-
1
-
-
84876286337
-
Right and Left: Ideological Disobedience in Israel
-
Chaim Gans, “Right and Left: Ideological Disobedience in Israel,” (2002) 36 Israel Law Review 19.
-
(2002)
Israel Law Review
, vol.36
, pp. 19
-
-
Gans, C.1
-
2
-
-
85023117040
-
-
This was contained in an opinion and supplementary opinion given by us to the Military Advocate General, which were submitted by the Military Prosecution to the Supreme Court in H.C. 7622/02
-
This was contained in an opinion and supplementary opinion given by us to the Military Advocate General, which were submitted by the Military Prosecution to the Supreme Court in H.C. 7622/02, Zonshein v. Judge Advocate General 57(1) P.D. 726.
-
P.D
, vol.57
, Issue.1
, pp. 726
-
-
-
3
-
-
84901177932
-
Zonshein v. Judge Advocate General
-
See also the Supreme court English Translation in The citations below refer to the English translation in this issue
-
See also the Supreme court English Translation in Supreme Court “Zonshein v. Judge Advocate General,” (2002) 36 Israel Law Review 1. The citations below refer to the English translation in this issue.
-
(2002)
Israel Law Review
, vol.36
, pp. 1
-
-
-
5
-
-
84876294214
-
The Right to Civil Disobedience
-
Tel Aviv,The “Yesh Gvul” Movement and Siman Kri'a Books in Ishai and Dina Menuchin, eds see also Hebrew
-
see also Joseph Raz, “The Right to Civil Disobedience,” in Ishai and Dina Menuchin, eds. The Limits of Obedience (Tel Aviv,The “Yesh Gvul” Movement and Siman Kri'a Books, 1985), 51. [Hebrew].
-
(1985)
The Limits of Obedience
, pp. 51
-
-
Raz, J.1
-
9
-
-
85022994581
-
Objection - Political or Conscientious (or: Is there a Border between Civil Disobedience and Conscientious Objection)?
-
Jerusalem, Siman Kria in Yishai Menuchin, ed. Hebrew
-
David Heyd, “Objection - Political or Conscientious (or: Is there a Border between Civil Disobedience and Conscientious Objection)?” in Yishai Menuchin, ed., Democracy and Obedience (Jerusalem, Siman Kria, 1990) 87–89. [Hebrew]
-
(1990)
Democracy and Obedience
, pp. 87-89
-
-
Heyd, D.1
-
10
-
-
85023009632
-
-
Tel Aviv, Hakibbutz Mamuechad Hebrew
-
Chaim Gans, Obedience and Refusal (Tel Aviv, Hakibbutz Mamuechad, 1996) 120–125 [Hebrew].
-
(1996)
Obedience and Refusal
, pp. 120-125
-
-
Gans, C.1
-
11
-
-
4243507618
-
The Will to Power
-
New York, New York Gordon Press, Reprint Edition Anthony M. Ludovici, trans, in Oscar Levy ed “No, facts are precisely what there is not, only interpretations. We cannot establish any fact ‘in itself […] In so far as the word Tmowledge’ has any meaning, the world is knowable; but it is interpretable otherwise, it has no meaning behind it, but countless meanings -‘Perspectivism’. ” See Aphorism 15
-
“No, facts are precisely what there is not, only interpretations. We cannot establish any fact ‘in itself […] In so far as the word Tmowledge’ has any meaning, the world is knowable; but it is interpretable otherwise, it has no meaning behind it, but countless meanings -‘Perspectivism’. ” See Friedrich Nietzsche, “The Will to Power” Anthony M. Ludovici, trans, in Oscar Levy ed. The Complete Works of Friedrich Nietzsche, (New York, New York Gordon Press, Reprint Edition 1974) Vol. 14, Aphorism 15.
-
(1974)
The Complete Works of Friedrich Nietzsche
, vol.14
-
-
Nietzsche, F.1
-
12
-
-
0003488717
-
-
Searle drew a distinction between “brute facts” and “institutional facts” and stated that “institutional facts” are indeed facts, but that their existence is based upon the presence of a certain social organization. See London: Cambridge University Press
-
Searle drew a distinction between “brute facts” and “institutional facts” and stated that “institutional facts” are indeed facts, but that their existence is based upon the presence of a certain social organization. See John R. Searle, Speech Acts: An Essay in the Philosophy of Language (London: Cambridge University Press, 1994) 50–51.
