메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 15, Issue 1, 2002, Pages 53-68

Sense and Quasisense of Schmitt's Großraum Theory in International Law – A Rejoinder to Carty's “Carl Schmitt's Critique of Liberal International Legal Order”

Author keywords

Carty; Gro raum; Nazi ideology; neoliberalism; Schmitt

Indexed keywords


EID: 85011465092     PISSN: 09221565     EISSN: 14789698     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S092215650200002X     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (9)

References (53)
  • 1
    • 84882121394 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 32 Harv. Int'l L. J. 397 (1991); N. Mac Cormick, Beyond the Sovereign State, 56 MLR 1 (1993); C. Schreuer, The Waning of the Sovereign State, 4 EJIL 447 (1993); O. Schachter, The Decline of the Nation-State and Its Implications for International Law, 36 Colum. J. Transnat'l L. 7 (1997); A. Hurrell & N. Woods, Globalization and Inequality, 24 Millennium 447 (1995); B. Kinsbury, Sovereignty and Inequality, 9 EJIL
    • Cf. M. Koskenniemi, The Future of Statehood, 32 Harv. Int'l L. J. 397 (1991); N. Mac Cormick, Beyond the Sovereign State, 56 MLR 1 (1993); C. Schreuer, The Waning of the Sovereign State, 4 EJIL 447 (1993); O. Schachter, The Decline of the Nation-State and Its Implications for International Law, 36 Colum. J. Transnat'l L. 7 (1997); A. Hurrell & N. Woods, Globalization and Inequality, 24 Millennium 447 (1995); B. Kinsbury, Sovereignty and Inequality, 9 EJIL 599 (1998).
    • (1998) The Future of Statehood , pp. 599
    • Koskenniemi, M.1
  • 4
    • 85011506698 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • sociological and legal perspectives see A. Paulus, Die internationale Gemeinschaft im Völkerrecht 97 et seq. (Munich, ).
    • For an excellent survey of current debate on globalization from political, sociological and legal perspectives see A. Paulus, Die internationale Gemeinschaft im Völkerrecht 97 et seq. (Munich, 2001).
    • (2001) For an excellent survey of current debate on globalization from political
  • 5
    • 85011506691 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • L'occidentalisation du monde (Paris, 1989); S. Sur, The State between Fragmentation and Globalization, 8 EJIL
    • Cf. S. Latouche, L'occidentalisation du monde (Paris, 1989); S. Sur, The State between Fragmentation and Globalization, 8 EJIL 421 (1997).
    • (1997) , pp. 421
    • Latouche, S.1
  • 8
    • 85011433515 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • She acknowledges that the division between liberal and non-liberal states “is likely to recall the 19th century distinctions between ‘civilized’ and ‘uncivilized’ States,” but limits herself to observe that “exclusionary norms are unlikely to be effective” in regulating the relationships between the two worlds (Slaughter, id., at 506). Anyway, given the demonization of the non-liberal states, it is quite obvious that the relations between liberal and non-liberal states would be reduced to a minimum and would be hostile. This outcome is implied in the author's thoughts on the “liberal peace” that would characterize the relations between liberal states, unlike their relations to non-liberal states (id., at 509), and in the further reflection that the new liberal concept of sovereignty “would exist side by side with more traditional conceptions, which are still accurate and important in relations between liberal and non-liberal States.” In clear text, the sovereignty of non-liberal states is “subject to violation primarily by coercive intervention” by other states or by international institutions (id., at 536, n. 68). Simpson, International Law in a World of Liberal States note 6, at 562 counts Slaughter among the “mild antipluralists,” in contrast to F.R. Teson and M. Reisman whom he considers “strong antipluralists,” because he finds that “the question of outlawry is not exercised much by Slaughter.” I am rather inclined to think that Slaughter's vagueness on this central point was intended.
