메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 55, Issue 1, 1996, Pages 89-121

Citizenship and obligation: Civil disobedience and civil dissent

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 85012469198     PISSN: 00081973     EISSN: 14692139     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S0008197300097750     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (8)

References (120)
  • 1
    • 84866556576 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • West Virginia Stale Boardof Education v. Barnette
    • 641
    • West Virginia Stale Boardof Education v. Barnette 319 U.S. 624, 641.
    • U.S , vol.319 , pp. 624
  • 2
    • 85012567868 scopus 로고
    • See, (Chicago), “A free society is one in which you cannot defame the government.”
    • See Harry Kalven, Jr. The Negro and the First Amendment (Chicago 1965), p. 16: “A free society is one in which you cannot defame the government.”
    • (1965) The Negro and the First Amendment , pp. 16
    • Kalven, H.1
  • 3
    • 85012540162 scopus 로고
    • Cf. (London) I, ch. 6, esp.
    • Cf. John Plamenatz, Man and Society (London 1963) I, ch. 6, esp. pp. 220–241;
    • (1963) Man and Society , pp. 220-241
    • Plamenatz, J.1
  • 4
    • 5844243437 scopus 로고
    • (Oxford) pp. Plamenatz, rejecting Locke's conception, defends a notion of “indirect” consent, based on a democratic form of government
    • Geoffrey Marshall, Constitutional Theory (Oxford 1971) pp. 208–211. Plamenatz, rejecting Locke's conception, defends a notion of “indirect” consent, based on a democratic form of government.
    • (1971) Constitutional Theory , pp. 208-211
    • Marshall, G.1
  • 7
    • 0007074450 scopus 로고
    • For the distinction between the “coverage” and “protection” of a right (such as a right to free speech), see, (Cambridge) pp
    • For the distinction between the “coverage” and “protection” of a right (such as a right to free speech), see Frederick Schauer, Free Speech: A Philosophical Enquiry (Cambridge 1982) pp. 8992.
    • (1982) Free Speech: A Philosophical Enquiry , pp. 8992
    • Schauer, F.1
  • 9
    • 34248543738 scopus 로고
    • A Theory of Freedom of Expression
    • discussing
    • discussing Thomas Scanlon, “A Theory of Freedom of Expression“ Philosophy and Public Affairs 1 (1972), 204.
    • (1972) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.1 , pp. 204
    • Scanlon, T.1
  • 11
    • 84978332420 scopus 로고
    • Free Speech as Toleration
    • See also, in W.J. Waluchow (ed.), (Oxford)
    • See also Richards, “Free Speech as Toleration“ in W.J. Waluchow (ed.), Free Expression: Essays in Law & Philosophy (Oxford 1994).
    • (1994) Free Expression: Essays in Law & Philosophy
    • Richards1
  • 12
    • 84927454448 scopus 로고
    • Justification and Judicial Responsibility
    • esp 193–199
    • “Justification and Judicial Responsibility“ (1984) 72 Calif. L.R. 178, esp 193–199;
    • (1984) Calif. L.R , vol.72 , pp. 178
  • 14
    • 0347508271 scopus 로고
    • The Concept of Law and The Concept of Law'
    • Cf.
    • Cf. Neil MacCormick, “The Concept of Law and The Concept of Law'“ (1994) 14 Oxford J. Legal Stud. 1.
    • (1994) Oxford J. Legal Stud , vol.14 , pp. 1
    • MacCormick, N.1
  • 15
    • 0000580092 scopus 로고
    • Legal Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals
    • See also
    • See also H.L.A. Hart, “Legal Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals“ (1958–1959) 71 Harv. L.R. 598
    • (1958) Harv. L.R , vol.71 , pp. 598
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 17
    • 84866556576 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 319 U.S. 624 (1943).
    • (1943) U.S , vol.319 , pp. 624
  • 18
    • 85012514797 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • U.S. 642.
    • U.S , pp. 642
  • 19
    • 85012431767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • U.S. 653–655.
