메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 12, Issue 2, 1997, Pages 25-46

What is a Critical Legal Pluralism?

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 85012507678     PISSN: 08293201     EISSN: 19110227     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S0829320100005342     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (177)

References (87)
  • 1
    • 85055297328 scopus 로고
    • Postmodernism and Protest: Recovering the Sociolegal Imagination
    • In describing our endeavour as one of imagining a research practice, we take our cue from K. Calavita &, at 770: “This is a crucial juncture for sociolegal studies. It is a time of self-reflection and reevaluation. a time of self-criticism and skepticism. about the validity of the endeavour itself.”
    • In describing our endeavour as one of imagining a research practice, we take our cue from K. Calavita & C. Seron, “Postmodernism and Protest: Recovering the Sociolegal Imagination“ (1992) 26 Law and Society Rev. 765 at 770: “This is a crucial juncture for sociolegal studies. It is a time of self-reflection and reevaluation. a time of self-criticism and skepticism. about the validity of the endeavour itself.”
    • (1992) Law and Society Rev , vol.26 , pp. 765
    • Seron, C.1
  • 2
    • 85010538266 scopus 로고
    • Introduction à l'éftide compaée du pluralisme juridique
    • See e.g. in J. Gilissen, ed. (Brussels: Université de Bruxelles)
    • See e.g. J. Gilissen, “Introduction à l'éftide compaée du pluralisme juridique“ in J. Gilissen, ed. Le Pluralisme juridique (Brussels: Université de Bruxelles, 1971) 7
    • (1971) Le Pluralisme juridique , pp. 7
    • Gilissen, J.1
  • 4
    • 85055311267 scopus 로고
    • The Folly of the ‘Social Scientific’ Conception of Legal Pluralism
    • See
    • See B. Z. Tamanaha, “The Folly of the ‘Social Scientific’ Conception of Legal Pluralism“ (1993) 20 Journal of Law and Society 192.
    • (1993) Journal of Law and Society , vol.20 , pp. 192
    • Tamanaha, B.Z.1
  • 5
    • 85012570649 scopus 로고
    • Compare, (New York: Oxford University Press)
    • Compare D. Black, Sociological Jurisprudence (New York: Oxford University Press, 1990)
    • (1990) Sociological Jurisprudence
    • Black, D.1
  • 6
    • 84985359619 scopus 로고
    • Law in Action or Living Law? Back to the Beginning in Sociology of Law
    • D. Nelken, “Law in Action or Living Law? Back to the Beginning in Sociology of Law“ (1984) 4 Legal Studies 157.
    • (1984) Legal Studies , vol.4 , pp. 157
    • Nelken, D.1
  • 8
    • 85012544728 scopus 로고
    • (Paris: Lefevre) at: “La loi, en général, est la raison humaine, en tant qu'elle gouverne tous les peuples de la terre; et les lois politiques et civiles de chaque nation ne doivent etre que des cas particuliers où s'applique cette raison humaine.”
    • C. L. Montesquieu, De I ‘esprit des lois (Paris: Lefevre, 1826) at 128: “La loi, en général, est la raison humaine, en tant qu'elle gouverne tous les peuples de la terre; et les lois politiques et civiles de chaque nation ne doivent etre que des cas particuliers où s'applique cette raison humaine.”
    • (1826) De I ‘esprit des lois , pp. 128
    • Montesquieu, C.L.1
  • 9
    • 85012506599 scopus 로고
    • The original Italian version was published in 1915 [L'ordinamento giuridico, 2nd ed.]. See, for the French version, 2nd ed. trans. L. Francois & P. Gothot (Paris: Dalloz)
    • The original Italian version was published in 1915 [L'ordinamento giuridico, 2nd ed.]. See, for the French version, G. Santi Romano, L'ordre juridique, 2nd ed. trans. L. Francois & P. Gothot (Paris: Dalloz, 1975).
    • (1975) L'ordre juridique
    • Santi Romano, G.1
  • 10
    • 54949141259 scopus 로고
    • Gurvitch's monograph was first published in French in 1940. (Paris: Aubier)
    • Gurvitch's monograph was first published in French in 1940. G. Gurvitch, Éléments de sociologie juridique (Paris: Aubier, 1940).
    • (1940) Éléments de sociologie juridique
    • Gurvitch, G.1
  • 11
    • 2642582632 scopus 로고
    • See, for the English version, (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul)
    • See, for the English version, G. Gurvitch, The Sociology of Law (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1942).