    • Actually Slaughter still owes us an explanation on how she sees the relations between the world of liberal states and the non-liberal ones. She acknowledges that the division between liberal and non-liberal states “is likely to recall the 19th century distinctions between ‘civilized’ and ‘uncivilized’ States,” but limits herself to observe that “exclusionary norms are unlikely to be effective” in regulating the relationships between the two worlds (Slaughter, id., at 506). Anyway, given the demonization of the non-liberal states, it is quite obvious that the relations between liberal and non-liberal states would be reduced to a minimum and would be hostile. This outcome is implied in the author's thoughts on the “liberal peace” that would characterize the relations between liberal states, unlike their relations to non-liberal states (id., at 509), and in the further reflection that the new liberal concept of sovereignty “would exist side by side with more traditional conceptions, which are still accurate and important in relations between liberal and non-liberal States.” In clear text, the sovereignty of non-liberal states is “subject to violation primarily by coercive intervention” by other states or by international institutions (id., at 536, n. 68). Simpson, International Law in a World of Liberal States note 6, at 562 counts Slaughter among the “mild antipluralists,” in contrast to F.R. Teson and M. Reisman whom he considers “strong antipluralists,” because he finds that “the question of outlawry is not exercised much by Slaughter.” I am rather inclined to think that Slaughter's vagueness on this central point was intended.
    • Actually Slaughter still owes us an explanation on how she sees the relations between the world of liberal states and the non-liberal ones.
  • 9
    • 1842832516 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 8 EJIL 435, at 441 (1997). For more criticisms on Slaughter's premises and thesis see S. Marks, “The End of History”. Reflections on Some International Legal Thesis, 8 EJIL 449, at 470-472 ; M. Koskenniemi, Carl Schmitt, Hans Morgenthau, and the Image of Law in International Relations, in M. Byers (Ed.), The Role of Law in International Politics 17 (Oxford, 2000); J.E. Alvarez, Do Liberal States Behave Better? A Critique of Slaughter's Liberal Theory, 12 EJIL 183 (2001); Paulus, Actually Slaughter still owes us an explanation on how she sees the relations between the world of liberal states and the non-liberal ones. note 4, at 205 et seq.
    • Cf. P. Alston, The Myopia of the Handmaidens: International Lawyers and Globalization, 8 EJIL 435, at 441 (1997). For more criticisms on Slaughter's premises and thesis see S. Marks, “The End of History”. Reflections on Some International Legal Thesis, 8 EJIL 449, at 470-472 (1997); M. Koskenniemi, Carl Schmitt, Hans Morgenthau, and the Image of Law in International Relations, in M. Byers (Ed.), The Role of Law in International Politics 17 (Oxford, 2000); J.E. Alvarez, Do Liberal States Behave Better? A Critique of Slaughter's Liberal Theory, 12 EJIL 183 (2001); Paulus, Actually Slaughter still owes us an explanation on how she sees the relations between the world of liberal states and the non-liberal ones. note 4, at 205 et seq.
    • (1997) The Myopia of the Handmaidens: International Lawyers and Globalization
    • Alston, P.1
  • 10
    • 85011433503 scopus 로고
    • 14 LJIL 25 (2001) (hereinafter ‘Carl Schmitt's Critique'). Actually, this does not come as a surprise. In his well known critique of theories on international law, Carty had proposed an “ethnical” view, based on the priority of nations in their historical reality over every possible system of international law, A. Carty, Critical International Law: Recent Trends in the Theory of International Law, 2 EJIL 66, at 93 (hereinafter ‘Critical International Law'). International law norms are seen as islands in an ocean of lacunae, as concretions formed by the accidental correspondence of the “cultural presuppositions” of different ethnics. It follows that an international discourse could only ever be possible between culturally homogeneous ethnics. Undoubtedly one feels reminded here of concepts similar to the “Artverwandheit” cherished by the Nazis.