-
(1994)
Speech Acts: An Essay in the Philosophy of Language
, pp. 50-51
-
-
Searle, J.R.1
-
14
-
-
0003662876
-
-
trans. A. M. Henderson T. Parsons, New York, The Citadel Press
-
Max Weber, The Theory of Social and Economic Organization (trans. A. M. Henderson T. Parsons, New York, The Citadel Press, 1964) 101.
-
(1964)
The Theory of Social and Economic Organization
, pp. 101
-
-
Weber, M.1
-
15
-
-
85004418327
-
-
Consolidated Version the margin caption of which reads “Power to exempt from or defer service”, provides: “The Minister of Defense may, by order, if he sees fit to do so for reasons connected with the size of the regular forces or reserve forces of the Israel Defense Forces, or for reasons connected with the requirements of education, security, settlement or the national economy or for family or other reasons (1) exempt a person of military age from the duty of regular service or reduce the period of his service; (2) exempt a person of military age from the duty of reserve service for a specific period or absolutely”
-
Defense Service Law (Consolidated Version) 1986, the margin caption of which reads “Power to exempt from or defer service”, provides: “The Minister of Defense may, by order, if he sees fit to do so for reasons connected with the size of the regular forces or reserve forces of the Israel Defense Forces, or for reasons connected with the requirements of education, security, settlement or the national economy or for family or other reasons (1) exempt a person of military age from the duty of regular service or reduce the period of his service; (2) exempt a person of military age from the duty of reserve service for a specific period or absolutely”.
-
(1986)
Defense Service Law
-
-
-
16
-
-
84879107414
-
-
The Supreme Court has held on a number of occasions that the term “other reasons” includes, in this context, reasons of conscience: H.C. 4062/95 26.7.95): H.C. 2700/96, Barnovsky v. Minister of Defense (unpublished 29.4.96
-
The Supreme Court has held on a number of occasions that the term “other reasons” includes, in this context, reasons of conscience: H.C. 4062/95, Epstein v. Minister of Defense (unpublished 26.7.95): H.C. 2700/96, Barnovsky v. Minister of Defense (unpublished 29.4.96)
-
unpublished
-
-
-
17
-
-
85023035988
-
-
H.C 1380/02
-
H.C 1380/02, Ben-Artzi v. Minister of Defense, 56(4) P.D. 476
-
P.D
, vol.56
, Issue.4
, pp. 476
-
-
-
20
-
-
85023157440
-
-
at From the judgment of the Military District Court, Central Command District, headed by the President of the Court, Col. Avi Levy: MT 151/03 hereinafter “the Five Refusniks”
-
From the judgment of the Military District Court, Central Command District, headed by the President of the Court, Col. Avi Levy: MT 151/03, The Military Attorney General v. Matar, at. 19 [hereinafter “the Five Refusniks”].
-
-
-
-
21
-
-
85023066967
-
-
at
-
P.D., at p. 28.
-
P.D
, pp. 28
-
-
-
22
-
-
85023027266
-
-
“Needless to say the same act can be both one of conscientious objection and of civil disobedience. Many of our actions are over-determined in the sense that we have plural and various motives for them”. Excerption: a letter written by Prof. Yosef Raz to Adv. Sfarad in relation to the Zonshein case and was submitted to the High Court of Justice
-
“Needless to say the same act can be both one of conscientious objection and of civil disobedience. Many of our actions are over-determined in the sense that we have plural and various motives for them”. Excerption: a letter written by Prof. Yosef Raz to Adv. Sfarad in relation to the Zonshein case and was submitted to the High Court of Justice, P.D.
-
P.D
-
-
-
23
-
-
85023152895
-
-
at fn
-
Gans, P.D., at fn. 45.
-
P.D
, pp. 45
-
-
Gans1
-
25
-
-
85023138560
-
Stealing the Bomb - The Nature of Justifications
-
For a review of the literature on this matter, see particularly [Hebrew], as well as the following sources, mentioned there
-
For a review of the literature on this matter, see particularly Paul H. Robinson, “Stealing the Bomb - The Nature of Justifications”, (1999) 22 Tel Aviv University Law Review 65. [Hebrew], as well as the following sources, mentioned there.
