메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 21, Issue 1, 1996, Pages 61-110

Between metaphysical and liberal pluralism: A reappraisal of rabbi a. i. kook's espousal of toleration

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 85012502226     PISSN: 03640094     EISSN: 14754541     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S0364009400007625     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (12)

References (114)
  • 1
    • 85012555502 scopus 로고
    • (Hebrew), Daat 20 (Winter 1988): 151-168; Binyamin Efrati, Sanegoriya (Seeing the Good Side) in the Teaching of R. Kook (Hebrew) (Jerusalem: Mosad Harav Kook, 1959); Zvi Yaron, The Philosophy of R. Kook (Hebrew) (Jerusalem: Jewish Agency Torah Dept., 1974), chap. 12: “Toleration,” pp. 323-373; Eliezer Schweid, Judaism and the Solitary Jew (Hebrew) (Tel Aviv: Am Oved, ), chap. 3: “Secularism from a Religious Perspective-R. Kook's Teaching,”
    • Binyamin ‘Ish-Shalom, “Tolerance and Its Theoretical Basis in the Teaching of Rabbi Kook” (Hebrew), Daat 20 (Winter 1988): 151-168; Binyamin Efrati, Sanegoriya (Seeing the Good Side) in the Teaching of R. Kook (Hebrew) (Jerusalem: Mosad Harav Kook, 1959); Zvi Yaron, The Philosophy of R. Kook (Hebrew) (Jerusalem: Jewish Agency Torah Dept., 1974), chap. 12: “Toleration,” pp. 323-373; Eliezer Schweid, Judaism and the Solitary Jew (Hebrew) (Tel Aviv: Am Oved, 1975), chap. 3: “Secularism from a Religious Perspective-R. Kook's Teaching,” pp. 178-192.
    • (1975) Binyamin ‘Ish-Shalom, “Tolerance and Its Theoretical Basis in the Teaching of Rabbi Kook” , pp. 178-192
  • 2
    • 85012571441 scopus 로고
    • As has been done by Jay Newman, American Philosophical Quarterly 15, no. 3 (July 1978): 187, and by P. F. Strawson, Freedom and Resentment (London: Methuen, ), chap. 4: “The Limits of Toleration,”
    • As has been done by Jay Newman, “The Idea of Religious Tolerance,” American Philosophical Quarterly 15, no. 3 (July 1978): 187, and by P. F. Strawson, Freedom and Resentment (London: Methuen, 1974), chap. 4: “The Limits of Toleration,” p. 43.
    • (1974) The Idea of Religious Tolerance , pp. 43
  • 4
    • 85012431119 scopus 로고
    • see Herbert Marcuse, “Repressive Tolerance,” in A Critique of Pure Tolerance, ed. R. P. Wolff, B. Moore Jr., and H. Marcuse (Boston: Beacon Press, 1969), pp. 81-123; W. Kendall, “The ‘Open Society” and Its Fallacies,” American Political Science Review 54 (1960): 972-979; David Lewis, “Mill and Milquetoast,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 67 : 152-171; Karl Popper, “Toleration and Intellectual Responsibility,” in On Toleration, ed. S. Mendus and D. Edwards (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1987), pp. 17-34; David Hed, “Two Concepts of Liberalism,” in In the Labyrinth of Democracy, ed. Yuval Lurie and Hayim Maranz (Ben-Gurion University, 1990),. The two versions of maximalism and minimalism have alternatively been described as thick or thin, rightist or leftist, individualistic or pluralistic, when applied not only to toleration as such, but also to the broader concept of liberalism as a form of government.
    • For a more elaborate explication of these two models of toleration and the respective philosophical and political difficulties they engender when forming the basis for practical policy, see Herbert Marcuse, “Repressive Tolerance,” in A Critique of Pure Tolerance, ed. R. P. Wolff, B. Moore Jr., and H. Marcuse (Boston: Beacon Press, 1969), pp. 81-123; W. Kendall, “The ‘Open Society” and Its Fallacies,” American Political Science Review 54 (1960): 972-979; David Lewis, “Mill and Milquetoast,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 67 (1989): 152-171; Karl Popper, “Toleration and Intellectual Responsibility,” in On Toleration, ed. S. Mendus and D. Edwards (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1987), pp. 17-34; David Hed, “Two Concepts of Liberalism,” in In the Labyrinth of Democracy, ed. Yuval Lurie and Hayim Maranz (Ben-Gurion University, 1990), pp. 169-184. The two versions of maximalism and minimalism have alternatively been described as thick or thin, rightist or leftist, individualistic or pluralistic, when applied not only to toleration as such, but also to the broader concept of liberalism as a form of government.
    • (1989) For a more elaborate explication of these two models of toleration and the respective philosophical and political difficulties they engender when forming the basis for practical policy , pp. 169-184
  • 5
    • 85012531651 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the contrary, they may reinforce each other. See Susan Mendus's introduction to Mendus and Edwards, On Toleration,. Mendus terms the three motives “prudence,” “rationality,” and “morality.”
    • Although these motives are separate and distinct justifications for toleration, they are not always mutually exclusive. On the contrary, they may reinforce each other. See Susan Mendus's introduction to Mendus and Edwards, On Toleration, pp. 3-4. Mendus terms the three motives “prudence,” “rationality,” and “morality.”