    • A. Carty, Carl Schmitt's Critique of Liberal International Legal Order Between 1933 and 1945, 14 LJIL 25 (2001) (hereinafter ‘Carl Schmitt's Critique'). Actually, this does not come as a surprise. In his well known critique of theories on international law, Carty had proposed an “ethnical” view, based on the priority of nations in their historical reality over every possible system of international law, A. Carty, Critical International Law: Recent Trends in the Theory of International Law, 2 EJIL 66, at 93 (1991) (hereinafter ‘Critical International Law'). International law norms are seen as islands in an ocean of lacunae, as concretions formed by the accidental correspondence of the “cultural presuppositions” of different ethnics. It follows that an international discourse could only ever be possible between culturally homogeneous ethnics. Undoubtedly one feels reminded here of concepts similar to the “Artverwandheit” cherished by the Nazis.
    • (1991) Carl Schmitt's Critique of Liberal International Legal Order Between 1933 and 1945
    • Carty, A.1
  • 12
    • 85011458729 scopus 로고
    • Id., at 29. see A. Carty, Alfred Verdross and Othmar Spann: German Romantic Nationalism, National Socialism and International Law, 6 EJIL 78. Carty's attempt to establish a nexus between Verdross's international law theory and Nazi Weltanschauung, starting from Verdross's early sympathy for pangerman nationalistic political parties, is beside the point. “Verdross's catholic universalism and National Socialism are simply irreconcilable,” as is concisely and perfectly rightly put by Paulus, Carl Schmitt's Critique note 4, at
    • Id., at 29. The outburst of sympathy is even more disturbing, if one recalls that some years ago it was Carty, who meticulously and critically hunted out every slightest trace of Verdross's association with National Socialism in the thirties, see A. Carty, Alfred Verdross and Othmar Spann: German Romantic Nationalism, National Socialism and International Law, 6 EJIL 78 (1995). Carty's attempt to establish a nexus between Verdross's international law theory and Nazi Weltanschauung, starting from Verdross's early sympathy for pangerman nationalistic political parties, is beside the point. “Verdross's catholic universalism and National Socialism are simply irreconcilable,” as is concisely and perfectly rightly put by Paulus, Carl Schmitt's Critique note 4, at 175.
    • (1995) The outburst of sympathy is even more disturbing, if one recalls that some years ago it was Carty, who meticulously and critically hunted out every slightest trace of Verdross's association with National Socialism in the thirties , pp. 175
  • 13
    • 84923529184 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The outburst of sympathy is even more disturbing, if one recalls that some years ago it was Carty, who meticulously and critically hunted out every slightest trace of Verdross's association with National Socialism in the thirties note 10, at 60: Schmitt does offer a reasoned, in the sense of limited, critique of Anglo-American international law ideology that continues to have considerable credibility.
    • Cf. Carty, Carl Schmitt's Critique, The outburst of sympathy is even more disturbing, if one recalls that some years ago it was Carty, who meticulously and critically hunted out every slightest trace of Verdross's association with National Socialism in the thirties note 10, at 60: Schmitt does offer a reasoned, in the sense of limited, critique of Anglo-American international law ideology that continues to have considerable credibility.
    • Carl Schmitt's Critique
    • Carty1
  • 14
    • 0003626244 scopus 로고
    • A typical exponent of this mystification is H. Quaritsch, 2nd Edn., at 121 (Berlin, ), who speaks of “Abschied vom Kampf.”
    • A typical exponent of this mystification is H. Quaritsch, Positionen und Begriffe Carl Schmitts, 2nd Edn., at 121 (Berlin, 1991), who speaks of “Abschied vom Kampf.”
    • (1991) Positionen und Begriffe Carl Schmitts
  • 15
    • 25344445608 scopus 로고
    • at 142 et seq. (Munich, 1988). M. Schmoeckel, Die Grossraumtheorie, at 151, notices a substantial continuity in Schmitt's post war writings on the Groβraum, which for the author should suffice to discharge Schmitt from the reproach of a slavish opportunism. The fact that after the war Schmitt sometimes used the Groβraum concept in a polemic mode to explain the political influence of the US in the western hemisphere (see the examples given by Schmoeckel, Positionen und Begriffe Carl Schmitts, at 80) does not change the truth that it was originally developed in order to provide a theoretical cloak to the Nazis’ expansionistic and aggressive goals.
