메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 40, Issue 4, 2001, Pages 651-668

Berkeley on the Act-Object Distinction

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 85011525707     PISSN: 00122173     EISSN: 17590949     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S0012217300004923     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (13)

References (52)
  • 1
    • 0001726721 scopus 로고
    • The Refutation of Idealism
    • London: Routledge & Kegan Paul
    • G. E. Moore, “The Refutation of Idealism,” reprinted in his Philosophical Studies (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1959).
    • (1959) reprinted in his Philosophical Studies
    • Moore, G.E.1
  • 3
    • 85011449540 scopus 로고
    • Berkeley and His Modern Critics
    • New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston A lone, but very attenuated, exception is perhaps Warren E. Steinkraus who says: “[o]f course, Berkeley regards the distinction as untenable, though in our day we should have wished for more detailed clarification” Below I hope to show that Berkeley provided a fair amount of detail
    • A lone, but very attenuated, exception is perhaps Warren E. Steinkraus who says: “[o]f course, Berkeley regards the distinction as untenable, though in our day we should have wished for more detailed clarification” (Warren E. Steinkraus, ed., “Berkeley and His Modern Critics,” in New Studies in Berkeley's Philosophy [New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1966], p. 162). Below I hope to show that Berkeley provided a fair amount of detail.
    • (1966) New Studies in Berkeley's Philosophy , pp. 162
    • Steinkraus, W.E.1
  • 5
    • 84875353855 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • sec. 22–23
    • Berkeley, Principles, pt.l, sec. 22–23, p. 50
    • Principles , pp. 50
    • Berkeley1
  • 7
    • 0011183539 scopus 로고
    • Berkeley's Master Argument
    • The argument was thus baptized by
    • The argument was thus baptized by André Gallois, “Berkeley's Master Argument,” The Philosophical Review, 83 (1974): 55–57.
    • (1974) The Philosophical Review , vol.83 , pp. 55-57
    • Gallois, A.1
  • 8
    • 0003583822 scopus 로고
    • esp New York: Cambridge University Press Amidst a rather extensive literature, Ian Hacking's is one of the very few to take the argument at all seriously
    • Amidst a rather extensive literature, Ian Hacking's Why Does Language Matter to Philosophy? (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1975), esp. p. 41, is one of the very few to take the argument at all seriously.
    • (1975) Why Does Language Matter to Philosophy? , pp. 41
  • 9
    • 34248894692 scopus 로고
    • Berkeley and the Ineffable
    • See also 231–50, esp.
    • See also Thomas M. Lennon, “Berkeley and the Ineffable,” Synthese, 75 (1988): 231–50, esp. pp. 231–37.
    • (1988) Synthese , vol.75
    • Lennon, T.M.1
  • 12
    • 84895000311 scopus 로고
    • The Berkeley, Plato, Aristotle Connection
    • For more, see also edited by C. M. Turbayne (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press
    • For more, see also C. M. Turbayne's “The Berkeley, Plato, Aristotle Connection,” in Berkeley: Critical and Interpretive Essays, edited by C. M. Turbayne (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1982), p. 299.
    • (1982) Berkeley: Critical and Interpretive Essays , pp. 299
    • Turbayne's, C.M.1
  • 14
    • 60949144642 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Locke and the Logic of Ideas
    • For more on the genitive analysis of ideas, see
    • For more on the genitive analysis of ideas, see Thomas M. Lennon, “Locke and the Logic of Ideas,” History of Philosophy Quarterly, 18 (2001): 155–77.
