메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 7, Issue 1, 2001, Pages 59-81

Necessity and restitution

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 85011500105     PISSN: 13523252     EISSN: 14698048     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/s1352325201071038     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (8)

References (43)
  • 2
    • 85022388322 scopus 로고
    • 39 HARV. L. REV. 307. The language of incomplete privilege was picked up by both the Restatement of Restitution (§ 122) and the Restatement of Torts (comment to subsection (2) of § 197). § 197 of the Restatement of Torts states both sides of the incomplete privilege. § 122 of the Restatement of Restitution concerns the duty of the trespasser to compensate the property owner for damage to her property.
    • Francis Bohlen, Incomplete Privilege to Inflict Intentional Invasions of Interest of Property and Personality, 39 HARV. L. REV. 307 (1926). The language of incomplete privilege was picked up by both the Restatement of Restitution (§ 122) and the Restatement of Torts (comment to subsection (2) of § 197). § 197 of the Restatement of Torts states both sides of the incomplete privilege. § 122 of the Restatement of Restitution concerns the duty of the trespasser to compensate the property owner for damage to her property.
    • (1926) Incomplete Privilege to Inflict Intentional Invasions of Interest of Property and Personality
    • Bohlen, F.1
  • 3
    • 85022359485 scopus 로고
    • Montague argues that it follows from the fact that the imperilled trespasser does no wrong that no compensation is owed the property owner. See Phillip Montague, Rights and Duties of Compensation, 13 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 374 (1984), and Davis and Western on Rights and Compensation, 14 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 390
    • The noteworthy exception is Phillip Montague. Montague argues that it follows from the fact that the imperilled trespasser does no wrong that no compensation is owed the property owner. See Phillip Montague, Rights and Duties of Compensation, 13 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 374 (1984), and Davis and Western on Rights and Compensation, 14 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 390 (1985).
    • (1985) The noteworthy exception is Phillip Montague.
  • 8
    • 85022442997 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • RISKS AND WRONGS note 6; Daniel Friedmann, 80 COLUM. L.REV. 514 (1970); John P. Finan & John Ritson, Tortious Necessity: The Privileged Defence, 26 AKRON L. REV. 1 (1992); Ernest J. Weinrib, THE IDEA OF PRIVATE LAW 196-203 (1995). While he casts his account in different terms, Arthur Ripstein suggests that it is equivalent to the restitutionary analysis. Arthur Ripstein, EQUALITY, RESPONSIBILITY, AND THE LAW 122. Writing about the English law of tort, W.V.H. Rogers suggests that while liability in necessity cases cannot be founded on tort, it is an open question whether a claim could be made out in restitution. WINFIELD AND JOLOWICZ ON TORT 880 (15th ed. 1998).
    • Robert Keeton, RISKS AND WRONGS note 6; Daniel Friedmann, Restitution of Benefits Obtained through the Appropriation of Property or the Commission of aWrong, 80 COLUM. L.REV. 514 (1970); John P. Finan & John Ritson, Tortious Necessity: The Privileged Defence, 26 AKRON L. REV. 1 (1992); Ernest J. Weinrib, THE IDEA OF PRIVATE LAW 196-203 (1995). While he casts his account in different terms, Arthur Ripstein suggests that it is equivalent to the restitutionary analysis. Arthur Ripstein, EQUALITY, RESPONSIBILITY, AND THE LAW 122 (1999). Writing about the English law of tort, W.V.H. Rogers suggests that while liability in necessity cases cannot be founded on tort, it is an open question whether a claim could be made out in restitution. WINFIELD AND JOLOWICZ ON TORT 880 (15th ed. 1998).
    • (1999) Restitution of Benefits Obtained through the Appropriation of Property or the Commission of aWrong
    • Keeton, R.1
  • 10
    • 84862543690 scopus 로고
    • 71 A. 188 (Vt. Sup. Ct. )
    • Ploof v. Putnam, 71 A. 188 (Vt. Sup. Ct. 1908)
    • (1908) Ploof v. Putnam
  • 11
    • 85022451551 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (See, the Restatement of Torts § 197, comment (c); Weinrib, Ploof v. Putnam note 10, at 196, 201-02.) Its not clear what this adds, practically speaking, if the quantum of damages in either case is measured by the damage inflicted. But there is an important conceptual point here: In the case in which the value of the property saved is less than the damage caused, perhaps damages are compensation for tortious wrongdoing, that is, for trespass and possibly conversion. I will set this aside here, however. My concern is with whether the restitutionary account can explain Vincent and similar cases, in which this proportionality condition is easily satisfied, and so the claim to the right of necessity is uncontroversially made out.
    • It is often held that the right extends only to circumstances in which the value of the property saved exceeds that of the damage inflicted. (See, the Restatement of Torts § 197, comment (c); Weinrib, Ploof v. Putnam note 10, at 196, 201-02.) Its not clear what this adds, practically speaking, if the quantum of damages in either case is measured by the damage inflicted. But there is an important conceptual point here: In the case in which the value of the property saved is less than the damage caused, perhaps damages are compensation for tortious wrongdoing, that is, for trespass and possibly conversion. I will set this aside here, however. My concern is with whether the restitutionary account can explain Vincent and similar cases, in which this proportionality condition is easily satisfied, and so the claim to the right of necessity is uncontroversially made out.