-
(1999)
Tel Aviv University Law Review
, vol.22
, pp. 65
-
-
Robinson, P.H.1
-
26
-
-
25444480376
-
-
For the English discussion, see
-
For the English discussion, see Gladstone William (1984) 78 Cr. App. R. 276
-
(1984)
Cr. App. R
, vol.78
, pp. 276
-
-
William, G.1
-
27
-
-
85023070596
-
-
Dadson (1850) 4 Cox C.C. 358
-
(1850)
Cox C.C
, vol.4
, pp. 358
-
-
Dadson1
-
28
-
-
85023077811
-
-
The American Model Penal Code makes use of formulae of “reason” in defining all the justification defenses: the perpetrator is justified if he believes that his acts are necessary for the purpose of the defense (Model Penal Code § 3.02(1), § 3.03(3)(a), § 3.04(1), § 3.05(l)(b), § 3.06(1) and § 3.07(1))
-
Thain (1985) 11 NI 31. The American Model Penal Code makes use of formulae of “reason” in defining all the justification defenses: the perpetrator is justified if he believes that his acts are necessary for the purpose of the defense (Model Penal Code § 3.02(1), § 3.03(3)(a), § 3.04(1), § 3.05(l)(b), § 3.06(1) and § 3.07(1)).
-
(1985)
NI
, vol.11
, pp. 31
-
-
Thain1
-
29
-
-
84928439492
-
Notes on the Structure of a Theory of Excuses
-
See also at 489, with attention to the argument for viewing the mental element as an essential component of the defense
-
See also Michael Corrado, “Notes on the Structure of a Theory of Excuses,” (1991) 82 Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology 465, at 489, with attention to the argument for viewing the mental element as an essential component of the defense
-
(1991)
Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology
, vol.82
, pp. 465
-
-
Corrado, M.1
-
30
-
-
84935457198
-
The Perplexing Borders of Justification and Excuse
-
emphasizing that modern laws usually require subjective belief in the existence of a defense of justification
-
Kent Greenawalt, “The Perplexing Borders of Justification and Excuse,” (1984) 84 Columbia Law Review 144, emphasizing that modern laws usually require subjective belief in the existence of a defense of justification
-
(1984)
Columbia Law Review
, vol.84
, pp. 144
-
-
Greenawalt, K.1
-
31
-
-
0007540494
-
-
St. Paul, Minnesota, West, second edition arguing that in order to enjoy the benefit of the defense it is necessary to act upon achieving the particular purpose stated there
-
Wayne LaFave and Austin Scott, The Criminal Law (St. Paul, Minnesota, West, second edition 1986) 685 arguing that in order to enjoy the benefit of the defense it is necessary to act upon achieving the particular purpose stated there
-
(1986)
The Criminal Law
, pp. 685
-
-
LaFave, W.1
Scott, A.2
-
33
-
-
0043179608
-
Competing Theories of Justification: Deeds vs. Reasons
-
in A Simester & A.T.H. Smith, eds. See the contrary opinion of Paul Robinson in his above article as well as Oxford, Clarendon Press
-
See the contrary opinion of Paul Robinson in his above article as well as Paul H. Robinson, “Competing Theories of Justification: Deeds vs. Reasons” in A Simester & A.T.H. Smith, eds., Harm and Culpability, (Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1996) 45–70.
-
(1996)
Harm and Culpability
, pp. 45-70
-
-
Robinson, P.H.1
-
34
-
-
85023068796
-
-
Thus, for example, a person defending a charge of assault under Section 34(m) of the on the ground that he is a police officer and that the assault enabled him to implement his power of arrest, enjoys a defense of justification, and therefore whoever helps him is also justified
-
Thus, for example, a person defending a charge of assault under Section 34(m) of the Israel Penal Law, 1977, on the ground that he is a police officer and that the assault enabled him to implement his power of arrest, enjoys a defense of justification, and therefore whoever helps him is also justified.
