메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 28, Issue 4, 1998, Pages 527-555

Families, friends, and special obligations

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 85019638112     PISSN: 00455091     EISSN: 19110820     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1080/00455091.1998.10715984     Document Type: Note
Times cited : (39)

References (39)
  • 1
    • 85063701628 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The former are easily accounted for by reference to the marriage contract or some similar explicit exchange of vows. The latter cannot always be seen as clear examples of the voluntary entering of a relationship, especially when abortion and/or contraceptive devices are not readily available
    • My primary concern is with those familial relationships that do not appear, any cases, to be voluntarily entered
    • The obvious exceptions are spousal relationships and parental relationships to children (but not vice versa). The former are easily accounted for by reference to the marriage contract or some similar explicit exchange of vows. The latter cannot always be seen as clear examples of the voluntary entering of a relationship, especially when abortion and/or contraceptive devices are not readily available. My primary concern is with those familial relationships that do not appear, in any cases, to be voluntarily entered.
    • The obvious exceptions are spousal relationships and parental relationships to children (but not vice versa)
  • 2
    • 85063698078 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I will briefly consider this option in section II below.
    • I will briefly consider this option in section II below.
  • 3
    • 0003890812 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, A. John Simmons
    • 1979. Moral Principles and Political Obligations 13Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. A. John Simmons
    • (1979) Moral Principles and Political Obligations , pp. 13
  • 5
    • 0003890812 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Simmons, takes an obligation to be ‘a moral requirement generated by the performance of some voluntary act (or omission)’ (14). Thus my terminology is not any sense standard, but, I suggest, it is useful for the discussion of obligations to family members. However, my discussion of Belliotti section IV below, I will deviate from my own terminology, which is specifically rejected by Belliotti (see note 33 below
    • Moral Principles and Political Obligations Simmons, in, takes an obligation to be ‘a moral requirement generated by the performance of some voluntary act (or omission)’ (14). Thus my terminology is not in any sense standard, but, I suggest, it is useful for the discussion of obligations to family members. However, in my discussion of Belliotti in section IV below, I will deviate from my own terminology, which is specifically rejected by Belliotti (see note 33 below).
    • Moral Principles and Political Obligations
  • 7
    • 85063705234 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course it might be said that your nature and the nature of the act of throwing a life preserver to you are not sufficient to explain why I have the duty to throw that life preserver to you: we also need to state that I happened to be standing on the bank of the river. But notice that once I am in a position to throw that life preserver to you, your nature and the nature of the action provide sufficient explanation of my duty. On the other hand, even when I am in a position to give you ten dollars (I have the money and you are standing in front of me with your hand out), appeal to your nature and the nature of the action are not sufficient to explain or ground an obligation, unless we can appeal to a promise that I made to you. It might be responded that if we redescribe the action as an act of promise-keeping, then appeal to the nature of the act is sufficient to ground an obligation. However, this is not a normatively neutral redescription of the act: to say that it is an act of promise-keeping is to say that it is obligatory in so far as genuine promises generate obligations. However, there are difficulties here that I cannot address, and that need not be resolved for my purposes
    • Of course it might be said that your nature and the nature of the act of throwing a life preserver to you are not sufficient to explain why I have the duty to throw that life preserver to you: we also need to state that I happened to be standing on the bank of the river. But notice that once I am in a position to throw that life preserver to you, your nature and the nature of the action provide sufficient explanation of my duty. On the other hand, even when I am in a position to give you ten dollars (I have the money and you are standing in front of me with your hand out), appeal to your nature and the nature of the action are not sufficient to explain or ground an obligation, unless we can appeal to a promise that I made to you. It might be responded that if we redescribe the action as an act of promise-keeping, then appeal to the nature of the act is sufficient to ground an obligation. However, this is not a normatively neutral redescription of the act: to say that it is an act of promise-keeping is to say that it is obligatory in so far as genuine promises generate obligations. However, there are difficulties here that I cannot address, and that need not be resolved for my purposes.