    • (1942) The Sociology of Law
    • Gurvitch, G.1
  • 13
    • 84923015933 scopus 로고
    • The Law's Precarious Hold On Life
    • L. L. Fuller, “The Law's Precarious Hold On Life“ (1969) 3 Georgia L. Rev. 609
    • (1969) Georgia L. Rev , vol.3 , pp. 609
    • Fuller, L.L.1
  • 14
    • 46049107813 scopus 로고
    • Law as a Means of Social Control and Law as a Facilitation of Human Interaction
    • L. L. Fuller, “Law as a Means of Social Control and Law as a Facilitation of Human Interaction“ [1975] Brigham Young University L. Rev. 89
    • (1975) Brigham Young University L. Rev , pp. 89
    • Fuller, L.L.1
  • 15
    • 85012540962 scopus 로고
    • Some Presuppositions Shaping the Concept of ‘Socialization'
    • in J. Tapp & F. Levine, eds. (New York: Holt Reinhart & Winston)
    • L. L. Fuller, “Some Presuppositions Shaping the Concept of ‘Socialization'“ in J. Tapp & F. Levine, eds. Law, Justice and the Individual in Society (New York: Holt Reinhart & Winston, 1977) 33.
    • (1977) Law, Justice and the Individual in Society , pp. 33
    • Fuller, L.L.1
  • 16
    • 85010506930 scopus 로고
    • What is Legal Pluralism?
    • For an early interpretation of social-scientific pluralism—since repudiated by its author—
    • J. Griffiths, “What is Legal Pluralism?“ (1986) 24 Journal of Legal Pluralism and Unofficial Law 1. For an early interpretation of social-scientific pluralism—since repudiated by its author—
    • (1986) Journal of Legal Pluralism and Unofficial Law , vol.24 , pp. 1
    • Griffiths, J.1
  • 20
    • 84923515503 scopus 로고
    • Some Realism About Customary Law: The West African Experience
    • G. R. Woodman, “Some Realism About Customary Law: The West African Experience“ [1969] Wisconsin L. Rev. 128.
    • (1969) Wisconsin L. Rev , pp. 128
    • Woodman, G.R.1
  • 23
    • 28444454157 scopus 로고
    • Law and Social Change: The Semi-autonomous Social Field as an Appropriate Subject of Study
    • See e.g. in S. F. Moore, ed. (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul)
    • See e.g. S. F. Moore, “Law and Social Change: The Semi-autonomous Social Field as an Appropriate Subject of Study“ in S. F. Moore, ed. Law as Process: An Anthropological Approach (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1978) 54
    • (1978) Law as Process: An Anthropological Approach , pp. 54
    • Moore, S.F.1
  • 24
    • 0010931511 scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge: Harvard University Press)
    • J. Auerbach, Justice Without Law (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1983)
    • (1983) Justice Without Law
    • Auerbach, J.1
  • 25
    • 84873682020 scopus 로고
    • The Law of the Oppressed: The Construction and Reproduction of Legality in Pasargada
    • B. de Sousa Santos, “The Law of the Oppressed: The Construction and Reproduction of Legality in Pasargada“ (1977) 12 Law and Society Rev. 5.
    • (1977) Law and Society Rev , vol.12 , pp. 5
    • de Sousa Santos, B.1
  • 26
    • 85012551369 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Acadie: à la rencontre de l'histoire du droit avant le dérangement
    • See also
    • See also J. Vanderlinden, “Acadie: à la rencontre de l'histoire du droit avant le dérangement“ (1996) 23 Manitoba Law Journal 146
    • (1996) Manitoba Law Journal , vol.23 , pp. 146
    • Vanderlinden, J.1
  • 27
    • 63849171089 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • La Réception des systèmes juridiques europ6ens au Canada
    • J. Vanderlinden, “La Réception des systèmes juridiques europ6ens au Canada“ (1996) 64 Legal History Rev. 359.
    • (1996) Legal History Rev , vol.64 , pp. 359
    • Vanderlinden, J.1
  • 28
    • 85012498306 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Legal Pluralism and Justice
    • See e.g. at 157: “Legal pluralism in general may be defined as the state of affairs in which a category of social relations is within the fields of operation of two or more bodies of legal norms. Alternatively, if it is viewed not from above in the process of mapping the legal universe but rather from the perspective of the individual subject of law, legal pluralism may be said to exist whenever a person is subject to more than one body of law.”