    • It is often held that the right extends only to circumstances in which the value of the property saved exceeds that of the damage inflicted.
  • 13
    • 85022373789 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Birks calls the cause of action in cases like A v. B and the cause of action in cases like C v. D “unjust enrichment by a wrong.” Id. at
    • Birks calls the cause of action in cases like A v. B “unjust enrichment by subtraction,” and the cause of action in cases like C v. D “unjust enrichment by a wrong.” Id. at 25-6.
    • unjust enrichment by subtraction , pp. 25-26
  • 15
    • 85022395545 scopus 로고
    • (It is also the feature that newcomers to the law of restitution find the hardest to accept. My students invariably think that A's money should stay with B, as a kind of private incompetence tax.) The distinctive and autonomous nature of restitution is well illustrated by the fact that in limited circumstances restitution is available to parties in default on a contract. See George E. Palmer, THE LAW OF RESTITUTION, ch. 5
    • It is this feature that separates restitution most clearly from other areas of private law. (It is also the feature that newcomers to the law of restitution find the hardest to accept. My students invariably think that A's money should stay with B, as a kind of private incompetence tax.) The distinctive and autonomous nature of restitution is well illustrated by the fact that in limited circumstances restitution is available to parties in default on a contract. See George E. Palmer, THE LAW OF RESTITUTION vol. 1, ch. 5 (1978).
    • (1978) It is this feature that separates restitution most clearly from other areas of private law. , vol.1
  • 16
    • 66049084904 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is this feature that separates restitution most clearly from other areas of private law. note 17, III.1 (on the distinction between voluntary and involuntary action), V.4 (on the role of this distinction in corrective justice).
    • Aristotle, It is this feature that separates restitution most clearly from other areas of private law. note 17, III.1 (on the distinction between voluntary and involuntary action), V.4 (on the role of this distinction in corrective justice).
    • Aristotle
  • 17
    • 85022389967 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (c) to § 1.
    • Comment (c) to § 1.
    • Comment
  • 18
    • 85022419258 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Comment note 10, at
    • Finan & Ritson, Comment note 10, at 7.
    • Finan & Ritson , pp. 7
  • 19
    • 85022403896 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 124 N.W. at
    • Vincent, 124 N.W. at 221.
    • Vincent , pp. 221
  • 21
    • 85022392741 scopus 로고
    • On which, see Guido Calabresi & A. Douglas Melamed, Property Rules, 85 HARV. L. REV. 1089 (1972); Jules Coleman & Jody Kraus, Rethinking the Theory of Legal Rights, 95 YALE L. J. 1335
    • On which, see Guido Calabresi & A. Douglas Melamed, Property Rules, Liability Rules and Inalienability: One View of the Cathedral, 85 HARV. L. REV. 1089 (1972); Jules Coleman & Jody Kraus, Rethinking the Theory of Legal Rights, 95 YALE L. J. 1335 (1986).
    • (1986) Liability Rules and Inalienability: One View of the Cathedral
  • 22
    • 85022417500 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Liability Rules and Inalienability: One View of the Cathedral note
    • Coleman & Kraus, Liability Rules and Inalienability: One View of the Cathedral note 33.
    • Coleman & Kraus , pp. 33
  • 24
    • 85022352933 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The locus classicus is A.M. Honoré, Ownership, in OXFORD ESSAYS IN JURISPRUDENCE (A.G. Guest ed., 1961). in Some Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial Reasoning, 23 YALE L. J. 16 (1913). For a recent review of the literature and issues surrounding this idea, see J.E. Penner, The “Bundle of Rights” Picture of Property, 43 UCLA L. REV. 711
    • The locus classicus is A.M. Honoré, Ownership, in OXFORD ESSAYS IN JURISPRUDENCE (A.G. Guest ed., 1961). The “bundle of rights” theory of property is often characterized as a conjunction of Honoré's analysis of the incidents of property in this paper and Wesley Hohfeld's analysis of the concept of “right” in Some Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial Reasoning, 23 YALE L. J. 16 (1913). For a recent review of the literature and issues surrounding this idea, see J.E. Penner, The “Bundle of Rights” Picture of Property, 43 UCLA L. REV. 711 (1996).
    • (1996) The “bundle of rights” theory of property is often characterized as a conjunction of Honoré's analysis of the incidents of property in this paper and Wesley Hohfeld's analysis of the concept of “right”
  • 26
    • 85022366255 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Omissions are noncontroversially causes here. The majority in Vincent made much of the fact that the crew replaced the lines that held the Reynolds moored, and so did something. But, as Lewis J. argued in dissent, this is inconsistent with the majority's own analysis. The majority rejected the idea that the captain of the Reynolds was at fault for failing to anticipate the severity of the storm and so for failing to seek a place of safety earlier. But then he could not have been at fault for not using stronger cables in the first place. Thus the actions of the crew in replacing the lines can not have the legal significance assigned to them in the majority opinion. Vincent, 124 N.W. at
    • But not on a third, that “remaining moored at the dock” is not an action. Omissions are noncontroversially causes here. The majority in Vincent made much of the fact that the crew replaced the lines that held the Reynolds moored, and so did something. But, as Lewis J. argued in dissent, this is inconsistent with the majority's own analysis. The majority rejected the idea that the captain of the Reynolds was at fault for failing to anticipate the severity of the storm and so for failing to seek a place of safety earlier. But then he could not have been at fault for not using stronger cables in the first place. Thus the actions of the crew in replacing the lines can not have the legal significance assigned to them in the majority opinion. Vincent, 124 N.W. at 222.