    • Although these motives are separate and distinct justifications for toleration, they are not always mutually exclusive , pp. 3-4
  • 7
    • 85012568879 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mill opposes the idea of public truth not because society must have freedom of speech, but for the same reason that it must have freedom of speech, i.e., an assault on one definitive truth. For Mill, skepticism and tolerance are integrally connected. He thinks our choice is either never to silence or to declare ourselves infallible. See Kendall, “Open Society,” Strawson, “Limits of Toleration,” p.
    • Contrary to what is usually assumed, it is this version of intellectual skepticism that supports J. S. Mill's liberalism. Mill opposes the idea of public truth not because society must have freedom of speech, but for the same reason that it must have freedom of speech, i.e., an assault on one definitive truth. For Mill, skepticism and tolerance are integrally connected. He thinks our choice is either never to silence or to declare ourselves infallible. See Kendall, “Open Society,” pp. 975-976; Strawson, “Limits of Toleration,” p. 50.
    • Contrary to what is usually assumed, it is this version of intellectual skepticism that supports J. S. Mill's liberalism , pp. 975-976
  • 10
    • 85012517534 scopus 로고
    • It has, however, been argued that one cannot draw a distinction between the moral and the nonmoral by contending that one is based on reason and the other on feeling. Morality itself is based on strong feelings, and the concept of morality would wither away and become lost in the concept of expediency if strong feelings or sentiment were not involved in the judgment that something is morally right or wrong. The conclusion is therefore drawn that no sharp line can be drawn between what I dislike and what I disapprove of. See Baroness Warnock's article, “The Limits of Toleration,” chap. 7 in On Toleration,. However, Wamock also argues that there is no necessity to identify relativism (the belief that nothing is ultimately better or worse than anything else) with the belief that morality is based as much on feeling as reason, for some feelings may be better or more important (culturally, historically) than others. 12. According to R. M. Hare in Freedom and Reason (Oxford: Clarendon Press, ), p. 177, “what distinguishes the liberal is that he respects the ideals of others as he does his own. This does not mean he agrees with them-that would be logically impossible if they are different from his.” But if his and others’ conflict, “he will-in arbitrating between people's interests and ideals, give as much weight to each person's as to any other's; he will not give his own ideals and interests preference because they are his own. It is only when somebody else's pursuit interferes with others’ that this arbitration becomes necessary.” But Hare then continues: “He does not claim finality for his own ideal, though he may be sure that it is the best that he has discovered so far… He may even think that a diversity of ideals is in itself a good thing, not only because people are different and what they are likely to achieve is different… but also, because it takes all sorts to make a world” (p. 180).
    • For those who accept the Kantian criterion of universalizability, with the implied universality and absoluteness of moral principles, the impossibility of tolerance would apply here too. It has, however, been argued that one cannot draw a distinction between the moral and the nonmoral by contending that one is based on reason and the other on feeling. Morality itself is based on strong feelings, and the concept of morality would wither away and become lost in the concept of expediency if strong feelings or sentiment were not involved in the judgment that something is morally right or wrong. The conclusion is therefore drawn that no sharp line can be drawn between what I dislike and what I disapprove of. See Baroness Warnock's article, “The Limits of Toleration,” chap. 7 in On Toleration, p. 126. However, Wamock also argues that there is no necessity to identify relativism (the belief that nothing is ultimately better or worse than anything else) with the belief that morality is based as much on feeling as reason, for some feelings may be better or more important (culturally, historically) than others. 12. According to R. M. Hare in Freedom and Reason (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1963), p. 177, “what distinguishes the liberal is that he respects the ideals of others as he does his own. This does not mean he agrees with them-that would be logically impossible if they are different from his.” But if his and others’ conflict, “he will-in arbitrating between people's interests and ideals, give as much weight to each person's as to any other's; he will not give his own ideals and interests preference because they are his own. It is only when somebody else's pursuit interferes with others’ that this arbitration becomes necessary.” But Hare then continues: “He does not claim finality for his own ideal, though he may be sure that it is the best that he has discovered so far… He may even think that a diversity of ideals is in itself a good thing, not only because people are different and what they are likely to achieve is different… but also, because it takes all sorts to make a world” (p. 180).
    • (1963) For those who accept the Kantian criterion of universalizability, with the implied universality and absoluteness of moral principles, the impossibility of tolerance would apply here too , pp. 126
  • 11
    • 85012490840 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (“Idea of Religious Tolerance,” p. 188), when toleration is applied to moral positions or to rational argument, the concept need not necessarily represent a normative ideal. A person may criticize himself or others for merely tolerating what calls for stronger approval or respect, or for even tolerating something that calls for stronger measures of disapproval and denunciation
    • Thus, as Newman points out (“Idea of Religious Tolerance,” p. 188), when toleration is applied to moral positions or to rational argument, the concept need not necessarily represent a normative ideal. A person may criticize himself or others for merely tolerating what calls for stronger approval or respect, or for even tolerating something that calls for stronger measures of disapproval and denunciation.
    • Thus, as Newman points out
  • 12
    • 85012558793 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thus, as Newman points out; Strawson
    • Newman, Thus, as Newman points out; Strawson, “Limits of Toleration,” pp. 43-55.