-
(1977)
Israel Penal Law
-
-
-
35
-
-
85023068796
-
-
In contrast, a person defending a charge of assault under Section 34(h) of the on the grounds of insanity, may only enjoy the benefit of an excuse and therefore anyone assisting him is not exempt from liability. This distinction has additional diverse ramifications. Thus, for example, the person being assaulted by the assailant police officer is not entitled to defend himself in accordance with the parameters of self-defense set out in Section 34(j) of the Law, but at the most in accordance with the more stringent parameters of the defense of necessity set out in Section 34(k). In contrast, a person attacked by an insane attacker is entitled to defend himself in accordance with the parameters of self-defense
-
In contrast, a person defending a charge of assault under Section 34(h) of the Israel Penal Law, 1977, on the grounds of insanity, may only enjoy the benefit of an excuse and therefore anyone assisting him is not exempt from liability. This distinction has additional diverse ramifications. Thus, for example, the person being assaulted by the assailant police officer is not entitled to defend himself in accordance with the parameters of self-defense set out in Section 34(j) of the Law, but at the most in accordance with the more stringent parameters of the defense of necessity set out in Section 34(k). In contrast, a person attacked by an insane attacker is entitled to defend himself in accordance with the parameters of self-defense.
-
(1977)
Israel Penal Law
-
-
-
37
-
-
85023147012
-
-
The Military Court stated in the verdict given in the case of the five persons refusing to serve
-
The Military Court stated in the verdict given in the case of the five persons refusing to serve Israel Penal Law, n. 19
-
Israel Penal Law
, Issue.19
-
-
-
38
-
-
85023024227
-
-
at He thus argues that “a humanist can justify the objection to serve in the Territories and simultaneously justify the punishment of the objectors. This is possible if the act of objection is performed not (or not only) as an act of conscientious objection, but also as an act of civil disobedience, i.e. if the act is not only motivated by principled refusal to participate in the crimes of the Occupation, but also serves as a means of attaining political goals such as protesting the government's occupation policy, interfering with it or even overturning it”
-
Gans, Israel Penal Law, at 48. He thus argues that “a humanist can justify the objection to serve in the Territories and simultaneously justify the punishment of the objectors. This is possible if the act of objection is performed not (or not only) as an act of conscientious objection, but also as an act of civil disobedience, i.e. if the act is not only motivated by principled refusal to participate in the crimes of the Occupation, but also serves as a means of attaining political goals such as protesting the government's occupation policy, interfering with it or even overturning it”.
-
Israel Penal Law
, pp. 48
-
-
Gans1
-
42
-
-
85023063282
-
-
Heyd proposed a criterion for the distinction between an act of civil disobedience and an act of conscientious objection: “the more selective the refusal and the more specific its boundaries, the more likely it is that it belongs to the sphere of conscientious objection. In contrast, global refusal is by nature an expression of political protest, the purpose of which exceeds the boundaries of preserving the blamelessness of the individual.” (p. 94). We are not convinced that Heyd's criterion is successful, as prima facie it follows from it that a pacifist performs an act of civil disobedience. In any event, Heyd's effort delineates the correct path in the opinion of anyone who believes that such a philosophical distinction is indeed of value: an attempt to examine motivations in accordance with the practices of their subjects
-
Israel Penal Law, Heyd proposed a criterion for the distinction between an act of civil disobedience and an act of conscientious objection: “the more selective the refusal and the more specific its boundaries, the more likely it is that it belongs to the sphere of conscientious objection. In contrast, global refusal is by nature an expression of political protest, the purpose of which exceeds the boundaries of preserving the blamelessness of the individual.” (p. 94). We are not convinced that Heyd's criterion is successful, as prima facie it follows from it that a pacifist performs an act of civil disobedience. In any event, Heyd's effort delineates the correct path in the opinion of anyone who believes that such a philosophical distinction is indeed of value: an attempt to examine motivations in accordance with the practices of their subjects.
-
Israel Penal Law
-
-
-
43
-
-
85023066392
-
-
July quoted in “If you are neutral in situations of injustice, you have chosen the side of the oppressor. If an elephant has his foot on the tail of a mouse and you say you are neutral, the mouse will not appreciate your neutrality.” www.uscathohc.org
-
“If you are neutral in situations of injustice, you have chosen the side of the oppressor. If an elephant has his foot on the tail of a mouse and you say you are neutral, the mouse will not appreciate your neutrality.” Archbishop Desmond Tutu, quoted in US Catholic, July 2003, p. 6. www.uscathohc.org.
-
(2003)
US Catholic
, pp. 6
-
-
Desmond Tutu, A.1
-
44
-
-
85023079125
-
Zonshein
-
It would seem that at least in one case the Supreme Court has identified conscientious objection with private conscientious objection and ignored “moral conscientious objection” (per in
-
It would seem that at least in one case the Supreme Court has identified conscientious objection with private conscientious objection and ignored “moral conscientious objection” (per President Barak in Zonshein, US Catholic, p. 8–10).