    • U.S , pp. 653-655
  • 20
    • 84892318796 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Minersvilk School District Board of Education v. Gobitis
    • Cf. 594–595 (Frankfurter J.)
    • Cf. Minersvilk School District Board of Education v. Gobitis 310 U.S. 586, 594–595 (Frankfurter J.).
    • U.S , vol.310 , pp. 586
  • 24
  • 29
    • 0012343251 scopus 로고
    • The Rule of Law and its Virtue
    • See, For a wider conception of the rule of law, encompassing legal tradition and the necessary culture of legality
    • See Joseph Raz, “The Rule of Law and its Virtue“ (1977) 93 L.Q.R. 195. For a wider conception of the rule of law, encompassing legal tradition and the necessary culture of legality
    • (1977) L.Q.R , vol.93 , pp. 195
    • Raz, J.1
  • 31
  • 32
    • 84922802039 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Finnis takes the attitude of the conscientious, law-abiding citizen as exemplifying the focal or central case of law: “a viewpoint in which the establishment and maintenance of legal. order is regarded as a moral ideal if not a compelling demand of justice”: Legal Obligation, p. 14
    • Cf. John Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights, above. Finnis takes the attitude of the conscientious, law-abiding citizen as exemplifying the focal or central case of law: “a viewpoint in which the establishment and maintenance of legal. order is regarded as a moral ideal if not a compelling demand of justice”: Legal Obligation, p. 14.
    • Natural Law and Natural Rights, above
    • Finnis, J.1
  • 33
    • 54349110135 scopus 로고
    • The rule of law, as here interpreted, therefore discourages the adoption of rules which some citizens can obey only at the cost of violating conscience. For his part, the citizen must make appropriate allowance, consistently with conscience, for the importance of accommodation with others in the interest of the common good. Cf. (New York) esp. Lectures 2 and 4
    • The rule of law, as here interpreted, therefore discourages the adoption of rules which some citizens can obey only at the cost of violating conscience. For his part, the citizen must make appropriate allowance, consistently with conscience, for the importance of accommodation with others in the interest of the common good. Cf. Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York 1993) esp. Lectures 2 and 4.
    • (1993) Political Liberalism
    • Rawls1
  • 35
    • 0004220262 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2nd ed. (Oxford) esp. ch. 2 and pp. 82–91
    • The Concept of Law, 2nd ed. (Oxford 1994) esp. ch. 2 and pp. 51–61, 82–91.
    • (1994) The Concept of Law , pp. 51-61
  • 42
    • 8344244497 scopus 로고
    • An objection which Hart subsequently appeared to concede: see his review of Fuller's Morality of Law in at p. 1294, reprinted in Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy, note 10 above, pp. 361–362
    • An objection which Hart subsequently appeared to concede: see his review of Fuller's Morality of Law in (1965) 78 Harv. L.R. 1281 at p. 1294, reprinted in Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy, note 10 above, pp. 361–362.
    • (1965) Harv. L.R , vol.78 , pp. 1281
  • 43
    • 0003566257 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Neil MacCormick has observed that, “What must be essential to the ‘internal aspect’ of the rule of recognition is some conscious commitment to pursuing the political values which are perceived as underpinning it, and to sustaining in concrete form the political principles deemed inherent in the constituted order of the society in question”: (Oxford) pp
    • Neil MacCormick has observed that, “What must be essential to the ‘internal aspect’ of the rule of recognition is some conscious commitment to pursuing the political values which are perceived as underpinning it, and to sustaining in concrete form the political principles deemed inherent in the constituted order of the society in question”: Legal Reasoning and Legal Theory (Oxford 1978) pp. 139–140.
    • (1978) Legal Reasoning and Legal Theory , pp. 139-140
  • 45
    • 84880890810 scopus 로고
    • Hart's Concept of Law
    • cf., in Robert S. Summers (ed), (Oxford) p
    • cf. Rolf Sartorius, “Hart's Concept of Law“, in Robert S. Summers (ed), More Essays in Legal Philosophy (Oxford 1971) p. 131.