    • Limits of Toleration , pp. 43-55
    • Newman1
  • 16
    • 85012508836 scopus 로고
    • (Hebrew), Mahanayim 5 (May 1993): 8-16; Menahem ‘Elon, “Freedom of Expression and the Control of Minority Rights in Jewish Law,” “Limits of Toleration,”…, pars. 5-6. See also TB Kritot 6b: “Every fast-day in which the sinners of Israel do not participate is not a true fast-day, as we see from the case of the helbena (galbanum), which has a bad smell but is included by Scripture (Exodus 30:34) among the ingredients to be included in the incense to be offered in the service of the sanctuary”; the theme is elaborated upon in Derashot Ha-ran (Nissim b. Reuven of Gerondi), edited by L. A. Feldman (Jerusalem, ), first derasha, pp. 3ff.
    • See ‘Avot 3:18. For further amplification of this theme, see Aaron Lichtenstein, “The Dignity of Created Beings” (Hebrew), Mahanayim 5 (May 1993): 8-16; Menahem ‘Elon, “Freedom of Expression and the Control of Minority Rights in Jewish Law,” “Limits of Toleration,”…, pp. 28-30, pars. 5-6. See also TB Kritot 6b: “Every fast-day in which the sinners of Israel do not participate is not a true fast-day, as we see from the case of the helbena (galbanum), which has a bad smell but is included by Scripture (Exodus 30:34) among the ingredients to be included in the incense to be offered in the service of the sanctuary”; the theme is elaborated upon in Derashot Ha-ran (Nissim b. Reuven of Gerondi), edited by L. A. Feldman (Jerusalem, 1973), first derasha, pp. 3ff.
    • (1973) ‘Avot 3:18. For further amplification of this theme, see Aaron Lichtenstein, “The Dignity of Created Beings” , pp. 28-30
  • 17
    • 85012553576 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see ‘Elon, “Freedom of Expression,”. A spirit of pluralism based on such sources surely animates the toleration of diversity in the realm of halakhic practice exemplified in such contemporary rulings as R. Moshe Feinstein's permitting the sale, during the year of shmita (the sabbatical year), of ‘etrogim (citrons) produced in the framework of belief in heter mekhirah (the possibility of “selling” the land of Israel in order to obviate its lying fallow) even to those who do not accept this heter, since there is no violation of “placing a stumbling block before the blind” regarding anything that is done in accordance with the decision of a sage until a Sanhedrin actually rules against it (Igrot Moshe, Orah Hayim, vol. 1, sec. 186). That is, it is recognized here that the fragmentation of religious authority allows for many opinions. Compare the Responsa Mishnat Yosef, pt. 1, sec. 100. Another leading contemporary decisor, R. Eliezer Waldenberg, in his Responsa Tzitz Eliezer 12, pt. 16, sec. 3, forbids practicing a humra (stringent measure) which will shame someone else who does not keep the same stringency. He wrote this in response to a query regarding the practice of the saintly Hafetz Hayim, who behaved in this manner regarding the eating of matzah sheruyah (moistened unleavened bread) on Passover; the questioner asked whether he was obligated to perform a hatarat nedarim (remission of vows) in this connection
    • For further amplification and sources, see ‘Elon, “Freedom of Expression,” pp. 25-26. A spirit of pluralism based on such sources surely animates the toleration of diversity in the realm of halakhic practice exemplified in such contemporary rulings as R. Moshe Feinstein's permitting the sale, during the year of shmita (the sabbatical year), of ‘etrogim (citrons) produced in the framework of belief in heter mekhirah (the possibility of “selling” the land of Israel in order to obviate its lying fallow) even to those who do not accept this heter, since there is no violation of “placing a stumbling block before the blind” regarding anything that is done in accordance with the decision of a sage until a Sanhedrin actually rules against it (Igrot Moshe, Orah Hayim, vol. 1, sec. 186). That is, it is recognized here that the fragmentation of religious authority allows for many opinions. Compare the Responsa Mishnat Yosef, pt. 1, sec. 100. Another leading contemporary decisor, R. Eliezer Waldenberg, in his Responsa Tzitz Eliezer 12, pt. 16, sec. 3, forbids practicing a humra (stringent measure) which will shame someone else who does not keep the same stringency. He wrote this in response to a query regarding the practice of the saintly Hafetz Hayim, who behaved in this manner regarding the eating of matzah sheruyah (moistened unleavened bread) on Passover; the questioner asked whether he was obligated to perform a hatarat nedarim (remission of vows) in this connection.
    • For further amplification and sources , pp. 25-26
  • 18
    • 85012511028 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Orah Hayim, vol. 1, sec. 46, that although the Israeli flag is a symbol of the state of the wicked heretics who deny Jewish tradition, there is no ban on it, for there is nothing against placing a secular object in the synagogue. Therefore, it is not worth creating a dispute over something which is not actually forbidden. In this case, the imprudence of divisiveness overrides the distaste for the dissident. One source that might be construed as extending the toleration principle even further is TB Menahot 27a, which compares the obligation to bind together the ‘arba’ minim (four species of plants blessed on Sukkot) to the obligation to bind together all types of Jews, which includes even the wicked among them. But the intent is most likely directed to tolerance of their persons, not of their wickedness per se.