  • 8
    • 85063697896 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • While special obligations are not so grounded. Promise-keeping and, as I will argue, obligations to intimates are grounded by the character of the relationship between obligor and obligee. I have left it open that other types of special obligations may be grounded on some fact other than the relationship between obligor and obligee, although all special obligations will be grounded by something other than or more than the
    • intrinsic nature of the obligee and the intrinsic character of the required action
    • I have characterized natural duties as grounded by the nature of the persons to whom the duties are owed, while special obligations are not so grounded. Promise-keeping and, as I will argue, obligations to intimates are grounded by the character of the relationship between obligor and obligee. I have left it open that other types of special obligations may be grounded on some fact other than the relationship between obligor and obligee, although all special obligations will be grounded by something other than or more than the intrinsic nature of the obligee and the intrinsic character of the required action.
    • I have characterized natural duties as grounded by the nature of the persons to whom the duties are owed
  • 9
    • 85063698713 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This fact about special obligations to intimates raises difficulties for my account that I will discuss section III, 2 below
    • This fact about special obligations to intimates raises difficulties for my account that I will discuss in section III, 2 below.
  • 10
    • 85063700646 scopus 로고
    • For a discussion of the voluntarist objection to associative or special obligations more generally, see Samuel Scheffler, ‘Families, Nations, and Strangers,’ The Lindley Lecture at the University of Kansas (October 17, For my response to Scheffler, see my ‘Associative Obligations, Voluntarism, and Equality,’ 77 (1996) 289–309
    • 1994. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly For a discussion of the voluntarist objection to associative or special obligations more generally, see Samuel Scheffler, ‘Families, Nations, and Strangers,’ The Lindley Lecture at the University of Kansas (October 17, For my response to Scheffler, see my ‘Associative Obligations, Voluntarism, and Equality,’ 77 (1996) 289–309.
    • (1994) Pacific Philosophical Quarterly
  • 11
    • 85063702731 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course, children may be required to care for older parents for any number of reasons, including utilitarian reasons. But such utilitarian reasons do not constitute special obligations: we have a general duty to promote or maximize well-being, and caring for parents may be a good or even the best way to fulfill such a duty. (If one is willing to view utilitarian duties as owed to other persons, then utilitarian duties are natural duties.) As I indicate in the next section, however, I am concerned to find the source of genuinely special obligations between family members.
    • Of course, children may be required to care for older parents for any number of reasons, including utilitarian reasons. But such utilitarian reasons do not constitute special obligations: we have a general duty to promote or maximize well-being, and caring for parents may be a good or even the best way to fulfill such a duty. (If one is willing to view utilitarian duties as owed to other persons, then utilitarian duties are natural duties.) As I indicate in the next section, however, I am concerned to find the source of genuinely special obligations between family members.
  • 12
    • 0004273805 scopus 로고
    • New York: Basic Books, See, for example, the discussion of obligations of fair play Robert Nozick, ff. See also Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligations, chap. Obligations of gratitude are often appealed to order to explain what adult children owe to their parents. See, for example, Nancy S. Jecker, ‘Are Filial Duties Unfounded?’ American Philosophical Quarterly26 (1989) 73–80; and Terrance McConnell, Gratitude (Philadelphia: Temple University Press 1993), chap. 7,. In
    • 1974. “ 5 ”. In Anarchy, State, and Utopia 90New York: Basic Books. See, for example, the discussion of obligations of fair play in Robert Nozick, ff. See also Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligations, chap. Obligations of gratitude are often appealed to in order to explain what adult children owe to their parents. See, for example, Nancy S. Jecker, ‘Are Filial Duties Unfounded?’ American Philosophical Quarterly26 (1989) 73–80; and Terrance McConnell, Gratitude (Philadelphia: Temple University Press 1993), chap. 7
    • (1974) Anarchy, State, and Utopia , pp. 90
  • 13
    • 85063704637 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A. John Simmons ‘External Justifications and Institutional Roles,’ 93 (1996
    • The journal of Philosophy, 30 A. John Simmons ‘External Justifications and Institutional Roles,’ 93 (1996
    • The journal of Philosophy , pp. 30
  • 14
    • 85063704443 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One can, for the purposes of my discussion, simply take as a starting point the claim that we have certain duties and obligations, including duties of mutual aid and obligations to keep the promises that we make. We can then see the deflationary account as holding that any obligations that we have to family members must be reducible (in a straightforward way) to some type or types of obligation or duty that were included in our initial set. If we understand the deflationary view in this way, then my view presented in section III will still not be deflationary
    • because I assimilate familial obligations to obligations of promise-keeping but I do not reduce the former to the latter
    • If one is unhappy with my earlier attempt to distinguish special obligations from natural duties (where obligations of promise-keeping are included under the former heading), one can, for the purposes of my discussion, simply take as a starting point the claim that we have certain duties and obligations, including duties of mutual aid and obligations to keep the promises that we make. We can then see the deflationary account as holding that any obligations that we have to family members must be reducible (in a straightforward way) to some type or types of obligation or duty that were included in our initial set. If we understand the deflationary view in this way, then my view presented in section III will still not be deflationary, because I assimilate familial obligations to obligations of promise-keeping but I do not reduce the former to the latter.