-
US Catholic
, pp. 8-10
-
-
Barak, P.1
-
45
-
-
85023076375
-
Military Court in the Five Refusniks
-
Likewise, in the verdict delivered by the there is a reference to the distinction between civil disobedience and general conscientious objection, without referring to the distinction between the two types of conscientious objection
-
Likewise, in the verdict delivered by the Military Court in the Five Refusniks, US Catholic, there is a reference to the distinction between civil disobedience and general conscientious objection, without referring to the distinction between the two types of conscientious objection.
-
US Catholic
-
-
-
46
-
-
85023110468
-
-
The sole sub-distinction drawn by the Military Court is that proposed by Gans, namely, between civil disobedience for purposes of persuasion on one hand, and civil disobedience for purposes of coercion on the other hand, see at
-
The sole sub-distinction drawn by the Military Court is that proposed by Gans, namely, between civil disobedience for purposes of persuasion on one hand, and civil disobedience for purposes of coercion on the other hand, see Gans, US Catholic, at 121.
-
US Catholic
, pp. 121
-
-
Gans1
-
47
-
-
85023117783
-
The Five Refusniks
-
The Military District Court stated:“[…] our feeling was that the accused made an effort to hide their intention to bring about a change in public opinion through their refusal and encourage many youths[…] to take steps, bringing about opposition to government policy and thereby its frustration”
-
The Military District Court stated:“[…] our feeling was that the accused made an effort to hide their intention to bring about a change in public opinion through their refusal and encourage many youths[…] to take steps, bringing about opposition to government policy and thereby its frustration”: The Five Refusniks, US Catholic, p. 72.
-
US Catholic
, pp. 72
-
-
-
48
-
-
85023110468
-
-
This strategy of defense is surprising, as Gans himself uses a different perception of the principle of generalization in a criticism, which he directs against Shlomo Avineri. In answer to Avineri's argument that selective refusal is flawed in that it does not meet the test of universality, Gans offers the following generalization: “[Objectors] can refuse to obey the laws prescribing […] acts of oppression in reliance upon a universal rule, applicable to every person, which forbids participation in acts of conquest and oppression of other people even if the majority supports such acts. This rule is universal because it makes a demand upon every person to disobey laws that mandate acts of oppression at
-
This strategy of defense is surprising, as Gans himself uses a different perception of the principle of generalization in a criticism, which he directs against Shlomo Avineri. In answer to Avineri's argument that selective refusal is flawed in that it does not meet the test of universality, Gans offers the following generalization: “[Objectors] can refuse to obey the laws prescribing […] acts of oppression in reliance upon a universal rule, applicable to every person, which forbids participation in acts of conquest and oppression of other people even if the majority supports such acts. This rule is universal because it makes a demand upon every person to disobey laws that mandate acts of oppression: Gans, US Catholic, at 27.
-
US Catholic
, pp. 27
-
-
Gans1
-
50
-
-
85023110468
-
-
at
-
US Catholic, at 52.
-
US Catholic
, pp. 52
-
-
-
51
-
-
85023110468
-
-
at
-
US Catholic, at 53.
-
US Catholic
, pp. 53
-
-
-
52
-
-
60949381961
-
Political Action: The Problem of Dirty Hands
-
For a founding discussion of the issue of “dirty hands”, see
-
For a founding discussion of the issue of “dirty hands”, see Michael Walzer, “Political Action: The Problem of Dirty Hands,” (1973) 2(2) Philosophy and Public Affairs 160, 180.
-
(1973)
Philosophy and Public Affairs
, vol.2
, Issue.2
-
-
Walzer, M.1
-
53
-
-
85023017139
-
Five Refusniks
-
at Significantly, not all those refusing to serve relied on this type of moral selfishness. Adam Maor, one of those refusing to serve who was convicted in the testified before the Military Court that “he was not refusing with the intention of changing the policy, he would have wanted everyone to think in accordance with his values, and he would have been happy if, hypothetically, had everyone refused.”
-
Significantly, not all those refusing to serve relied on this type of moral selfishness. Adam Maor, one of those refusing to serve who was convicted in the Five Refusniks (Philosophy and Public Affairs, at 25) testified before the Military Court that “he was not refusing with the intention of changing the policy, he would have wanted everyone to think in accordance with his values, and he would have been happy if, hypothetically, had everyone refused.”