    • E.g., see R. Moshe Feinstein's ruling in his Igrot Moshe, Orah Hayim, vol. 1, sec. 46, that although the Israeli flag is a symbol of the state of the wicked heretics who deny Jewish tradition, there is no ban on it, for there is nothing against placing a secular object in the synagogue. Therefore, it is not worth creating a dispute over something which is not actually forbidden. In this case, the imprudence of divisiveness overrides the distaste for the dissident. One source that might be construed as extending the toleration principle even further is TB Menahot 27a, which compares the obligation to bind together the ‘arba’ minim (four species of plants blessed on Sukkot) to the obligation to bind together all types of Jews, which includes even the wicked among them. But the intent is most likely directed to tolerance of their persons, not of their wickedness per se.
    • R. Moshe Feinstein's ruling in his Igrot Moshe
  • 19
    • 85012481631 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III, chap. 51, regarding the second class of people surrounding the palace in search of the king. Since they hold wrong opinions, sometimes they must be slain and all memory of their opinions destroyed, so that they will not mislead others.
    • E.g., see Maimonides’ opinion in his Guide of the Perplexed, III, chap. 51, regarding the second class of people surrounding the palace in search of the king. Since they hold wrong opinions, sometimes they must be slain and all memory of their opinions destroyed, so that they will not mislead others.
    • see Maimonides’ opinion in his Guide of the Perplexed
  • 20
    • 85012507016 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2:2. See also Yaron, Philosophy of R. Kook, and especially
    • Rambam, Hilkhot Gerushin 2:2. See also Yaron, Philosophy of R. Kook, p. 327, and especially n. 13.
    • Hilkhot Gerushin , pp. 327
    • Rambam1
  • 22
    • 85012565822 scopus 로고
    • pt. 1, chap. 32. For discussion of further references which mitigate the level of hatred one is obligated to harbor for the transgressor, see Yehudah ‘Amital, “Regarding the Status of the Secular Jew in Our Days” (Hebrew), ‘Alon Shvut le-Bogrei Yeshivat Har Etzyon, no. 6 (Elul 1988), pp. 11-12; Mordecai Gafni, “The Halakhic Approach Toward Secularists” (Hebrew), Mahanayim, May,.
    • Tanya’, pt. 1, chap. 32. For discussion of further references which mitigate the level of hatred one is obligated to harbor for the transgressor, see Yehudah ‘Amital, “Regarding the Status of the Secular Jew in Our Days” (Hebrew), ‘Alon Shvut le-Bogrei Yeshivat Har Etzyon, no. 6 (Elul 1988), pp. 11-12; Mordecai Gafni, “The Halakhic Approach Toward Secularists” (Hebrew), Mahanayim, pp. 189-190, May, 1993.
    • (1993) Tanya’ , pp. 189-190
  • 27
    • 85012496635 scopus 로고
    • The lack of choice stems from a recognition of the possibility of intellectual seduction. E.g., see R. Meir Simha Ha-cohen of Dvinsk (-1928) in Meshekh Hokhma, Shemot 3, 19, or R. Tzadoq Ha-cohen in Tzidqat ha-Tzaddiq, sec. 43. An even more ingenious and radical rationale for relating to modern heretics be-‘avotot ahavah (“lovingly”) rather than with tokhehah (“chastisement”), and not applying the law of kofrim to them, is suggested by the Hazon ‘Ish (Yoreh De'ah, Hilkhot Shehitah 2, end of n. 16): i.e., the fact that Divine Providence is not evident in our day.
    • A ruling by Maimonides that although it is a mitzvah to kill epiqorsim and mumarim who deny the divinity of the Torah, the children of such dissenters are to be regarded as tinoqot shenishbu who had no choice, serves as the basis for posqim in recent generations to regard current secularists leniently. The lack of choice stems from a recognition of the possibility of intellectual seduction. E.g., see R. Meir Simha Ha-cohen of Dvinsk (1843-1928) in Meshekh Hokhma, Shemot 3, 19, or R. Tzadoq Ha-cohen in Tzidqat ha-Tzaddiq, sec. 43. An even more ingenious and radical rationale for relating to modern heretics be-‘avotot ahavah (“lovingly”) rather than with tokhehah (“chastisement”), and not applying the law of kofrim to them, is suggested by the Hazon ‘Ish (Yoreh De'ah, Hilkhot Shehitah 2, end of n. 16): i.e., the fact that Divine Providence is not evident in our day.
    • (1843) A ruling by Maimonides that although it is a mitzvah to kill epiqorsim and mumarim who deny the divinity of the Torah, the children of such dissenters are to be regarded as tinoqot shenishbu who had no choice, serves as the basis for posqim in recent generations to regard current secularists leniently
  • 30
    • 85012562705 scopus 로고
    • (Jerusalem, ), pp.
    • igrotR'ayah I (Jerusalem, 1962), pp. 58, 160-161.
    • (1962) igrotR'ayah I , pp. 160-161
  • 31
    • 85012554406 scopus 로고
    • see Aviezer Ravitzky, Messianism, Zionism and Jewish Religious Radicalism (Hebrew) (Tel Aviv: Am Oved, Tel Aviv
    • For several examples of such criticism, see Aviezer Ravitzky, Messianism, Zionism and Jewish Religious Radicalism (Hebrew) (Tel Aviv: Am Oved, Tel Aviv, 1993), p. 160.