    • But not on a third, that “remaining moored at the dock” is not an action. , pp. 222
  • 27
    • 85022429849 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But not on a third, that “remaining moored at the dock” is not an action. note 10, at
    • See Finan & Ritson, But not on a third, that “remaining moored at the dock” is not an action. note 10, at 6.
    • Finan & Ritson , pp. 6
  • 30
    • 85022373431 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Finan and Ritson support this idea, Palmer argues that even though it is not explicit on this point, the Restitution would support restitution in both Vincent and Vincent II, in each case measured by the damage inflicted on the plaintiff. note 10, at 7, n.20. Keeton, Palmer argues that even though it is not explicit on this point, the Restitution would support restitution in both Vincent and Vincent II, in each case measured by the damage inflicted on the plaintiff. note 6, at 411, argues that this is the only way to make sense of Vincent as a restitutionary case. See comment (e) to § 1.
    • Finan and Ritson support this idea, Palmer argues that even though it is not explicit on this point, the Restitution would support restitution in both Vincent and Vincent II, in each case measured by the damage inflicted on the plaintiff. note 10, at 7, n.20. Keeton, Palmer argues that even though it is not explicit on this point, the Restitution would support restitution in both Vincent and Vincent II, in each case measured by the damage inflicted on the plaintiff. note 6, at 411, argues that this is the only way to make sense of Vincent as a restitutionary case. The drafters of the Restatement were hesitant to accept the decreased chance of injury as an enrichment-or so much is implied by their characterization of a physician's failed attempt to save someone's life as a case in which the patient was not enriched. See comment (e) to § 1.
    • The drafters of the Restatement were hesitant to accept the decreased chance of injury as an enrichment-or so much is implied by their characterization of a physician's failed attempt to save someone's life as a case in which the patient was not enriched.
  • 34
    • 85022362644 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It cannot be the former, because then the domain of private law would extend to human and natural accidents. So it must be the latter. Id. at 283-84; Weinrib, The Gains and Losses of Corrective Justice note 10, at
    • Correlatively properly understood entails that the link must be either between material gains and losses or between normative gains and losses. It cannot be the former, because then the domain of private law would extend to human and natural accidents. So it must be the latter. Id. at 283-84; Weinrib, The Gains and Losses of Corrective Justice note 10, at 116-17.
    • Correlatively properly understood entails that the link must be either between material gains and losses or between normative gains and losses. , pp. 116-117
  • 39
    • 85022432551 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 81 CORNELL L. R. 698, 732-33 (1996); Peter Cane, Corrective Justice and Correlativity in Private Law, 16 OXFORD J. LEGAL STUD.
    • See Kenneth W. Simons, Justification in Private Law, 81 CORNELL L. R. 698, 732-33 (1996); Peter Cane, Corrective Justice and Correlativity in Private Law, 16 OXFORD J. LEGAL STUD. 471, 486-87 (1996).
    • (1996) Justification in Private Law , vol.471 , pp. 486-487
    • Simons, K.W.1
  • 42
    • 85022397032 scopus 로고
    • The plaintiff's right to restitutio in integrum in the context of an account that identifies the locus of liability with the wrong seems to require erasing all the effects of the wrong. But as Jules Coleman argues, this leads to a kind of remedial indeterminacy. Suppose, he suggests, on the way to the airport my taxi driver negligently gets into an accident. I miss my plane. It turns out that the plane crashes and everyone on board dies. Erasing all of the effects of the negligence seems to require my death. (Thus, Coleman suggests, “harm” must be somehow built into the definition of corrective justice.) Coleman, Moments of Carelessness and Massive Loss note 8, at 322-24; Jules Coleman, The Mixed Conception of Corrective Justice, 77 IOWA L. REV.
    • There are other difficulties here. The plaintiff's right to restitutio in integrum in the context of an account that identifies the locus of liability with the wrong seems to require erasing all the effects of the wrong. But as Jules Coleman argues, this leads to a kind of remedial indeterminacy. Suppose, he suggests, on the way to the airport my taxi driver negligently gets into an accident. I miss my plane. It turns out that the plane crashes and everyone on board dies. Erasing all of the effects of the negligence seems to require my death. (Thus, Coleman suggests, “harm” must be somehow built into the definition of corrective justice.) Coleman, Moments of Carelessness and Massive Loss note 8, at 322-24; Jules Coleman, The Mixed Conception of Corrective Justice, 77 IOWA L. REV. 427, 441 (1992).
    • (1992) There are other difficulties here. , vol.427 , pp. 441


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.