    • See e.g. G. R. Woodman, “Legal Pluralism and Justice“ [1996] 40 Journal of African Law 152 at 157: “Legal pluralism in general may be defined as the state of affairs in which a category of social relations is within the fields of operation of two or more bodies of legal norms. Alternatively, if it is viewed not from above in the process of mapping the legal universe but rather from the perspective of the individual subject of law, legal pluralism may be said to exist whenever a person is subject to more than one body of law.”
    • (1996) Journal of African Law , vol.40 , pp. 152
    • Woodman, G.R.1
  • 30
    • 40149089896 scopus 로고
    • Vers une nouvelle conception du pluralisme juridique
    • in which the author elaborates a modification of his earlier position: “Je modifierais ma definition de 1969 de la manière suivante: le pluralisme juridique est la situation, pour un individu, dans laquelle des mécanismes juridiques relevant d'ordonnancements différents sont susceptibles de s'appliquer à cette situation.” [emphasis in original]
    • J. Vanderlinden, “Vers une nouvelle conception du pluralisme juridique“ (1993) 53 Revue de la recherche juridique 573, in which the author elaborates a modification of his earlier position: “Je modifierais ma definition de 1969 de la manière suivante: le pluralisme juridique est la situation, pour un individu, dans laquelle des mécanismes juridiques relevant d'ordonnancements différents sont susceptibles de s'appliquer à cette situation.” [emphasis in original].
    • (1993) Revue de la recherche juridique , vol.53 , pp. 573
    • Vanderlinden, J.1
  • 32
    • 0040874786 scopus 로고
    • On this point generally, see, (Boston: Little, Brown) at: “The fundamental and unavoidable problem of choice of law is one of perspective. What normative perspective should a court adopt in making the choice between the law of one state and the law of another state?. Choice of law theory vacillates erratically between two different answers to this question of proper perspective. One tradition is unabashedly a priori; it locates the source of choice of law rules in some normative system external to and more important than the authority of any particular state. The other, internal tradition avoids the problem of authoritative source by treating the choice of law issue as turning on the forum state's local law.”
    • On this point generally, see L. Brilmayer, Conflict of Laws: Foundations and Future Directions (Boston: Little, Brown, 1991) at 1–2: “The fundamental and unavoidable problem of choice of law is one of perspective. What normative perspective should a court adopt in making the choice between the law of one state and the law of another state?. Choice of law theory vacillates erratically between two different answers to this question of proper perspective. One tradition is unabashedly a priori; it locates the source of choice of law rules in some normative system external to and more important than the authority of any particular state. The other, internal tradition avoids the problem of authoritative source by treating the choice of law issue as turning on the forum state's local law.”
    • (1991) Conflict of Laws: Foundations and Future Directions , pp. 1-2
    • Brilmayer, L.1
  • 33
    • 84899264787 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Les Vieilles Gardes: Hypothèses sur l'émergence des normes, l'internormativité et le désordre à travers une typologie des institutions normatives
    • For a more complete examination of this theme, see, in J.-G. Belley, ed. (Paris: L.G.D.J.)
    • For a more complete examination of this theme, see R. A. Macdonald, “Les Vieilles Gardes: Hypothèses sur l'émergence des normes, l'internormativité et le désordre à travers une typologie des institutions normatives“ in J.-G. Belley, ed. Le Droit soluble: Contributions québécoises à Vétude de l'internormativité (Paris: L.G.D.J. 1996) 233.
    • (1996) Le Droit soluble: Contributions québécoises à Vétude de l'internormativité , pp. 233
    • Macdonald, R.A.1
  • 34
    • 85012435429 scopus 로고
    • Customary Law: A Confusing Fiction
    • This is essentially the point argued by, in A. D. Renteln & A. Dundes, (New York: Garland) at 111
    • This is essentially the point argued by J. P. B. Josselin de Jong, “Customary Law: A Confusing Fiction“ in A. D. Renteln & A. Dundes, Folk Law: Essays in the Theory and Practice of lex non scripta (New York: Garland, 1994) at 111.
    • (1994) Folk Law: Essays in the Theory and Practice of lex non scripta
    • Josselin de Jong, J.P.B.1
  • 35
    • 0347665900 scopus 로고
    • Law, Plurality and Underdevelopment
    • See also, in D. Sugarman, ed. (London: Academic) at 175:
    • See also P. Fitzpatrick, “Law, Plurality and Underdevelopment“ in D. Sugarman, ed. Legality, Ideology and the State (London: Academic, 1983) 159 at 175:
    • (1983) Legality, Ideology and the State , pp. 159
    • Fitzpatrick, P.1
  • 37
    • 84935455946 scopus 로고
    • Legal Pluralism
    • See, generally, at 890: “[Legal pluralism]. provides a framework for understanding the dynamics of the imposition of law and of resistance to law. attention to plural orders examines limits to the ideological power of state law.”