    • (1993) For several examples of such criticism , pp. 160
  • 32
    • 85012506545 scopus 로고
    • (Hebrew), in Be-Hevlei Massoret u-Temura (Rehovot
    • See Yosef Ahitov, “The Attitude Towards Secularists” (Hebrew), in Be-Hevlei Massoret u-Temura (Rehovot, 1990), pp. 35-50.
    • (1990) The Attitude Towards Secularists , pp. 35-50
    • Ahitov, Y.1
  • 33
    • 85012471005 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • pp. 20-21. Further development of this idea appears in R. Kook's letter to the Ridbaz (Igrot R'ayah II, ). In this letter R. Kook also employs another metaphysical concept to justify his refusal to distance himself from the secular Zionists, i.e., the midrashic understanding of the ‘erev rav (“mixed multitude”) as those who were destined to produce superior offspring in the generations that follow. The use of this notion relates to a kabbalistic dispute about whether the final redemption will be the result of a separation of the holy and the profane, or the sanctification of the profane and its elevation
    • Igrot R ‘ayah I, pp. 20-21. Further development of this idea appears in R. Kook's letter to the Ridbaz (Igrot R'ayah II, pp. 184-198). In this letter R. Kook also employs another metaphysical concept to justify his refusal to distance himself from the secular Zionists, i.e., the midrashic understanding of the ‘erev rav (“mixed multitude”) as those who were destined to produce superior offspring in the generations that follow. The use of this notion relates to a kabbalistic dispute about whether the final redemption will be the result of a separation of the holy and the profane, or the sanctification of the profane and its elevation.
    • Igrot R ‘ayah I , pp. 184-198
  • 35
    • 85012449900 scopus 로고
    • I, pp. 170-171, 368-370; ‘“Al Bamoteinu Halalim,” Ma'amarei R'ayah I (Jerusalem
    • J grot R'ayah II. I, pp. 170-171, 368-370; ‘“Al Bamoteinu Halalim,” Ma'amarei R'ayah I (Jerusalem, 1980), pp. 90-91.
    • (1980) J grot R'ayah II , pp. 90-91
  • 36
  • 37
    • 85012471005 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Igrot R'ayah I., pp. 170-171, 100-101.
    • Igrot R'ayah I , pp. 170-171
  • 39
    • 85012484259 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see the letter R. Kook wrote to his parents in Igrot R ‘ayah I, regarding the policy of those who opposed his approach to the secularists. (In this letter he displays great nobility and personal tolerance regarding his adversaries on this issue.)
    • For an expression of this view, see the letter R. Kook wrote to his parents in Igrot R ‘ayah I, pp. 352-353, regarding the policy of those who opposed his approach to the secularists. (In this letter he displays great nobility and personal tolerance regarding his adversaries on this issue.)
    • For an expression of this view , pp. 352-353
  • 45
    • 85012460131 scopus 로고
    • E.g., see Yosef Ahitov, “Reflections Regarding the Future of Relations with the Secularists” (Hebrew), in Be-Hevlei Massoret u-Temura, ed. Menahem Kahanah (Rehovot: Kivvunim
    • This is in contradiction to the view of some that R. Kook's tolerance never goes beyond the status of post-factum (bedi'avad). E.g., see Yosef Ahitov, “Reflections Regarding the Future of Relations with the Secularists” (Hebrew), in Be-Hevlei Massoret u-Temura, ed. Menahem Kahanah (Rehovot: Kivvunim, 1990), pp. 37-38.
    • (1990) This is in contradiction to the view of some that R. Kook's tolerance never goes beyond the status of post-factum (bedi'avad) , pp. 37-38
  • 46
    • 85012485178 scopus 로고
    • (Jerusalem
    • ‘Orotha-'Emunah (Jerusalem, 1985), pp. 66-67.
    • (1985) ‘Orotha-'Emunah , pp. 66-67
  • 47
    • 85012560719 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ma'amarei R'ayah I, sec.
    • “Talelei ‘Orot,” Ma'amarei R'ayah I, p. 26, sec. 8.
    • Talelei ‘Orot , pp. 26
  • 48
    • 85012497408 scopus 로고
    • (Jerusalem, 1963), pp. 176-177; ‘Orot ha-'Emunah, ‘Arpelei Tohar (Jerusalem, ), p.
    • ‘Orot ha-Qodesh I (Jerusalem, 1963), pp. 176-177; ‘Orot ha-'Emunah, pp. 67-68; ‘Arpelei Tohar (Jerusalem, 1983), p. 62.
    • (1983) ‘Orot ha-Qodesh I , pp. 67-68
  • 49
    • 85012492543 scopus 로고
    • (Jerusalem, ), p.
    • ‘Eder ha-Yaqar (Jerusalem, 1963), p. 14
    • (1963) ‘Eder ha-Yaqar
  • 50
    • 85012462590 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • pp. 14-15. See also “Ma'amar Meyuhad,” in Ma'amarei R'ayah I, p. 105; Igrot R'ayah
    • ‘Eder ha-Yaqar., pp. 14-15. See also “Ma'amar Meyuhad,” in Ma'amarei R'ayah I, p. 105; Igrot R'ayah, pp. 192-193.