    • If one is unhappy with my earlier attempt to distinguish special obligations from natural duties (where obligations of promise-keeping are included under the former heading)
  • 15
    • 85063705185 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a more complete discussion of special obligations and utilitarianism, see my ‘Relatives and Relativism,’ with Richard Fumerton 87 (1997, 57
    • Philosophical Studies, 143 For a more complete discussion of special obligations and utilitarianism, see my ‘Relatives and Relativism,’ with Richard Fumerton 87 (1997, 57
    • Philosophical Studies , pp. 143
  • 16
    • 85063701054 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ‘Filial Morality,’ 83 (1986
    • The journal of Philosophy, 446 ‘Filial Morality,’ 83 (1986
    • The journal of Philosophy , pp. 446
  • 17
    • 0010844192 scopus 로고
    • her well-known paper ‘What Do Grown Children Owe Their Parents?’ (in, !Onora ONeill and William Ruddick, [New York: Oxford University Press] 351–6), Jane English argues that ‘the duties of grown children are those of friends and result from love between them and their parents’ (351). My account of familial obligations accepts, some form, that claim of Englishs; however, my account is an attempt to explain why the features shared by friendships and certain familial relationships do fact generate obligations, a question upon which Englishs paper is silent. By offering such an account, we will be a far better position to respond to the views that I discuss the next section
    • 1979. Having Children: Philosophical and Legal Reflections on Parenthood In her well-known paper ‘What Do Grown Children Owe Their Parents?’ (in, !Onora O'Neill and William Ruddick, [New York: Oxford University Press] 351–6), Jane English argues that ‘the duties of grown children are those of friends and result from love between them and their parents’ (351). My account of familial obligations accepts, in some form, that claim of English's; however, my account is an attempt to explain why the features shared by friendships and certain familial relationships do in fact generate obligations, a question upon which English's paper is silent. By offering such an account, we will be in a far better position to respond to the views that I discuss in the next section.
    • (1979) Having Children: Philosophical and Legal Reflections on Parenthood
  • 18
    • 85063705760 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am grateful to Thomas Hurka for pointing out to me the need to differentiate between forced intimacy and genuine intimacy.
    • I am grateful to Thomas Hurka for pointing out to me the need to differentiate between forced intimacy and genuine intimacy.
  • 19
    • 85063700483 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am not, of course, talking about a project of having friends, or of making friends. I am speaking of a friendship with a certain person as a project. The latter but not the former essentially involves a specific other.
    • I am not, of course, talking about a project of having friends, or of making friends. I am speaking of a friendship with a certain person as a project. The latter but not the former essentially involves a specific other.