    • See, generally, S. E. Merry, “Legal Pluralism“ (1988) 22 Law and Society Rev. 869 at 890: “[Legal pluralism]. provides a framework for understanding the dynamics of the imposition of law and of resistance to law. attention to plural orders examines limits to the ideological power of state law.”
    • (1988) Law and Society Rev , vol.22 , pp. 869
    • Merry, S.E.1
  • 38
    • 0011513516 scopus 로고
    • The Two Faces of Janus: Rethinking Legal Pluralism
    • at 1443:
    • G. Teubner, “The Two Faces of Janus: Rethinking Legal Pluralism“ (1992) 13 Cardozo L. Rev. 1443 at 1443:
    • (1992) Cardozo L. Rev , vol.13 , pp. 1443
    • Teubner, G.1
  • 40
    • 84905296827 scopus 로고
    • Legal Integration as Disintegration of National Law
    • in H. Petersen & H. Zahle, eds. (Aldershot, England: Dartmouth) at: “[T]he paradigmatic concept of law is still the (one and only) law of the national state” [emphasis in original]
    • T. Wilhelmsson, “Legal Integration as Disintegration of National Law“ in H. Petersen & H. Zahle, eds. Legal Polycentricity: Consequences of Pluralism in Law (Aldershot, England: Dartmouth, 1995) at 128: “[T]he paradigmatic concept of law is still the (one and only) law of the national state” [emphasis in original].
    • (1995) Legal Polycentricity: Consequences of Pluralism in Law , pp. 128
    • Wilhelmsson, T.1
  • 41
    • 0004251932 scopus 로고
    • This, of course, is simply an instantiation of a point made forcefully by Ludwig Wittgenstein. See, trans. G.E.M. Anscombe (Oxford: Blackwell) s.: “A picture held us captive. And we could not get outside it, for it lay in our language and language seemed to repeat it to us inexorably.”
    • This, of course, is simply an instantiation of a point made forcefully by Ludwig Wittgenstein. See L. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, trans. G.E.M. Anscombe (Oxford: Blackwell, 1958) s. 115: “A picture held us captive. And we could not get outside it, for it lay in our language and language seemed to repeat it to us inexorably.”
    • (1958) Philosophical Investigations , pp. 115
    • Wittgenstein, L.1
  • 42
    • 84905580376 scopus 로고
    • Postmodernism and Law: A Symposium
    • For explorations of how law constitutes subjectivity, see generally et al.
    • For explorations of how law constitutes subjectivity, see generally P. Schlag et al. “Postmodernism and Law: A Symposium“ (1991) 62 Colorado L. Rev. 439.
    • (1991) Colorado L. Rev , vol.62 , pp. 439
    • Schlag, P.1
  • 43
    • 0001493123 scopus 로고
    • Force of Law: The ‘Mystical Foundation of Authority'
    • See also
    • See also J. Derrida, “Force of Law: The ‘Mystical Foundation of Authority'“ (1990) 11 Cardozo L. Rev. 919
    • (1990) Cardozo L. Rev , vol.11 , pp. 919
    • Derrida, J.1
  • 44
    • 84965632018 scopus 로고
    • The Face of Justice: A Jurisprudence of Alterity
    • C. Douzinas & R. Warrington, “The Face of Justice: A Jurisprudence of Alterity“ (1994) 3 Social and Legal Studies 405
    • (1994) Social and Legal Studies , vol.3 , pp. 405
    • Douzinas, C.1    Warrington, R.2
  • 45
    • 84937298099 scopus 로고
    • A Prophecy of Possibility: Metaphorical Exploration of Postmodern Legal Subjectivity
    • A. Sarat, “A Prophecy of Possibility: Metaphorical Exploration of Postmodern Legal Subjectivity“ (1995) 29 Law and Society Rev. 615.
    • (1995) Law and Society Rev , vol.29 , pp. 615
    • Sarat, A.1
  • 49
    • 57349190358 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Beyond the Provincial: Space, Aesthetics, and Modernist Legal Theory
    • See
    • See D. Manderson, “Beyond the Provincial: Space, Aesthetics, and Modernist Legal Theory“ (1996) 20 Melbourne University L. Rev. 1048.