    • ‘Eder ha-Yaqar , pp. 192-193
  • 51
    • 85012523865 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 22; ‘Orot ha-Emunah
    • ‘Orot ha-Qodesh I, 22; ‘Orot ha-Emunah, pp. 67-68.
    • ‘Orot ha-Qodesh I , pp. 67-68
  • 52
    • 85012561845 scopus 로고
    • (Jerusalem, ), introduction
    • ‘Orot ha-Qodesh III (Jerusalem, 1964), introduction, p. 26.
    • (1964) ‘Orot ha-Qodesh III , pp. 26
  • 53
    • 85012431750 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • p. 21; ‘Orot ha-Qodesh HI, introduction
    • ‘Orot ha-Emunah, p. 21; ‘Orot ha-Qodesh HI, introduction, p. 44.
    • ‘Orot ha-Emunah , pp. 44
  • 54
    • 85012476275 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ‘Orot, pp. 73-74.
    • ‘Orot , pp. 73-74
  • 55
    • 85012533000 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Igrot R'ayah, pp. 171-172.
    • Igrot R'ayah , pp. 171-172
  • 57
    • 85012435734 scopus 로고
    • 6 (Jerusalem, ), where love of the rasha’ is perceived as problematic because it could lead to a blurring of the distinction between the bearer of the wickedness and the wickedness itself.
    • E.g., see Ginzei R'ayah 6 (Jerusalem, 1990), p. 151, where love of the rasha’ is perceived as problematic because it could lead to a blurring of the distinction between the bearer of the wickedness and the wickedness itself.
    • (1990) see Ginzei R'ayah , pp. 151
  • 63
    • 85012533000 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • II
    • Igrot R'ayah II, pp. 184-198.
    • Igrot R'ayah , pp. 184-198
  • 68
    • 85012501206 scopus 로고
    • 2nd ed. (London, 1897) and Essays on Truth and Reality (Oxford, ).
    • See particularly his Appearance and Reality, 2nd ed. (London, 1897) and Essays on Truth and Reality (Oxford, 1914).
    • (1914) particularly his Appearance and Reality
  • 69
    • 85012431750 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (a parallel passage appears in ‘Arpelei Tohar, p. 45).
    • ‘Orot ha-Emunah, pp. 23-24 (a parallel passage appears in ‘Arpelei Tohar, p. 45).
    • ‘Orot ha-Emunah , pp. 23-24
  • 71
    • 85012483283 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Igrot R'ayah I, p. 47) describes the Jewish understanding of all human perceptions as “subjective and relative,” without adding any further distinctions.
    • The danger is intensified by the fact that R. Kook himself (Igrot R'ayah I, p. 47) describes the Jewish understanding of all human perceptions as “subjective and relative,” without adding any further distinctions.
    • The danger is intensified by the fact that R. Kook himself
  • 72
    • 85012478729 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • p. 403; The danger is intensified by the fact that R. Kook himself. Ill
    • ‘Orot ha-Qodesh II, p. 403; The danger is intensified by the fact that R. Kook himself. Ill, p. 327.
    • ‘Orot ha-Qodesh II , pp. 327
  • 73
    • 85012454799 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ma'amarei R'ayah II
    • “Ne'edar ba-Qodesh,” Ma'amarei R'ayah II, p. 400.
    • Ne'edar ba-Qodesh , pp. 400
  • 74
    • 85012532514 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • R'ayah
    • Igrot R'ayah 1, p. 164.
    • Igrot , pp. 164
  • 75
  • 78
    • 85012540731 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • p. 327; see also ‘Orot ha-Qodesh II
    • ‘Orot ha-Qodesh III, p. 327; see also ‘Orot ha-Qodesh II, p. 484.
    • ‘Orot ha-Qodesh III , pp. 484
  • 79
    • 85012541875 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ‘Orot, pp. 130-131.
    • ‘Orot , pp. 130-131
  • 82
    • 85012431750 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ‘Orot, p. 105.
    • ‘Orot, pp. 42-44, ‘Orot ha-'Emunah, p. 105.
    • Orot ha-'Emunah , pp. 42-44
  • 83
    • 85012525992 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The fact that Jewish society is composed of households and families, rather than individuals, as the basic unit guarantees the Jewish woman her unique position within her home, and spares her the need to resort to the indignities of political hustling (Igrot R'ayah III, ).
    • E.g., see R. Kook's remarks on the status of the Jewish woman. The fact that Jewish society is composed of households and families, rather than individuals, as the basic unit guarantees the Jewish woman her unique position within her home, and spares her the need to resort to the indignities of political hustling (Igrot R'ayah III, pp. 50-51).
    • see R. Kook's remarks on the status of the Jewish woman , pp. 50-51
  • 84
    • 85012442147 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ‘Orot, pp. 130-131.
    • ‘Orot , pp. 130-131
  • 85
    • 85012471005 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Igrot R'ayah I
    • Igrot R'ayah I, pp. 19-20.
  • 86
    • 85012498922 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • in delineating the nature of modem nationalism.
    • ‘Orot, p. 152, sec. 2. This theme was also stressed by Mazzini, in delineating the nature of modem nationalism.