    • B. Rüthers, Entartetes Recht, at 142 et seq. (Munich, 1988). M. Schmoeckel, Die Grossraumtheorie, at 151 (1994), notices a substantial continuity in Schmitt's post war writings on the Groβraum, which for the author should suffice to discharge Schmitt from the reproach of a slavish opportunism. The fact that after the war Schmitt sometimes used the Groβraum concept in a polemic mode to explain the political influence of the US in the western hemisphere (see the examples given by Schmoeckel, Positionen und Begriffe Carl Schmitts, at 80) does not change the truth that it was originally developed in order to provide a theoretical cloak to the Nazis’ expansionistic and aggressive goals.
    • (1994) Entartetes Recht
    • Rüthers, B.1
  • 17
    • 85011486209 scopus 로고
    • The conclusive speech held by Schmitt is published in Deutsche Juristenzeitung, column 1193 (1936). That Schmitt's anti-Semitism was far from being a transient weakness is proved by his post war writings. In his post war diary one can read entries like the following: “Gerade der assimilierte Jude ist der wahre Feind”; “Denn Juden bleiben immer Juden. Während der Kommunist sich bessern und ändern kann”, cf. E. Freiherr von Medem (Ed.), Glossarium. Aufzeichnungen der Jahre 1947-1951, at 18, 255 (Berlin, 1991). For an appraisal of the Glossarium see R. Mehring, Zu Carl Schmitts Dämonologie, 32 Rechtstheorie 258 (1992). Therefore the affirmations by J.W. Bendersky, Carl Schmitt at Nuremberg, 72 Telos 91, at 95 : “He never succumbed to racism,” and by Schmoeckel, Der Führer schützt das Recht note 15, at 144: “Das Rassendenken hat Schmitt grundsätzlich nicht rezipiert” are totally untenable.
    • On the course and intrigue of this infamous congress strongly wanted by Schmitt see Rüthers, Der Führer schützt das Recht note 15, at 135 et seq. The conclusive speech held by Schmitt is published in Deutsche Juristenzeitung, column 1193 (1936). That Schmitt's anti-Semitism was far from being a transient weakness is proved by his post war writings. In his post war diary one can read entries like the following: “Gerade der assimilierte Jude ist der wahre Feind”; “Denn Juden bleiben immer Juden. Während der Kommunist sich bessern und ändern kann”, cf. E. Freiherr von Medem (Ed.), Glossarium. Aufzeichnungen der Jahre 1947-1951, at 18, 255 (Berlin, 1991). For an appraisal of the Glossarium see R. Mehring, Zu Carl Schmitts Dämonologie, 32 Rechtstheorie 258 (1992). Therefore the affirmations by J.W. Bendersky, Carl Schmitt at Nuremberg, 72 Telos 91, at 95 (1987): “He never succumbed to racism,” and by Schmoeckel, Der Führer schützt das Recht note 15, at 144: “Das Rassendenken hat Schmitt grundsätzlich nicht rezipiert” are totally untenable.
    • (1987) On the course and intrigue of this infamous congress strongly wanted by Schmitt see Rüthers, Der Führer schützt das Recht note 15, at 135 et seq.
  • 20
    • 85011486213 scopus 로고
    • Der Nomos der Erde (Berlin, 1950). According to Quaritsch, Schmitt himself provided a mystifying version of this episode of his life note 14, at 121 the book was already finished by
    • C. Schmitt, Der Nomos der Erde (Berlin, 1950). According to Quaritsch, Schmitt himself provided a mystifying version of this episode of his life note 14, at 121 the book was already finished by 1945.
    • (1945)
    • Schmitt, C.1
  • 21
    • 85011472350 scopus 로고
    • in Quaritsch, Schmitt himself provided a mystifying version of this episode of his life note 14, at 88 et seq. It was the text of a conference held on 29 October 1927 for the ‘Gesellschaft der Freunde und Förderer der Universität Bonn’ and originally published in Hochland, January, at
    • C. Schmitt, Der Völkerbund und Europa, in Quaritsch, Schmitt himself provided a mystifying version of this episode of his life note 14, at 88 et seq. It was the text of a conference held on 29 October 1927 for the ‘Gesellschaft der Freunde und Förderer der Universität Bonn’ and originally published in Hochland, January 1928, at 345.