    • (2001) History of Philosophy Quarterly , vol.18
    • Lennon, T.M.1
  • 15
    • 83255170384 scopus 로고
    • (1660), translated by Jacques Rieux and Bernard E. Rollin (The Hague: Mouton This is the companion piece to the Port-Royal Logic (1662). The approach taken in this paper follows Berkeley's caution in his notebooks: “of & thing causes of mistake”; “The referring Ideas to things w[hich] are not Ideas, the using the Term, Idea of, is one great cause of mistake” (nos. 115, 660). Given the mistakes he sees deriving from “idea of,” one might ask why Berkeley uses the term at all. As he explains in nos. 685 and 807, it is because the term is already in use. This is not just a terminological point; it is the logic of the term that interests him. He thinks that realists get it wrong and thus go astray
    • Claude Lancelot, The Port-Royal Grammar (1660), translated by Jacques Rieux and Bernard E. Rollin (The Hague: Mouton, 1975). This is the companion piece to the Port-Royal Logic (1662). The approach taken in this paper follows Berkeley's caution in his notebooks: “of & thing causes of mistake”; “The referring Ideas to things w[hich] are not Ideas, the using the Term, Idea of, is one great cause of mistake” (nos. 115, 660). Given the mistakes he sees deriving from “idea of,” one might ask why Berkeley uses the term at all. As he explains in nos. 685 and 807, it is because the term is already in use. This is not just a terminological point; it is the logic of the term that interests him. He thinks that realists get it wrong and thus go astray.
    • (1975) The Port-Royal Grammar
    • Lancelot, C.1
  • 16
    • 0010826342 scopus 로고
    • References for Berkeley's notebooks are to the corrected edition in edited by M. R. Ayers (London: Dent
    • References for Berkeley's notebooks are to the corrected edition in George Berkeley, Philosophical Works, edited by M. R. Ayers (London: Dent, 1975).
    • (1975) Philosophical Works
    • Berkeley, G.1
  • 17
    • 0040727742 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous
    • In his notebooks, Berkeley had already noted the threat to his idealism posed by this distinction: “ ‘Twas the opinion that ideas could exist unperceiv'd or before perception that made Men think perception was somewhat different from the Idea perceived, [tha]t it was an idea of Reflexion whereas the thing perceiv'd was an idea of Sensation. I say ’twas this made ‘em think the understanding took it in receiv'd it from without w[hi]ch could never be did not they think it existed without” (no. 658). If there are, as Locke maintained, ideas both of reflection (i.e., ideas of acts of perception) and ideas of sensation (perceptions conveyed into the mind) the ideata of the latter can only be mind-independent
    • Berkeley, Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous, in The Works of George Berkeley, Vol. 2, p. 194. In his notebooks, Berkeley had already noted the threat to his idealism posed by this distinction: “ ‘Twas the opinion that ideas could exist unperceiv'd or before perception that made Men think perception was somewhat different from the Idea perceived, [tha]t it was an idea of Reflexion whereas the thing perceiv'd was an idea of Sensation. I say ’twas this made ‘em think the understanding took it in receiv'd it from without w[hi]ch could never be did not they think it existed without” (no. 658). If there are, as Locke maintained, ideas both of reflection (i.e., ideas of acts of perception) and ideas of sensation (perceptions conveyed into the mind) the ideata of the latter can only be mind-independent.
    • The Works of George Berkeley , vol.2 , pp. 194
    • Berkeley1
  • 20
    • 60949412264 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing
    • Robert G. Muehlmann, Berkeley's Ontology (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing, 1992), p. 196.
    • (1992) Berkeley's Ontology , pp. 196
    • Muehlmann, R.G.1
  • 22
    • 60949412264 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thus the importance of arguments from perceptual relativity, which seem therefore to have the positive role generally accorded them by the literature. On the other hand, if it is to be passive the mind cannot make a causal difference. But it can make an ontological difference, it would seem, only in the case of perceived qualities that are tied to hedonic qualities (see chap. 5
    • Thus the importance of arguments from perceptual relativity, which seem therefore to have the positive role generally accorded them by the literature. On the other hand, if it is to be passive the mind cannot make a causal difference. But it can make an ontological difference, it would seem, only in the case of perceived qualities that are tied to hedonic qualities (see Muehlmann, Berkeley's Ontology, chap. 5).
    • Berkeley's Ontology
    • Muehlmann1
  • 23
    • 85011460154 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also Berkeley's Philosophical Commentaries, nos. 810–11 (in “Pure Intellect I understand not.” “Locke is in [th]e right in those things wherein he differs from [th]e Cartesians.”