    • This theme was also stressed by Mazzini , pp. 152
  • 87
    • 85012505499 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 64, sec. 10; “Talelei ‘Orot,” Ma'amarei R'ayah I, p. 21; “Le-mahalah ha-'Ideiot be-Yisrael,” ‘Orot
    • ‘Orot. 64, sec. 10; “Talelei ‘Orot,” Ma'amarei R'ayah I, p. 21; “Le-mahalah ha-'Ideiot be-Yisrael,” ‘Orot, p. 120.
    • ‘Orot , pp. 120
  • 88
    • 85012546214 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • pp. 129-130, 138; ‘Olat R'ayah I,. R. Kook's view of knesset yisrael as the concentrate of all humanity is rooted in the special status that this concept has in qabbalistic symbolism, where knesset yisrael is equated with malhut, the lowest sefira, which serves as a final receptacle for the bounty of all the higher sefirot that flow into it. This sefira is characterized by the fact that it has no special character of its own. Its lack of a distinguishing quality is just what allows it to best serve as a sponge for collecting all the others, for its own character poses no barrier.
    • ‘Orot, pp. 129-130, 138; ‘Olat R'ayah I, pp. 376-377. R. Kook's view of knesset yisrael as the concentrate of all humanity is rooted in the special status that this concept has in qabbalistic symbolism, where knesset yisrael is equated with malhut, the lowest sefira, which serves as a final receptacle for the bounty of all the higher sefirot that flow into it. This sefira is characterized by the fact that it has no special character of its own. Its lack of a distinguishing quality is just what allows it to best serve as a sponge for collecting all the others, for its own character poses no barrier.
    • ‘Orot , pp. 376-377
  • 89
    • 85012516425 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • pp. 3, 105-106; ‘Orot ha-Teshuvah, chap. 5, sec. 2; ‘Orot ha-Qodesh III, ‘Orot, p. 138, sec.
    • ‘Arpelei Tohai; pp. 3, 105-106; ‘Orot ha-Teshuvah, chap. 5, sec. 2; ‘Orot ha-Qodesh III, pp. 65-66; ‘Orot, p. 138, sec. 3.
    • ‘Arpelei Tohai; , pp. 65-66
  • 91
    • 85012480232 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 64; ‘Orot, p.
    • ‘Arpelei Tohar, pp. 56-57, 64; ‘Orot, p. 138.
    • ‘Arpelei Tohar , pp. 56-57
  • 92
    • 85012431812 scopus 로고
    • (Jerusalem, ), pp. 124-125; ‘Orot, pp. 63-64, sec. 9; IggerotR'ayah n,.
    • ‘Ikveiha-Tzon (Jerusalem, 1963), pp. 124-125; ‘Orot, pp. 63-64, sec. 9; IggerotR'ayah n,pp. 186-187.
    • (1963) ‘Ikveiha-Tzon , pp. 186-187
  • 93
    • 85012505623 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • pp. 147-148; Orot ha-Qodesh III, pp. 117-118; ‘Olat R'ayah II, pp. 43-44; ‘Orot ha-Qodesh II
    • ‘Ilcvei ha-Tzon, pp. 147-148; Orot ha-Qodesh III, pp. 117-118; ‘Olat R'ayah II, pp. 43-44; ‘Orot ha-Qodesh II, pp. 561-562.
    • ‘Ilcvei ha-Tzon , pp. 561-562
  • 94
    • 85012483640 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Igrot Rayah II, ‘Orot
    • p. 144, sec.
    • ‘Igrot Rayah II, pp. 65-66; ‘Orot, p. 144, sec. 3.
  • 97
    • 85012480232 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • pp. 56-57; ‘Orot ha-Qodesh III, “Ikvei ha-Tzon, p.
    • ‘Arpelei Tohar, pp. 56-57; ‘Orot ha-Qodesh III, pp. 349-350; “Ikvei ha-Tzon, p. 123.
    • ‘Arpelei Tohar , pp. 349-350
  • 98
    • 85012443928 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (‘Orot, p. 138, sec. 2). Because they contain all tendencies, the Jewish people are more prone to inner conflict. For the same reason, they are more self-sufficient, (‘Arpelei Tohar., p. 169). Another difference is the creative power of the history and culture of the Jewish people. The national cultures of other nations merely rearrange what already exists in various forms and constellations; they describe and preserve. But Jewish creativity is ex nihilo, true innovation (‘Orot ha-Qodesh III, ). This is similar to the view of R. Yehudah Halevi, who also held that Israel's uniqueness did consist in its comprising an organism separate from the rest Of humanity, but rather in its serving as the heart of the general universal organism. There is no room for questions of equality within an organism, because all parts of the hierarchy work together for the common good. It is only when the various elements are viewed in partial, individual terms that there is room for talk of inequity.
    • According to R. Kook, the Jewish people's unique comprehensive quality of concentrating all powers and meshing them into one coherent whole gives rise to concomitant other qualities, just as one is not surprised that the brain and heart of the individual organism exhibit manifestations of life that are not found in the rest of the body (‘Orot, p. 138, sec. 2). Because they contain all tendencies, the Jewish people are more prone to inner conflict. For the same reason, they are more self-sufficient, (‘Arpelei Tohar., p. 169). Another difference is the creative power of the history and culture of the Jewish people. The national cultures of other nations merely rearrange what already exists in various forms and constellations; they describe and preserve. But Jewish creativity is ex nihilo, true innovation (‘Orot ha-Qodesh III, pp. 67-69). This is similar to the view of R. Yehudah Halevi, who also held that Israel's uniqueness did consist in its comprising an organism separate from the rest Of humanity, but rather in its serving as the heart of the general universal organism. There is no room for questions of equality within an organism, because all parts of the hierarchy work together for the common good. It is only when the various elements are viewed in partial, individual terms that there is room for talk of inequity.