  • 20
    • 0002430002 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Ma: Harvard University Press, I do not mean my language of mutual projects and our projects to be taken as a rejection of individualism or of what has come to be known as ‘atomism’: I am not postulating some metaphysical ‘us’ distinct from the individual parties to the friendship. Rather, I am pointing out a fact about the character of the project of friendship and of the sorts of attitudes of the parties to a friendship. For a discussion of such projects that does reject individualism, see Charles Taylor, ‘Cross-Purposes: The Liberal Communitarian Debate,’, ed
    • Rosenblum, N., ed. 1989. Liberalism and the Moral Life 159–82. Cambridge, Ma: Harvard University Press. I do not mean my language of mutual projects and our projects to be taken as a rejection of individualism or of what has come to be known as ‘atomism’: I am not postulating some metaphysical ‘us’ distinct from the individual parties to the friendship. Rather, I am pointing out a fact about the character of the project of friendship and of the sorts of attitudes of the parties to a friendship. For a discussion of such projects that does reject individualism, see Charles Taylor, ‘Cross-Purposes: The Liberal Communitarian Debate,’
    • (1989) Liberalism and the Moral Life , pp. 159-182
    • Rosenblum, N.1
  • 22
    • 85063699493 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • So, unlike with respect to most promises, there is an open-endedness about the content of duties to friends: they are required to care about one another and to maintain the friendship (of course, these are prima facie requirements that can be overridden). If Tracy is my friend, then, there are no specific acts, perhaps, that I am required to perform, unless certain specific acts are necessary conditions of my caring for Tracy and for sustaining our friendship. But, as with promising, what I owe is correlated with what I have chosen: in one case, I have chosen the content of my promise, in the other I have chosen the character of the shared project. I will return to this point below.
    • So, unlike with respect to most promises, there is an open-endedness about the content of duties to friends: they are required to care about one another and to maintain the friendship (of course, these are prima facie requirements that can be overridden). If Tracy is my friend, then, there are no specific acts, perhaps, that I am required to perform, unless certain specific acts are necessary conditions of my caring for Tracy and for sustaining our friendship. But, as with promising, what I owe is correlated with what I have chosen: in one case, I have chosen the content of my promise, in the other I have chosen the character of the shared project. I will return to this point below.
  • 24
    • 85063700416 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An analogous confusion sometimes arises discussions of emotions. It is often said that we cannot choose to feel a particular emotion at a particular time. That is true, if we mean that we cannot choose to be, for example, angry, the way that we can choose to say ‘I promise.’ But, over the course of time, we can make choices and perform actions that will influence the types of persons we become, such as whether we are people who get angry certain types of circumstances. So the feeling of a particular emotion may not be voluntary any straightforward way, but that does not mean that emotions are beyond our control
    • An analogous confusion sometimes arises in discussions of emotions. It is often said that we cannot choose to feel a particular emotion at a particular time. That is true, if we mean that we cannot choose to be, for example, angry, in the way that we can choose to say ‘I promise.’ But, over the course of time, we can make choices and perform actions that will influence the types of persons we become, such as whether we are people who get angry in certain types of circumstances. So the feeling of a particular emotion may not be voluntary in any straightforward way, but that does not mean that emotions are beyond our control.
  • 25
    • 84924172853 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also Joseph Kupfer ‘Can Parents and Children Be Friends?’ 27 (1990, 26, for an interesting discussion of the relationships that can be realized between parents and children, although I disagree with his claim that parents and adult children cannot be friends
    • American Philosophical Quarterly, 15 See also Joseph Kupfer ‘Can Parents and Children Be Friends?’ 27 (1990, 26, for an interesting discussion of the relationships that can be realized between parents and children, although I disagree with his claim that parents and adult children cannot be friends.
    • American Philosophical Quarterly , pp. 15
  • 27
    • 0003478473 scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press, See note 12 above for references to works that develop accounts based on gratitude. One way to develop a more general account based on the realization of goods is to take an Aristotelian approach to special obligations; for example, see Thomas Hurka
    • 1993. Perfectionism 134–6. New York: Oxford University Press. See note 12 above for references to works that develop accounts based on gratitude. One way to develop a more general account based on the realization of goods is to take an Aristotelian approach to special obligations; for example, see Thomas Hurka
    • (1993) Perfectionism , pp. 134-136
  • 28
    • 85063701717 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Ma: The MIT Press, For an interesting critique of the various sociobiological enterprises the context of E.O. Wilsons work, see Philip Kitcher, ‘The Hypothalamic Imperative,’ from reprinted Issues Evolutionary Ethics, Paul Thompson, ed. (AlbanyState University of New York Press 1995) 203–23
    • 1985. Vaulting Ambition 417–34. Cambridge, Ma: The MIT Press. For an interesting critique of the various sociobiological enterprises in the context of E.O. Wilson's work, see Philip Kitcher, ‘The Hypothalamic Imperative,’ from reprinted in Issues in Evolutionary Ethics, Paul Thompson, ed. (AlbanyState University of New York Press 1995) 203–23.