    • (1996) Melbourne University L. Rev , vol.20 , pp. 1048
    • Manderson, D.1
  • 50
    • 84935786772 scopus 로고
    • On Modes of Production of Law and Social Power
    • This is most explicit in writings of progressive legal pluralists such as Boaventura de Sousa Santos. See, for example
    • This is most explicit in writings of progressive legal pluralists such as Boaventura de Sousa Santos. See, for example, B. de Sousa Santos, “On Modes of Production of Law and Social Power“ (1985) 13 International Journal of the Sociology of Law 299.
    • (1985) International Journal of the Sociology of Law , vol.13 , pp. 299
    • de Sousa Santos, B.1
  • 51
    • 0003837911 scopus 로고
    • (New York: Routledge) at
    • D. Fuss, Identification Papers (New York: Routledge, 1995) at 40–42.
    • (1995) Identification Papers , pp. 40-42
    • Fuss, D.1
  • 52
    • 84929065102 scopus 로고
    • Missing Pieces: A Cognitive Approach to Law
    • A critical view must surely reject the rationalist world view which “constantly asks for the redemption and justification of all descriptive and normative claims and that privileges the individual rationalist self and its ability to make normative recommendations about the law's ideal structure through ego-centered reason.” See, at 1208
    • A critical view must surely reject the rationalist world view which “constantly asks for the redemption and justification of all descriptive and normative claims and that privileges the individual rationalist self and its ability to make normative recommendations about the law's ideal structure through ego-centered reason.” See P. Schlag, “Missing Pieces: A Cognitive Approach to Law“ (1989) 67 Texas L. Rev. 1195 at 1208.
    • (1989) Texas L. Rev , vol.67 , pp. 1195
    • Schlag, P.1
  • 54
    • 85023035211 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ideological Conflict and Social Observation: Recent Debate About Legal Pluralism
    • See, [forthcoming]
    • See G. R. Woodman, “Ideological Conflict and Social Observation: Recent Debate About Legal Pluralism“ (1998) 40 Journal of Legal Pluralism and Unofficial Law [forthcoming]
    • (1998) Journal of Legal Pluralism and Unofficial Law , vol.40
    • Woodman, G.R.1
  • 55
    • 84933491816 scopus 로고
    • Anthropology, Law, and Transitional Processes
    • See, at 358, and
    • See S. E. Merry, “Anthropology, Law, and Transitional Processes“ (1992) 21 Annual Review of Anthropology 357 at 358, and
    • (1992) Annual Review of Anthropology , vol.21 , pp. 357
    • Merry, S.E.1
  • 56
    • 84934562338 scopus 로고
    • Law: A Map of Misreading. Toward a Postmodern Conception of Law
    • at 298. In an attempt to provide a postmodern reconception of law, de Sousa Santos argues that legal pluralism plays a critical role. Here, however, the legal pluralism to which he appeals is not the traditional version of legal anthropologists “in which legal orders are conceived as separate entities coexisting in the same political space, but rather the conception of different legal spaces superimposed, interpenetrated, and mixed in our minds as much as in our actions, in occasions of qualitative leaps or sweeping crises in our life trajectories as well as in the dull routine of eventless everyday life” [emphasis added]
    • B. de Sousa Santos, “Law: A Map of Misreading. Toward a Postmodern Conception of Law“ (1987) 14 Journal of Law and Society 279 at 298. In an attempt to provide a postmodern reconception of law, de Sousa Santos argues that legal pluralism plays a critical role. Here, however, the legal pluralism to which he appeals is not the traditional version of legal anthropologists “in which legal orders are conceived as separate entities coexisting in the same political space, but rather the conception of different legal spaces superimposed, interpenetrated, and mixed in our minds as much as in our actions, in occasions of qualitative leaps or sweeping crises in our life trajectories as well as in the dull routine of eventless everyday life” [emphasis added].
    • (1987) Journal of Law and Society , vol.14 , pp. 279
    • de Sousa Santos, B.1
  • 57
    • 77957188008 scopus 로고
    • An Analytical Map of Social Scientific Approaches to the Concept of Law
    • See the discussion in, [hereinafter “Social Scientific Approaches”]
    • See the discussion in B. Z. Tamanaha, “An Analytical Map of Social Scientific Approaches to the Concept of Law“ (1995) 15 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 501 [hereinafter “Social Scientific Approaches”].