    • According to R. Kook, the Jewish people's unique comprehensive quality of concentrating all powers and meshing them into one coherent whole gives rise to concomitant other qualities, just as one is not surprised that the brain and heart of the individual organism exhibit manifestations of life that are not found in the rest of the body , pp. 67-69
  • 99
    • 85012532742 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • sec.
    • ‘Orot, p. 156, sec. 11.
    • ‘Orot , pp. 156
  • 101
    • 85012568771 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ‘Iggerot R'ayah I, pp. 48*9.
    • ‘Orot, pp. 73-74; ‘Iggerot R'ayah I, pp. 48*9.
    • ‘Orot , pp. 73-74
  • 102
    • 85012514784 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (appealing to the religious on prudential grounds, in the interest of social cohesion, and to the secularists in terms of their ideological commitment to pluralism), see Hed, “Two Concepts of Liberalism,”
    • For a modified version of the more usual suggestion of a modus vivendi between the religious and secular camps, which works in reverse (appealing to the religious on prudential grounds, in the interest of social cohesion, and to the secularists in terms of their ideological commitment to pluralism), see Hed, “Two Concepts of Liberalism,” pp. 183-184.
    • For a modified version of the more usual suggestion of a modus vivendi between the religious and secular camps, which works in reverse , pp. 183-184
  • 104
    • 85012540078 scopus 로고
    • see Rivka Shatz, “R. Kook's Stand Regarding the Question of Religious Legislation in 1920” (Hebrew), Kivvunim
    • For a discussion of this exchange, see Rivka Shatz, “R. Kook's Stand Regarding the Question of Religious Legislation in 1920” (Hebrew), Kivvunim 33 (1986): 101-104.
    • (1986) For a discussion of this exchange , pp. 101-104
  • 105
    • 85012568585 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • it is worth noting that R. Zvi Yehudah objected to nonobservant visitors donning a head covering merely out of deference to him when such practice was unaccompanied by inner conviction. He was also a card-carrying member of the League Against Religious Coercion until he became convinced that his unlikely colleagues had no comparable objection to the coercion of secular practices. See Yaron, Philosophy of R. Kook
    • If the son's behavior is any measure of the father's policy, it is worth noting that R. Zvi Yehudah objected to nonobservant visitors donning a head covering merely out of deference to him when such practice was unaccompanied by inner conviction. He was also a card-carrying member of the League Against Religious Coercion until he became convinced that his unlikely colleagues had no comparable objection to the coercion of secular practices. See Yaron, Philosophy of R. Kook, p. 337, n. 40.
    • If the son's behavior is any measure of the father's policy , pp. 337
  • 106
    • 85012571369 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see Locke's Epistola de Tolerantia, published in 1688. This most likely served as the subsequent basis for viewing autonomous decision as a necessary prerequisite of morality in Kantian ethics.
    • For one of the earliest systematic presentations of this argument, see Locke's Epistola de Tolerantia, published in 1688. This most likely served as the subsequent basis for viewing autonomous decision as a necessary prerequisite of morality in Kantian ethics.
    • For one of the earliest systematic presentations of this argument
  • 107
    • 84949367565 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see Sagie, “Jewish Religion.”
    • For sources, see Sagie, “Jewish Religion.”
    • For sources
  • 108
    • 85012534613 scopus 로고
    • See also Joseph Agassi, Religion and Nationality: Toward an Israeli National Identity (Hebrew) (Tel Aviv: Papyrus, ).
    • As proposed by Yesh'ayahu Leibowitz in his writings. See also Joseph Agassi, Religion and Nationality: Toward an Israeli National Identity (Hebrew) (Tel Aviv: Papyrus, 1984).
    • (1984) As proposed by Yesh'ayahu Leibowitz in his writings
  • 111
    • 85012455992 scopus 로고
    • see Charles Taylor, “Cross-Purposes: The Liberal-Communitarian Debate.” in Liberalism and the Moral Life, ed. Nancy L. Rosenblum (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1989); Allen E. Buchanan, “Assessing the Communitarian Critique of Liberalism,” Ethics 99 (July
    • For a more extensive account of communitarianism and its critique of liberalism, see Charles Taylor, “Cross-Purposes: The Liberal-Communitarian Debate.” in Liberalism and the Moral Life, ed. Nancy L. Rosenblum (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1989); Allen E. Buchanan, “Assessing the Communitarian Critique of Liberalism,” Ethics 99 (July 1989): 852-882.
    • (1989) For a more extensive account of communitarianism and its critique of liberalism , pp. 852-882
  • 113
    • 85012474253 scopus 로고
    • (Paper presented at the Ninth Annual Social Philosophy Conference, Davidson College, North Carolina, August ).
    • David D. Duquette, “Liberal Purposes and Community” (Paper presented at the Ninth Annual Social Philosophy Conference, Davidson College, North Carolina, August 1992).
    • (1992) Liberal Purposes and Community
    • Duquette, D.D.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.