-
Philosophy and Public Affairs
, pp. 25
-
-
-
58
-
-
0042378507
-
Some Main Problems of Deontic Logic
-
Dordrecht, D. Reidel in Risto Hilpinen, ed. One of the criticisms raised against using the Saul Kripke's semantics of possible worlds to model deontic logic, is that it follows from this semantic (in Kripke's S4 and S5 systems) that there is “a duty to ‘x or not-x’,” This very statement (that everyone is obliged to do “x or not x”) expresses, so it is asserted, a profound lack of understanding of the concept of duty
-
One of the criticisms raised against using the Saul Kripke's semantics of possible worlds to model deontic logic, is that it follows from this semantic (in Kripke's S4 and S5 systems) that there is “a duty to ‘x or not-x’,” [Jaako Hintikka, “Some Main Problems of Deontic Logic” in Risto Hilpinen, ed., Deontic Logic: Introductory and Systematic Readings (Dordrecht, D. Reidel, 1971) 58.] This very statement (that everyone is obliged to do “x or not x”) expresses, so it is asserted, a profound lack of understanding of the concept of duty.
-
(1971)
Deontic Logic: Introductory and Systematic Readings
, pp. 58
-
-
Hintikka, J.1
-
59
-
-
80054442755
-
-
Amsterdam, Rodopi See A. G. Cohen voiced a similarly constructed criticism against the moral theory of Rawls. In his view even a complete scoundrel may satisfy the criteria of Rawlsian justice (for example, by voting for a party which supports equality at the same time as gathering riches at the expense of others
-
See: Avi Sagi, Kirkegaard, Religion and Existence, The Voyage of The Self (Amsterdam, Rodopi, 2000) 75–78. A. G. Cohen voiced a similarly constructed criticism against the moral theory of Rawls. In his view even a complete scoundrel may satisfy the criteria of Rawlsian justice (for example, by voting for a party which supports equality at the same time as gathering riches at the expense of others).
-
(2000)
Kirkegaard, Religion and Existence, The Voyage of The Self
, pp. 75-78
-
-
Sagi, A.1
-
60
-
-
84937266898
-
Where the Action is: On the Site of Distributive Justice
-
See at 30
-
See Gerald A. Cohen, “Where the Action is: On the Site of Distributive Justice,” (1997) 26(1) Philosophy and Public Affairs 3, at 30.
-
(1997)
Philosophy and Public Affairs
, vol.26
, Issue.1
, pp. 3
-
-
Cohen, G.A.1
-
61
-
-
85023028579
-
-
Jerusalem, Shalem Publishers The Indian term satyagraha means “to adhere to truth”. Mahatma Ghandi used this term as the key principle of his political conception. Ghandi stressed that adherence to the truth expresses recognition of the fact that the truth is a supreme good, which cannot be achieved by violence, and that it is therefore necessary to apply to people's reason and heart prior to the struggle to achieve it. See Hebrew
-
The Indian term satyagraha means “to adhere to truth”. Mahatma Ghandi used this term as the key principle of his political conception. Ghandi stressed that adherence to the truth expresses recognition of the fact that the truth is a supreme good, which cannot be achieved by violence, and that it is therefore necessary to apply to people's reason and heart prior to the struggle to achieve it. See Yehoshua Weinstein, ed. Disobedience and Democracy (Jerusalem, Shalem Publishers, 1998) 112. [Hebrew]
-
(1998)
Disobedience and Democracy
, pp. 112
-
-
Weinstein, Y.1
-
62
-
-
32644466097
-
Michel Foucault's lecture delivered to the Architectural study Group on 14 March 1967
-
According to Michele Foucault, heterotopias are “a type of place outside of all places, even though they are in fact localizable.” Excerption
-
According to Michele Foucault, heterotopias are “a type of place outside of all places, even though they are in fact localizable.” Excerption: Michel Foucault's lecture delivered to the Architectural study Group on 14 March 1967,5 Architecture, Movement, Continuité 46–49 (1984).
-
(1984)
Architecture, Movement, Continuité
, vol.5
, pp. 46-49
-
-
-
63
-
-
85023127783
-
-
New York, W. W. Norton & Company
-
Henry David Thoreau, Walden;And, Resistance to Civil Government:Authoritative Texts, Journal, Reviews, and Essays in Criticism (New York, W. W. Norton & Company, 1992) 37.