    • (1995) Oxford Journal of Legal Studies , vol.15 , pp. 501
    • Tamanaha, B.Z.1
  • 58
    • 85012505105 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Creative Self
    • There exist many ways of conceiving of “critical legal pluralism” in the legal imagination. Although the image presented here has been inspired by hermeneutic and narrative analyses, the intent has not been to restrict the scope of the proposed agenda. The necessary conditions of a critical legal pluralism, as outlined in the following paragraphs, are broad enough to encompass numerous images of law, of which ours is but an example. The use of the indefinite article “a” in the title of this essay is meant to signal the diverse possibilities with the frame of critical legal pluralism. Alternative and contrasting conceptions of a critical legal pluralism are present in the authors’ own previous work.
    • There exist many ways of conceiving of “critical legal pluralism” in the legal imagination. Although the image presented here has been inspired by hermeneutic and narrative analyses, the intent has not been to restrict the scope of the proposed agenda. The necessary conditions of a critical legal pluralism, as outlined in the following paragraphs, are broad enough to encompass numerous images of law, of which ours is but an example. The use of the indefinite article “a” in the title of this essay is meant to signal the diverse possibilities with the frame of critical legal pluralism. Alternative and contrasting conceptions of a critical legal pluralism are present in the authors’ own previous work. See e.g. “The Creative Self', Oxford Journal of Legal Studies ∗;
    • Oxford Journal of Legal Studies
  • 60
    • 85012450710 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Hermeneutic Turn Through Narrative
    • “A Hermeneutic Turn Through Narrative“, Oxford Journal of Legal Studies ∗;
    • Oxford Journal of Legal Studies
  • 61
    • 85012502668 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Multiple Selves and Legal Pluralism
    • “Multiple Selves and Legal Pluralism,” Oxford Journal of Legal Studies ∗;
    • Oxford Journal of Legal Studies
  • 63
    • 84978248787 scopus 로고
    • Of course, because subjects and communities are in a constructing/constructed relationship, a critical legal pluralism could even define “community” as a process of knowledge construction and, thus, capture the relational nature of community within the subject. See, (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press) at: “I inherit from the past of my family, my city, my tribe, my nation, a variety of debts, inheritances, rightful expectations and obligations. These constitute the given of my life, my moral starting point.”
    • Of course, because subjects and communities are in a constructing/constructed relationship, a critical legal pluralism could even define “community” as a process of knowledge construction and, thus, capture the relational nature of community within the subject. See A. Maclntyre, After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1984) at 220: “I inherit from the past of my family, my city, my tribe, my nation, a variety of debts, inheritances, rightful expectations and obligations. These constitute the given of my life, my moral starting point.”
    • (1984) After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory , pp. 220
    • Maclntyre, A.1
  • 64
    • 0003885883 scopus 로고
    • See also, (Cambridge: Harvard University Press) at: “It can never be the case that there is a ‘self independent of one's cultural-historical existence.”
    • See also J. Bruner, Actual Minds, Possible Worlds (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1986) at 67: “It can never be the case that there is a ‘self independent of one's cultural-historical existence.”
    • (1986) Actual Minds, Possible Worlds , pp. 67
    • Bruner, J.1
  • 65
    • 84937287128 scopus 로고
    • Three Metaphors for a New Conception of Law: The Frontier, the Baroque, and the South
    • at 573
    • B. de Sousa Santos, “Three Metaphors for a New Conception of Law: The Frontier, the Baroque, and the South“ (1995) 29 Law and Society Rev. 569 at 573.
    • (1995) Law and Society Rev , vol.29 , pp. 569
    • de Sousa Santos, B.1
  • 66
    • 85012494698 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the points raised in the next few paragraphs see, generally, (Doctoral dissertation, Faculty of Law, McGill University) [unpublished]
    • On the points raised in the next few paragraphs see, generally, S. C. McGuire, “Critical Legal Pluralism: A Thought-Piece on a Direction for Socio-legal Studies“ (Doctoral dissertation, Faculty of Law, McGill University, 1996) [unpublished].
    • (1996) Critical Legal Pluralism: A Thought-Piece on a Direction for Socio-legal Studies
    • McGuire, S.C.1
  • 67
    • 84890505344 scopus 로고
    • The Truth About Autopoiesis
    • These assumptions animate a conception of law as i) a positive phenomenon, ii) centrally defined, even if implicitly, by appeal to the model of state law and, iii) monistic within each of the orders comprising its quantitative plurality. Even more recent social scientific theories such as autopoiesis, for example, rest on the positivity of the characteristic binary distinctions of law: lawful/unlawful; legal/illegal. See M. King
    • These assumptions animate a conception of law as i) a positive phenomenon, ii) centrally defined, even if implicitly, by appeal to the model of state law and, iii) monistic within each of the orders comprising its quantitative plurality. Even more recent social scientific theories such as autopoiesis, for example, rest on the positivity of the characteristic binary distinctions of law: lawful/unlawful; legal/illegal. See M. King, “The Truth About Autopoiesis“ (1993) 20 Journal of Law and Society 218.