    • See also Berkeley's Philosophical Commentaries, nos. 810–11 (in The Works of George Berkeley, Vol. 1, p. 97): “Pure Intellect I understand not.” “Locke is in [th]e right in those things wherein he differs from [th]e Cartesians.”
    • The Works of George Berkeley , vol.1 , pp. 97
  • 24
    • 84879965266 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Berkeley sometimes suggests that the mind is active in perception, for example, at and especially at p. 139: “a soul or spirit is an active being whose existence consists, not in being perceived, but in perceiving ideas and thinking” (in The Works of George Berkeley, Vol. 2, p. 105). But in none of these texts does he say that the mind's activity consists in its perceiving rather than entirely in willing. Moreover, especially in the more problematic texts, his concern is to distinguish the mind from its ideas, which he does in terms of the activity of the former and the passivity of the latter. Once it is acknowledged that perceiving and being perceived are the same occurrence, it is clear that the mind is passive with respect to it. It is God who is active
    • Berkeley sometimes suggests that the mind is active in perception, for example, at Principles, pt. 2, p. 27, and especially at p. 139: “a soul or spirit is an active being whose existence consists, not in being perceived, but in perceiving ideas and thinking” (in The Works of George Berkeley, Vol. 2, p. 105). But in none of these texts does he say that the mind's activity consists in its perceiving rather than entirely in willing. Moreover, especially in the more problematic texts, his concern is to distinguish the mind from its ideas, which he does in terms of the activity of the former and the passivity of the latter. Once it is acknowledged that perceiving and being perceived are the same occurrence, it is clear that the mind is passive with respect to it. It is God who is active.
    • Principles , pp. 27
  • 25
    • 84909016960 scopus 로고
    • Berkeley and Descartes: Reflections on the Theory of Ideas
    • edited by P. K. Machamer and R. G. Turnbull (Columbus: Ohio State University Press
    • Wilfrid Sellars, “Berkeley and Descartes: Reflections on the Theory of Ideas,” in Studies in Perception, edited by P. K. Machamer and R. G. Turnbull (Columbus: Ohio State University Press, 1978), p. 289.
    • (1978) Studies in Perception , pp. 289
    • Sellars, W.1
  • 26
    • 84954000285 scopus 로고
    • Berkeley and Cartesianism
    • Essays on Rationalism and Empiricism Suppl. 165–76, esp.
    • Daisie Radner, “Berkeley and Cartesianism,” The Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Suppl. Vol. 4: Essays on Rationalism and Empiricism (1978): 165–76, esp. p. 167.
    • (1978) The Canadian Journal of Philosophy , vol.4 , pp. 167
    • Radner, D.1
  • 27
    • 79956902896 scopus 로고
    • Minds and Ideas in Berkeley
    • 198–207, esp
    • George Pitcher, “Minds and Ideas in Berkeley,” American Philosophical Quarterly, 6 (1969): 198–207, esp. p. 200.
    • (1969) American Philosophical Quarterly , vol.6 , pp. 200
    • Pitcher, G.1
  • 29
    • 85011459489 scopus 로고
    • See London: Methuen
    • See I. C. Tipton, Berkeley (London: Methuen, 1974), pp. 15–16.
    • (1974) , pp. 15-16
    • Tipton, I.C.1    Berkeley2
  • 30
    • 85011460086 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The dance tune had in fact come to Berkeley from Hobbes. See “Hobbs in some degree falls in w[i]th Locke saying thought is to the Mind or him self as dancing to the Dancer.” The example is a bit misleading in that the waltz is not an immediate object of perception, which, as Berkeley repeatedly insists, is the only topic of the first dialogue. With its institutional, dispositional character, a waltz is more like Berkeley's constructed physical object. In fact, Hobbes had used the image of jumping, which was to be taken up by G. F. Stout in the twentieth century
    • The dance tune had in fact come to Berkeley from Hobbes. See Philosophical Commentaries, no. 796: “Hobbs in some degree falls in w[i]th Locke saying thought is to the Mind or him self as dancing to the Dancer.” The example is a bit misleading in that the waltz is not an immediate object of perception, which, as Berkeley repeatedly insists, is the only topic of the first dialogue. With its institutional, dispositional character, a waltz is more like Berkeley's constructed physical object. In fact, Hobbes had used the image of jumping, which was to be taken up by G. F. Stout in the twentieth century.