    • (1971) More Essays in Legal Philosophy , pp. 131
    • Sartorius, R.1
  • 46
    • 85012463717 scopus 로고
    • For the hermeneutic, as distinguished from the internal, point of view, see, and H.L.A. Hart (London) ch. 3
    • For the hermeneutic, as distinguished from the internal, point of view, see Neil MacCormick, Legal Reasoning and Legal Theory, above, Appendix, and H.L.A. Hart (London 1981) ch. 3
    • (1981) Legal Reasoning and Legal Theory, above, Appendix
    • MacCormick, N.1
  • 47
  • 49
    • 0004220262 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 23 above, (Postscript)
    • The Concept of Law, note 23 above, pp. 239–244 (Postscript).
    • The Concept of Law , pp. 239-244
  • 50
    • 84936068266 scopus 로고
    • The interpretative legal theory of Ronald Dworkin entails similar conclusions, as I have tried to show elsewhere: see, (London)
    • The interpretative legal theory of Ronald Dworkin entails similar conclusions, as I have tried to show elsewhere: see Ronald Dworkin, Law's Empire (London 1986)
    • (1986) Law's Empire
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 51
    • 84974277670 scopus 로고
    • Justice and Fairness in Law's Empire
    • T.R.S. Allan, “Justice and Fairness in Law's Empire“ [1993] C.L.J. 64.
    • (1993) C.L.J , pp. 64
    • Allan, T.R.S.1
  • 52
    • 84856648926 scopus 로고
    • Church of the Lukumi Babalu Aye v. City of Hialeah
    • 519
    • Church of the Lukumi Babalu Aye v. City of Hialeah 124 L.Ed.2d 472, 519 (1993).
    • (1993) L.Ed.2d , vol.124 , pp. 472
  • 53
    • 27744517261 scopus 로고
    • Wisconsin v. Yoder
    • See also
    • See also Wisconsin v. Yoder 406 U.S. 205 (1972)
    • (1972) U.S , vol.406 , pp. 205
  • 54
    • 33746436655 scopus 로고
    • Employment Division, Dept. of Human Resources of Oregon v. Smith
    • Employment Division, Dept. of Human Resources of Oregon v. Smith 494 U.S. 872 (1990).
    • (1990) U.S , vol.494 , pp. 872
  • 55
    • 84855883464 scopus 로고
    • U.S. v. Seeger
    • U.S. v. Seeger 380 U.S. 163 (1965)
    • (1965) U.S , vol.380 , pp. 163
  • 56
    • 84897238810 scopus 로고
    • Welsh v. U.S.
    • 342
    • Welsh v. U.S. 398 U.S. 333, 342–343 (1970).
    • (1970) U.S , vol.398 , pp. 333-343
  • 57
    • 84883214856 scopus 로고
    • Gillette v. U.S.
    • Appropriate respect for conscience also favours the exemption of non-pacifists who object to participation in a particular war on account of its perceived injustice. Douglas J., who described “conscience and belief as the “bedrock of free speech as well as religion”, thought that restricting exemption to pacifist objectors constituted “an invidious discrimination in favour of religious persons and against others with like scruples”:, 465–469 (Douglas J. dissenting). Gillette resisted conscription on the ground of his opposition to the Vietnam conflict as an unjust war. For further discussion
    • Appropriate respect for conscience also favours the exemption of non-pacifists who object to participation in a particular war on account of its perceived injustice. Douglas J. who described “conscience and belief as the “bedrock of free speech as well as religion”, thought that restricting exemption to pacifist objectors constituted “an invidious discrimination in favour of religious persons and against others with like scruples”: Gillette v. U.S. 401 U.S. 437, 465–469 (1971) (Douglas J. dissenting). Gillette resisted conscription on the ground of his opposition to the Vietnam conflict as an unjust war. For further discussion
    • (1971) U.S , vol.401 , pp. 437
  • 59
    • 85012569112 scopus 로고
    • The British experience in the 2nd World War is briefly discussed by, (Oxford) pp
    • The British experience in the 2nd World War is briefly discussed by Peter Singer, Democracy and Disobedience (Oxford 1974) pp. 101–102.