    • (1993) Journal of Law and Society , vol.20 , pp. 218
  • 68
    • 85012476204 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Social Scientific Approaches
    • For a critique of autopoiesis along these lines, see 42
    • For a critique of autopoiesis along these lines, see “Social Scientific Approaches“, Journal of Law and Society 42.
    • Journal of Law and Society
  • 69
    • 85012493912 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • En effet, si l'on peut parfaitement concevoi le droit sans l'État, il est impossible de définir l'état sans recourir au concept de droit
    • 6 at 82–83.
    • Santi Romano, Journal of Law and Society 6 at 82–83. “En effet, si l'on peut parfaitement concevoi le droit sans l'État, il est impossible de définir l'état sans recourir au concept de droit.”
    • Journal of Law and Society
    • Romano, S.1
  • 70
    • 85012569430 scopus 로고
    • Vers la reconnaissance d'une normativité implicite et inférentielle
    • See
    • See R. A. Macdonald, “Vers la reconnaissance d'une normativité implicite et inférentielle“ (1985) 18 Sociologie et Sociétés 38.
    • (1985) Sociologie et Sociétés , vol.18 , pp. 38
    • Macdonald, R.A.1
  • 71
    • 0003605855 scopus 로고
    • For a similar argument made with regards to contemporary debates about modern constitutionalism and cultural diversity, see, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press) at
    • For a similar argument made with regards to contemporary debates about modern constitutionalism and cultural diversity, see J. Tully, Strange Multiplicity Constitutionalism in an Age of Diversity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1995) at 58ff.
    • (1995) Strange Multiplicity Constitutionalism in an Age of Diversity , pp. 58ff.
    • Tully, J.1
  • 72
    • 0004224658 scopus 로고
    • trans. D. Paul & G. E. M. Anscombe (London: Basi Blackwell) at para
    • L. Wittgenstein, On Certainty, trans. D. Paul & G. E. M. Anscombe (London: Basi Blackwell, 1969) at para. 84ff.
    • (1969) On Certainty , pp. 84ff.
    • Wittgenstein, L.1
  • 73
    • 85012562635 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Human Interaction and the Law
    • One could also argue that, notwithstanding the discursive source of this concept of “law” in European political systems, even there it has transcended the boundaries imposed upon it by its original construction. It is just this local transcendence that makes the present inquiry possible. See e.g. the discussion in L. L. Fuller, in Winston, 8, 211
    • One could also argue that, notwithstanding the discursive source of this concept of “law” in European political systems, even there it has transcended the boundaries imposed upon it by its original construction. It is just this local transcendence that makes the present inquiry possible. See e.g. the discussion in L. L. Fuller, “Human Interaction and the Law“ in Winston, On Certainty 8, 211.
    • On Certainty
  • 74
    • 85012489109 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In fact, it might be argued that Teubner's proposed solution to the deconstructive dilemma of postmodern approaches highlights the need to find agency in discussions of legal pluralism. Teubner calls attention to the lack of reconstructive practice in postmodern jurisprudence, and suggests that autopoiesis might be the answer. His solution, however, succeeds only in anthropomorphizing and subjectifying the normative orders. The realm of his inquiry remains the normative orders as phenomena, albeit “living” phenomena. See
    • In fact, it might be argued that Teubner's proposed solution to the deconstructive dilemma of postmodern approaches highlights the need to find agency in discussions of legal pluralism. Teubner calls attention to the lack of reconstructive practice in postmodern jurisprudence, and suggests that autopoiesis might be the answer. His solution, however, succeeds only in anthropomorphizing and subjectifying the normative orders. The realm of his inquiry remains the normative orders as phenomena, albeit “living” phenomena. See Teubner, On Certainty 24.
    • On Certainty , pp. 24
    • Teubner1
  • 75
    • 85012488154 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • “Social Scientific Approaches“
    • “Social Scientific Approaches“, On Certainty 42.
    • On Certainty , pp. 42
  • 76
    • 0004285730 scopus 로고
    • (New York: Basic) at
    • C. Geertz, Local Knowledge (New York: Basic, 1983) at 232.
