argued elsewhere (‘The Mishap at Reichenbach Fall: Singular vs. General Causation’) that this account renders the truth of causal claims unacceptably sensitive to the details of how probabilities evolve with time
-
‘, Causation,’ 162,. In
-
‘Causation,’ 162. In Postscript B, 179–80 Lewis does offer an ingenious account of cases such as Good's where a cause appears to lower the probability of its effect. I have argued elsewhere (‘The Mishap at Reichenbach Fall: Singular vs. General Causation’) that this account renders the truth of causal claims unacceptably sensitive to the details of how probabilities evolve with time.
-
Postscript B, 179–80
-
-
-
28
-
-
85064025247
-
-
As of the time of this writing.
-
As of the time of this writing.
-
-
-
|