    • (1974) Democracy and Disobedience , pp. 101-102
    • Singer, P.1
  • 62
    • 85012482209 scopus 로고
    • For the complexities involved where several groups have legitimate grounds for disobedience, and there is the consequent risk of serious disorder, see, (Oxford) pp
    • For the complexities involved where several groups have legitimate grounds for disobedience, and there is the consequent risk of serious disorder, see John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Oxford 1972) pp. 373–375.
    • (1972) A Theory of Justice , pp. 373-375
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 68
    • 0009131584 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For analysis of the reasons for obedience to law based on the conception of democracy as a fair compromise between competing claims to power, see, note 36 above
    • For analysis of the reasons for obedience to law based on the conception of democracy as a fair compromise between competing claims to power, see Peter Singer, Democracy and Disobedience, note 36 above.
    • Democracy and Disobedience
    • Singer, P.1
  • 69
    • 84969757875 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For conflicting requirements of justice and fairness, see, note 32 above
    • For conflicting requirements of justice and fairness, see Dworkin, Law's Empire, note 32 above
    • Law's Empire
    • Dworkin1
  • 71
    • 0039948325 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf., note 6 above, p. Scanlon argues that autonomous citizens could not concede to the state the right to have its decrees obeyed without deliberation
    • Cf. Scanlon, “A Theory of Freedom of Expression“, note 6 above, p. 214. Scanlon argues that autonomous citizens could not concede to the state the right to have its decrees obeyed without deliberation.
    • A Theory of Freedom of Expression , pp. 214
    • Scanlon1
  • 72
    • 85012511741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 36 above, (See also pp. 138–142.) Walzer also observes that we can regard the state as being composed of consenting citizens only in so far as the legitimacy of “secondary associations with limited claims to primacy” is recognised: A Theory of Freedom of Expression. pp. 18–19. The implications of pluralism for the role of freedom of expression are explored by Raz, Ethics in the Public Domain, note 4 above, ch. 6
    • Obligations, note 36 above, p. 132. (See also pp. 138–142.) Walzer also observes that we can regard the state as being composed of consenting citizens only in so far as the legitimacy of “secondary associations with limited claims to primacy” is recognised: A Theory of Freedom of Expression. pp. 18–19. The implications of pluralism for the role of freedom of expression are explored by Raz, Ethics in the Public Domain, note 4 above, ch. 6.
    • Obligations , pp. 132
  • 73
    • 84891471166 scopus 로고
    • Cf
    • Cf. X v. Morgan-Grampian [1991] 1 A.C. 1
    • (1991) A.C , vol.1 , pp. 1
  • 76
    • 84922802039 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In describing his conduct as disobedience to law the dissentient may, of course, simply use language which reflects the viewpoint of others—a viewpoint which he does not actually share: cf. note 16 above
    • In describing his conduct as disobedience to law the dissentient may, of course, simply use language which reflects the viewpoint of others—a viewpoint which he does not actually share: cf. Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights, note 16 above, pp. 234–237.
    • Natural Law and Natural Rights , pp. 234-237
    • Finnis1
  • 77
    • 84971104286 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 37 above
    • A Theory of Justice, note 37 above, pp. 363–391.
    • A Theory of Justice , pp. 363-391
  • 78
    • 0009131584 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It should be noted that civil disobedience need not be limited to an appeal to a common conception of justice, but may invoke principles of justice which the majority ought to recognise: see, note 36 above
    • It should be noted that civil disobedience need not be limited to an appeal to a common conception of justice, but may invoke principles of justice which the majority ought to recognise: see Peter Singer, Democracy and Disobedience, note 36 above, pp. 86–90.
    • Democracy and Disobedience , pp. 86-90
    • Singer, P.1
  • 79
    • 85012544867 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Although Rawls's account of the rule of law is largely formal or procedural, it obtains its significance from the theory of justice. To his description of a legal system as “a coercive order of public rules addressed to rational persons for the purpose of regulating their conduct and providing the framework for social co-operation”, Rawls adds: (op.cil. note 37 above, p.)