    • (1983) Local Knowledge , pp. 232
    • Geertz, C.1
  • 77
    • 0004262315 scopus 로고
    • dative, accusative, ablative, vocative and locative. In Cree there are about a dozen and one-half. Each case might be said to key to a self: subject, belonger, receiver, object, exponent, self-assessor, and locator. Similarly, selves might be conceived as being formed and/or understood through narrative. Within such a narrative approach acts of self-narration, or the autobiographical ruminations that concerr the critical legal pluralist, leave the realm of mere description, and become fundamental to the emergence and reality of subjects themselves. See, further, (Indianapolis: Indiana University Press)
    • dative, accusative, ablative, vocative and locative. In Cree there are about a dozen and one-half. Each case might be said to key to a self: subject, belonger, receiver, object, exponent, self-assessor, and locator. Similarly, selves might be conceived as being formed and/or understood through narrative. Within such a narrative approach acts of self-narration, or the autobiographical ruminations that concerr the critical legal pluralist, leave the realm of mere description, and become fundamental to the emergence and reality of subjects themselves. See, further, A. P. Kerby, Narrative and the Self (Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 1991)
    • (1991) Narrative and the Self
    • Kerby, A.P.1
  • 78
    • 0004152399 scopus 로고
    • (Chicago: University of Chicago Press)
    • H. Arendt, The Human Condition (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1981).
    • (1981) The Human Condition
    • Arendt, H.1
  • 80
    • 0000322565 scopus 로고
    • Virtue and Reason
    • at 339
    • J. McDowell, “Virtue and Reason“ (1979) 62 The Monist 331 at 339.
    • (1979) The Monist , vol.62 , pp. 331
    • McDowell, J.1
  • 81
    • 84956817270 scopus 로고
    • Historical Studies of Legal Change
    • J. Starr & J. F. Collier, “Historical Studies of Legal Change“ (1987) 28 Current Anthropology 367.
    • (1987) Current Anthropology , vol.28 , pp. 367
    • Starr, J.1    Collier, J.F.2
  • 82
    • 0040267944 scopus 로고
    • Law and the Postmodern Mind: Rethinking the Beyond of the Real
    • D. Cornell, “Law and the Postmodern Mind: Rethinking the Beyond of the Real“ (1995) 16 Cardozo L. Rev. 729.
    • (1995) Cardozo L. Rev , vol.16 , pp. 729
    • Cornell, D.1
  • 83
    • 85012547097 scopus 로고
    • For a discussion of an analogous situation in the differing approaches to theater (the linear/transgression model of the Theatre of the Oppressed and the circular model of certain aboriginal groups adopting methods used in “healing circles”), see, (Paper presented to the Association for Canadian Theatre Research Annual Conference) [unpublished]
    • For a discussion of an analogous situation in the differing approaches to theater (the linear/transgression model of the Theatre of the Oppressed and the circular model of certain aboriginal groups adopting methods used in “healing circles”), see C. Graham, “On the Seductiveness of Clarity and the Pain of Erasure“ (Paper presented to the Association for Canadian Theatre Research Annual Conference, 1992) [unpublished].
    • (1992) On the Seductiveness of Clarity and the Pain of Erasure
    • Graham, C.1
  • 84
    • 0003744932 scopus 로고
    • (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France) c
    • G. Bachelard, La Poétique de I'espace (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1958) c. 10.
    • (1958) La Poétique de I'espace , pp. 10
    • Bachelard, G.1
  • 85
    • 85012465373 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The circular image is not intended to conjure the empty sphere of geometricians, rather it embodies the full sphere of being. See at
    • The circular image is not intended to conjure the empty sphere of geometricians, rather it embodies the full sphere of being. See G. Bachelard, La Poétique de I'espace 64 at 244
    • La Poétique de I'espace , vol.64 , pp. 244
    • Bachelard, G.1
  • 86
    • 65849483762 scopus 로고
    • at Munich: R. Piper “Jedes Dasein Scheint in sich rund” (Every being seems in itself round)
    • K. Jaspers, Von der Wahrheit (Munich: R. Piper, 1947) at 50: “Jedes Dasein Scheint in sich rund” (Every being seems in itself round).
    • (1947) Von der Wahrheit , pp. 50
    • Jaspers, K.1
  • 87
    • 85012517227 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Le Pluralisme juridique chez Roderick Macdonald: Une Analyse séquentielle
    • See, in Lajoie, ed. ∗ [forthcoming]
    • See J.-G. Belley, “Le Pluralisme juridique chez Roderick Macdonald: Une Analyse séquentielle“ in Lajoie, ed. Von der Wahrheit ∗ [forthcoming].
    • Von der Wahrheit
    • Belley, J.-G.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.