    • Philosophical Commentaries , Issue.796
  • 31
    • 85011456014 scopus 로고
    • See translated by J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, and D. Murdoch (New York: Cambridge University Press
    • See Descartes, The Philosophical Writings, translated by J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, and D. Murdoch (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1984), Vol. 2, p. 125.
    • (1984) The Philosophical Writings , vol.2 , pp. 125
    • Descartes1
  • 32
    • 85011491284 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hobbes's objections are not the only ones of interest here. In the first set, concerning ideas and their causes, Caterus and Descartes employ a distinction between intrinsic and extrinsic denominations that exactly parallels the internal-external accusative distinction 74–75 [which, unfortunately, translates in terms of “extraneous labels”])
    • Hobbes's objections are not the only ones of interest here. In the first set, concerning ideas and their causes, Caterus and Descartes employ a distinction between intrinsic and extrinsic denominations that exactly parallels the internal-external accusative distinction (Descartes, The Philosophical Writings, pp. 66–67, 74–75 [which, unfortunately, translates in terms of “extraneous labels”]).
    • The Philosophical Writings , pp. 66-67
    • Descartes1
  • 36
    • 0003851654 scopus 로고
    • translated by Norman Kemp Smith (London: Macmillan 88–90
    • Emanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, translated by Norman Kemp Smith (London: Macmillan, 1963), pp. 72, 88–90.
    • (1963) Critique of Pure Reason , pp. 72
    • Kant, E.1
  • 38
    • 0003939914 scopus 로고
    • Indianapolis: Hackett Notably, for one who has little use for history, Goodman credits Berkeley, among others (including Kant), for the “overwhelming case against perception without conception, the pure given, absolute immediacy, the innocent eye, substance as substratum” (p. 6)
    • Nelson Goodman, Ways of Worldmaking (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1978), pp. 3–4. Notably, for one who has little use for history, Goodman credits Berkeley, among others (including Kant), for the “overwhelming case against perception without conception, the pure given, absolute immediacy, the innocent eye, substance as substratum” (p. 6).
    • (1978) Ways of Worldmaking , pp. 3-4
    • Goodman, N.1
  • 40
    • 61249504157 scopus 로고
    • Substance, Reality, and Primary Qualities
    • Jonathan Bennett, “Substance, Reality, and Primary Qualities,” American Philosophical Quarterly, 2 (1965): 1–17
    • (1965) American Philosophical Quarterly , vol.2 , pp. 1-17
    • Bennett, J.1
  • 42
    • 0039916353 scopus 로고
    • Garden City, NY: Doubleday If Locke has an implicit ontology of predication, it would be the class-inclusion account made explicit in Berkeley
    • M. J. Loux, Universal and Particulars: Readings in Ontology (Garden City, NY: Doubleday, 1970), pp. 7–8. If Locke has an implicit ontology of predication, it would be the class-inclusion account made explicit in Berkeley.
    • (1970) Universal and Particulars: Readings in Ontology , pp. 7-8
    • Loux, M.J.1
  • 44
    • 85011490132 scopus 로고
    • Ideas, Minds, and Berkeley
    • This interpretation began in the 1950s with papers by R. Van Iten and W. H. Hay on the role of universals for Berkeley. It was first formulated by E. B. Allaire and subsequently received considerable debate. For criticism of it, see 181–94, esp.
    • This interpretation began in the 1950s with papers by R. Van Iten and W. H. Hay on the role of universals for Berkeley. It was first formulated by E. B. Allaire and subsequently received considerable debate. For criticism of it, see George Pappas, “Ideas, Minds, and Berkeley,” American Philosophical Quarterly, 17 (1980): 181–94, esp. pp. 188–90.