    • Although Rawls's account of the rule of law is largely formal or procedural, it obtains its significance from the theory of justice. To his description of a legal system as “a coercive order of public rules addressed to rational persons for the purpose of regulating their conduct and providing the framework for social co-operation”, Rawls adds: “When these rules are just they establish a basis for legitimate expectations“ (op.cil. note 37 above, p. 235).
    • When these rules are just they establish a basis for legitimate expectations , pp. 235
  • 82
    • 85012544867 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • p. emphasis added. In so far as Rawls treats gravely unjust requirements as valid laws, despite their violation of the principles of justice for which his theory provides, his account seems confused
    • When these rules are just they establish a basis for legitimate expectations. p. 351, emphasis added. In so far as Rawls treats gravely unjust requirements as valid laws, despite their violation of the principles of justice for which his theory provides, his account seems confused.
    • When these rules are just they establish a basis for legitimate expectations , pp. 351
  • 86
    • 84971104286 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 37 above
    • A Theory of Justice, note 37 above, pp. 387–388.
    • A Theory of Justice , pp. 387-388
  • 87
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고
    • See also, (New York) Lecture 4
    • See also Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York 1993) Lecture 4.
    • (1993) Political Liberalism
    • Rawls1
  • 89
    • 0004220262 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For discussion of such theories, see, above, chs. 2 & 3
    • For discussion of such theories, see Hart, The Concept of Law, above, chs. 2 & 3.
    • The Concept of Law
    • Hart1
  • 90
    • 0021786482 scopus 로고
    • 155–159
    • [1985] 2 All E.R. 151, 155–159.
    • (1985) All E.R , vol.2 , pp. 151
  • 91
    • 85012565802 scopus 로고
    • 1080
    • [1985] A.C. 1054, 1080.
    • (1985) A.C , pp. 1054
  • 92
    • 84903086134 scopus 로고
    • Free Speech and the Advocacy of Illegal Action in Law and Political Theory
    • Cf.
    • Cf. Sheldon L. Leader, “Free Speech and the Advocacy of Illegal Action in Law and Political Theory“ (1982) 82 Col.L. Rev. 412.
    • (1982) Col.L. Rev , vol.82 , pp. 412
    • Leader, S.L.1
  • 93
    • 32144452595 scopus 로고
    • 249 U.S. 47 (1919).
    • (1919) U.S , vol.249 , pp. 47
  • 94
    • 85012488841 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • U.S. 52.
    • U.S , pp. 52
  • 95
    • 84998172138 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. note 61 above
    • Cf. Rawls, Political Liberalism, note 61 above, pp. 348–356.
    • Political Liberalism , pp. 348-356
    • Rawls1
  • 96
    • 79851502055 scopus 로고
    • Debs v. U.S.
    • See also, upholding the conviction of a socialist candidate for the presidency, under the Espionage Act 1917, for a public speech denouncing the war with Germany, on the ground that the natural and intended effect of the speech was to obstruct recruiting
    • See also Debs v. U.S. 249 U.S. 211 (1919), upholding the conviction of a socialist candidate for the presidency, under the Espionage Act 1917, for a public speech denouncing the war with Germany, on the ground that the natural and intended effect of the speech was to obstruct recruiting.
    • (1919) U.S , vol.249 , pp. 211
  • 97
    • 32144448339 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 376
    • 274 U.S. 357, 376 (1927).
    • (1927) U.S , vol.274 , pp. 357
  • 98
    • 33645100624 scopus 로고
    • Gitlow v. New York
    • Cf, 673 (Holmes J. dissenting)
    • Cf Gitlow v. New York 268 U.S. 652, 673 (1925) (Holmes J. dissenting).
    • (1925) U.S , vol.268 , pp. 652
  • 99
    • 85012508064 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 274 U.S. 375–376.
    • U.S , vol.274 , pp. 375-376
  • 100
    • 84870191142 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Frohwerk v. U.S.