    • (1985) Vaulting Ambition , pp. 417-434
  • 29
    • 85063698039 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ‘Evolutionary Ethics: A Phoenix Arisen,’ 225–47
    • Issues in Evolutionary Ethics ‘Evolutionary Ethics: A Phoenix Arisen,’ in 225–47.
    • Issues in Evolutionary Ethics
  • 30
    • 0004253960 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press
    • 1982. Liberalism and the Limits of justice 179Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
    • (1982) Liberalism and the Limits of justice , pp. 179
  • 31
    • 85063697881 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ‘Honor Thy Father and Thy Mother and to Thine Own Self Be True,’ 24 (1986
    • The Southern journal of Philosophy, 152 ‘Honor Thy Father and Thy Mother and to Thine Own Self Be True,’ 24 (1986
    • The Southern journal of Philosophy , pp. 152
  • 32
    • 0004206765 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Blackwell, Actually, Belliottis view on this point is unclear. He seems to think that it does not matter whether we hold that children owe abusive parents prima facie obligations or we hold that such abusive parents ‘fall outside the realm of consideration’ (157). But, order to be consistent, he (or anyone who thinks that biology generates moral requirements) has to hold the former: if genetic contribution generates moral requirements, then, even if such requirements can be overridden by other moral considerations, they still exist abusive contexts. At least, such is the case, if one accepts what has come to be known as generalism, as opposed to particularism. For a defense of particularism, see Jonathan Dancy, chaps. 4–7
    • 1993. Moral Reasons Oxford: Blackwell. Actually, Belliotti's view on this point is unclear. He seems to think that it does not matter whether we hold that children owe abusive parents prima facie obligations or we hold that such abusive parents ‘fall outside the realm of consideration’ (157). But, in order to be consistent, he (or anyone who thinks that biology generates moral requirements) has to hold the former: if genetic contribution generates moral requirements, then, even if such requirements can be overridden by other moral considerations, they still exist in abusive contexts. At least, such is the case, if one accepts what has come to be known as generalism, as opposed to particularism. For a defense of particularism, see Jonathan Dancy, chaps. 4–7.
    • (1993) Moral Reasons
  • 38
    • 85063700420 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • If at all, only in the case of biological familial relations. The more important worry about his contrast is that we can imagine many roles altered so that persons are born into them. Suppose that persons were born into the role of sailor in the navy as a result of having a parent in the navy and being born on board a naval vessel. And it might be ‘meaningful, rational, or good’ that persons play the role of sailor in the navy. See also Simmons
    • External Justifications and Institutional Roles
    • These cases also reveal why Hardimon's appeal to birth as being different from impressment is useful, if at all, only in the case of biological familial relations. The more important worry about his contrast is that we can imagine many roles altered so that persons are born into them. Suppose that persons were born into the role of sailor in the navy as a result of having a parent in the navy and being born on board a naval vessel. And it might be ‘meaningful, rational, or good’ that persons play the role of sailor in the navy. See also Simmons, ‘External Justifications and Institutional Roles,’ 34–5.
    • These cases also reveal why Hardimon's appeal to birth as being different from impressment is useful , pp. 34-35
  • 39
    • 84954729873 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I would like to thank Richard Fumerton, Thomas Hurka, and two anonymous referees for the for helpful comments on earlier versions of this paper
    • Canadian Journal of Philosophy I would like to thank Richard Fumerton, Thomas Hurka, and two anonymous referees for the for helpful comments on earlier versions of this paper.
    • Canadian Journal of Philosophy


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.