    • (1980) American Philosophical Quarterly , vol.17
    • Pappas, G.1
  • 45
    • 84928420241 scopus 로고
    • Adhering to Inherence: A New Look at the Old Steps that Led to Berkeley's Idealism
    • For defense of it, see
    • For defense of it, see Alan M. Hausman, “Adhering to Inherence: A New Look at the Old Steps that Led to Berkeley's Idealism,” The Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 14 (1984): 421–43.
    • (1984) The Canadian Journal of Philosophy , vol.14
    • Hausman, A.M.1
  • 46
    • 0042610235 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But cf. Toronto: University of Toronto Press
    • But cf. David Hausman and Alan Hausman, Descartes's Legacy (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1997), p. 116.
    • (1997) Descartes's Legacy , pp. 116
    • Hausman, D.1    Hausman, A.2
  • 48
    • 79958135498 scopus 로고
    • Some Problems of Substance among the Cartesians
    • H. M. Bracken has shown that the Cartesians, at least, had already invoked an account of the connection between substance and mode other than that of inherence in
    • H. M. Bracken has shown that the Cartesians, at least, had already invoked an account of the connection between substance and mode other than that of inherence in “Some Problems of Substance among the Cartesians,” American Philosophical Quarterly, 1 (1964): 129–37.
    • (1964) American Philosophical Quarterly , vol.1
  • 49
    • 60949412264 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Although he calls ideas acts, Muehlmann at one point gets this exactly right. “Berkeley describes perception of the proper objects [e.g., colour] as a ”bare reception.’ He would urge, accordingly, that it is more perspicuous to say of these proper objects that they are had (rather in the way that we have such “objects' as pains and pleasures) than to say that they are immediate perceivings distinct from, but directed at, these proper objects”
    • Although he calls ideas acts, Muehlmann at one point gets this exactly right. “Berkeley describes perception of the proper objects [e.g., colour] as a ”bare reception.’ He would urge, accordingly, that it is more perspicuous to say of these proper objects that they are had (rather in the way that we have such “objects' as pains and pleasures) than to say that they are immediate perceivings distinct from, but directed at, these proper objects” (Muehlmann, Berkeley's Ontology, p. 202).
    • Berkeley's Ontology , pp. 202
    • Muehlmann1
  • 50
    • 22544484390 scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press Winkler provides enormous textual support to show that ideas are immediate objects of perception in his What these texts show, it seems to me, is that each idea taken “singly,” as Hylas puts it just before he is given the Master Argument, is not an object in the sense explicated by the congeries analysis. On the other hand, if Winkler is right, then of course the defense here of Berkeley against Moore is in trouble
    • Kenneth P. Winkler provides enormous textual support to show that ideas are immediate objects of perception in his Berkeley: An Interpretation (New York: Oxford University Press, 1989), pp. 3–10. What these texts show, it seems to me, is that each idea taken “singly,” as Hylas puts it just before he is given the Master Argument, is not an object in the sense explicated by the congeries analysis. On the other hand, if Winkler is right, then of course the defense here of Berkeley against Moore is in trouble.
    • (1989) Berkeley: An Interpretation , pp. 3-10
    • Kenneth, P.1
  • 52
    • 85011530300 scopus 로고
    • 567–73, esp As M. R. Ayers puts it, once Berkeley has rejected the mind-independent thing-and with it the Cartesian distinction between esse formate and esse obiectiva—he must “puff up the idea (i.e., the intentional object, the thing as it exists in the mind) as something in its own right” and n.10). On the reading above, the idea, although taking a subjective genitive, ceases thereby to be a mere appearance
    • As M. R. Ayers puts it, once Berkeley has rejected the mind-independent thing-and with it the Cartesian distinction between esse formate and esse obiectiva—he must “puff up the idea (i.e., the intentional object, the thing as it exists in the mind) as something in its own right” (History of European Ideas, 7 (1986): 567–73, esp. pp. 569–70 and n.10). On the reading above, the idea, although taking a subjective genitive, ceases thereby to be a mere appearance.
    • (1986) History of European Ideas , vol.7


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.