    • 208
    • Frohwerk v. U.S. 249 U.S. 204, 208 (1919).
    • (1919) U.S , vol.249 , pp. 204
  • 101
    • 85012535321 scopus 로고
    • 684
    • R. v. Arrowsmith [1975] 1 Q.B. 678, 684.
    • (1975) Q.B , vol.1 , pp. 678
    • Arrowsmith, R.v.1
  • 102
    • 84998172138 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 61 above
    • Political Liberalism, note 61 above, pp. 345–346.
    • Political Liberalism , pp. 345-346
  • 105
    • 32144459811 scopus 로고
    • Brandenburg v. Ohio
    • See, 447
    • See Brandenburg v. Ohio 395 U.S. 444, 447 (1969).
    • (1969) U.S , vol.395 , pp. 444
  • 106
    • 85012516033 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf., note 69 above
    • Cf. Sheldon Leader, “Free Speech“, note 69 above, pp. 431–432.
    • Free Speech , pp. 431-432
    • Leader, S.1
  • 107
    • 84870191142 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Frohwerk v. U.S.
    • (above), 206
    • Frohwerk v. U.S. (above) 249 U.S. 204, 206.
    • U.S , vol.249 , pp. 204
  • 108
    • 84878234390 scopus 로고
    • Nolo v. U.S.
    • It follows that the distinction drawn in the American cases, between the “abstract teaching. of the moral propriety or even moral necessity for a resort to force and violence”, on one hand, and the preparation of “a group for violent action and steeling it to such action”, on the other, may be defended as a coherent constraint on freedom of speech: see, 297–298
    • It follows that the distinction drawn in the American cases, between the “abstract teaching. of the moral propriety or even moral necessity for a resort to force and violence”, on one hand, and the preparation of “a group for violent action and steeling it to such action”, on the other, may be defended as a coherent constraint on freedom of speech: see Nolo v. U.S. 367 U.S. 290, 297–298 (1961).
    • (1961) U.S , vol.367 , pp. 290
  • 109
    • 32144448339 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Whitney v. California
    • Cf. 376 (1927) (Brandeis J.)
    • Cf. Whitney v. California 274 U.S. 357, 376 (1927) (Brandeis J.).
    • U.S , vol.274 , pp. 357
  • 110
    • 32144459811 scopus 로고
    • Brandenburg v. Ohio
    • Advocacy which is “directed to inciting or producing imminent lawless action”, and likely to incite or produce it, where the action entails coercion and violence, can legitimately be proscribed:, 447
    • Advocacy which is “directed to inciting or producing imminent lawless action”, and likely to incite or produce it, where the action entails coercion and violence, can legitimately be proscribed: Brandenburg v. Ohio 395 U.S. 444, 447 (1969).
    • (1969) U.S , vol.395 , pp. 444
  • 111
    • 84971104286 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 37 above
    • A Theory of Justice, note 37 above, p. 366.
    • A Theory of Justice , pp. 366
  • 114
    • 32144448339 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Whitney v. California
    • Cf. 377–378 (Brandeis J.)
    • Cf. Whitney v. California 274 U.S. 357, 377–378 (Brandeis J.).
    • U.S , vol.274 , pp. 357
  • 117
    • 27744567278 scopus 로고
    • Texas v. Johnson
    • Cf
    • Cf. Texas v. Johnson 491 U.S. 397 (1989).
    • (1989) U.S , vol.491 , pp. 397
  • 118
    • 79961239211 scopus 로고
    • Stromberg v. California
    • Stromberg v. California 283 U.S. 359 (1931).
    • (1931) U.S , vol.283 , pp. 359
  • 119
    • 85109807146 scopus 로고
    • U.S. v. O'Brien
    • 67 note Harlan J.'s qualified concurrence at 388–389
    • U.S. v. O'Brien 391 U.S. 3 67 (1968); note Harlan J.'s qualified concurrence at 388–389.
    • (1968) U.S , vol.391 , pp. 3


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.