-
(1992)
Walden;And, Resistance to Civil Government:Authoritative Texts, Journal, Reviews, and Essays in Criticism
, pp. 37
-
-
David Thoreau, H.1
-
64
-
-
0004003322
-
-
16 April The letter contains many references to a willingness to sacrifice, for example: “One who breaks an unjust law must do so openly, lovingly, and with a willingness to accept the penalty. I submit that an individual who breaks a law that conscience tells him is unjust and who willingly accepts the penalty of imprisonment in order to arouse the conscience of the community over its injustice, is in reality expressing the highest respect for law”
-
Martin Luther King, Letter from a Birmingham City Jail (16 April, 1963). The letter contains many references to a willingness to sacrifice, for example: “One who breaks an unjust law must do so openly, lovingly, and with a willingness to accept the penalty. I submit that an individual who breaks a law that conscience tells him is unjust and who willingly accepts the penalty of imprisonment in order to arouse the conscience of the community over its injustice, is in reality expressing the highest respect for law”.
-
(1963)
Letter from a Birmingham City Jail
-
-
Luther King, M.1
-
65
-
-
85023008499
-
-
Ahmedabad: Navajivan In Ghandi continues: “Although non-cooperation is the main weapon in the armory of Satyagraha, it should not be forgotten that it is after all only a means to secure the cooperation of the opponent consistently with truth and justice”. Singer states that: “Disobedience, and especially disobedience followed by acceptance of punishment, may make the majority realize that what is for it a matter of indifference is of great importance to others”
-
In Kripalani, Acharya J B., ed. Collected Works of Mahatma Ghandi:All Men Are Brothers. (Ahmedabad: Navajivan, 1958) 447, Ghandi continues: “Although non-cooperation is the main weapon in the armory of Satyagraha, it should not be forgotten that it is after all only a means to secure the cooperation of the opponent consistently with truth and justice”. Singer states that: “Disobedience, and especially disobedience followed by acceptance of punishment, may make the majority realize that what is for it a matter of indifference is of great importance to others”
-
(1958)
Collected Works of Mahatma Ghandi:All Men Are Brothers
, pp. 447
-
-
Kripalani, A.J.B.1
-
66
-
-
80054960013
-
Disobedience as a Plea For Reconsideration
-
in Hugo Adam Bedau, ed London, Routledge
-
P. Singer “Disobedience as a Plea For Reconsideration”, in Hugo Adam Bedau, ed. Civil Disobedience in Focus (London, Routledge 1994) 122.
-
(1994)
Civil Disobedience in Focus
, pp. 122
-
-
Singer, P.1
-
67
-
-
85023003865
-
-
This position is also accepted by some of those refusing to serve themselves. Thus, for example, Shomri Zameret stated, prior to entering prison: “The Court granted us a right when it sent us to prison, because the protest is effective when it is backed by a personal price” 21.1.04, B3 “Female refusniks are not sent to prison - is this a right or discrimination?” by Lily Galilee]. The women who refused to serve claimed that the fact that the army was less inclined to send them to prison undermined their ability to engage in political struggle. Thus, for example, Noah Levy stated: “Our refusal is a political act to change the consensus, and the boys say that if their refusal becomes an offence, their statement provides a greater kick, is more painful. They are right”
-
This position is also accepted by some of those refusing to serve themselves. Thus, for example, Shomri Zameret stated, prior to entering prison: “The Court granted us a right when it sent us to prison, because the protest is effective when it is backed by a personal price” [Ha'aretz, 21.1.04, B3 “Female refusniks are not sent to prison - is this a right or discrimination?” by Lily Galilee]. The women who refused to serve claimed that the fact that the army was less inclined to send them to prison undermined their ability to engage in political struggle. Thus, for example, Noah Levy stated: “Our refusal is a political act to change the consensus, and the boys say that if their refusal becomes an offence, their statement provides a greater kick, is more painful. They are right”.
-
Ha'aretz
-
-
-
69
-
-
85022993582
-
-
Military Court 3/57
-
Military Court 3/57 Military Prosecutor v. Malinki, 17 D. Ct. 90, pp. 213–214.
-
D. Ct
, vol.17
, Issue.90
, pp. 213-214
-
-
|