    • (1928) Der Völkerbund und Europa , pp. 345
    • Schmitt, C.1
  • 22
    • 84920569279 scopus 로고
    • in Quaritsch, Der Völkerbund und Europa note 14, at 162 et seq., and originally published in 8 Könisberger Auslandsstudien
    • C. Schmitt, Völkerrechtliche Formen des modernen Imperialismus, in Quaritsch, Der Völkerbund und Europa note 14, at 162 et seq., and originally published in 8 Könisberger Auslandsstudien 117-142 (1933).
    • (1933) Völkerrechtliche Formen des modernen Imperialismus , pp. 117-142
    • Schmitt, C.1
  • 26
    • 85011495759 scopus 로고
    • in E. Zechlin (Ed.), Völker und Meere 342 (Leipzig, ).
    • Cf. C. Schmitt, Die letzte globale Linie, in E. Zechlin (Ed.), Völker und Meere 342 (Leipzig, 1944).
    • (1944) Die letzte globale Linie
    • Schmitt, C.1
  • 28
    • 85011433479 scopus 로고
    • (pseudonym for J. Herz), Die Völkerrechtslehre des Nationalsozialismus (Zürich, ). See also Gruchmann, considering Hitler as a model for Schmitt, and comparing Hitler's absolute and fanatic radicality with Schmitt's outlook, Carty plays down Schmitt's enterprise as a “mixture of extreme naiveté and irresponsibility” note 20, at 138; Schmoeckel, considering Hitler as a model for Schmitt, and comparing Hitler's absolute and fanatic radicality with Schmitt's outlook, Carty plays down Schmitt's enterprise as a “mixture of extreme naiveté and irresponsibility” note 15, at
    • Cf. E. Bristler (pseudonym for J. Herz), Die Völkerrechtslehre des Nationalsozialismus (Zürich, 1938). See also Gruchmann, considering Hitler as a model for Schmitt, and comparing Hitler's absolute and fanatic radicality with Schmitt's outlook, Carty plays down Schmitt's enterprise as a “mixture of extreme naiveté and irresponsibility” note 20, at 138; Schmoeckel, considering Hitler as a model for Schmitt, and comparing Hitler's absolute and fanatic radicality with Schmitt's outlook, Carty plays down Schmitt's enterprise as a “mixture of extreme naiveté and irresponsibility” note 15, at 112.
    • (1938) , pp. 112
    • Bristler, E.1
  • 31
    • 85011495528 scopus 로고
    • cf. F. Klein, Die staats-und völkerrechtliche Stellung des Protektorats Böhmen und Mähren, 31 Archiv des öffentlichen Rechts 262. Although Art. 3 of the Decree vaguely spoke of “sovereign rights” to be exercised by officials of the Protectorate, all government members had to be nominated and could at any time be removed by the Reichsprotektor (Art. 5(3)), the German Government could enact statutes for the Protectorate whenever it judged suitable and could assume directly the administration of some sectors (Art. 11).
    • The point was already made clear by the contemporary German doctrine, cf. F. Klein, Die staats-und völkerrechtliche Stellung des Protektorats Böhmen und Mähren, 31 Archiv des öffentlichen Rechts 262 (1940). Although Art. 3 of the Decree vaguely spoke of “sovereign rights” to be exercised by officials of the Protectorate, all government members had to be nominated and could at any time be removed by the Reichsprotektor (Art. 5(3)), the German Government could enact statutes for the Protectorate whenever it judged suitable and could assume directly the administration of some sectors (Art. 11).
    • (1940) The point was already made clear by the contemporary German doctrine
  • 34
    • 85011511362 scopus 로고
    • see M. Rössler, Generalplan Ost (Berlin, 1993); B. Wasser, Himmlers Raumplanung im Osten. Der Generalplan Ost in Polen 1940-1944 (Basel, 1993); and the classical, still valuable works by M. Broszat, Nationalsozialistische Polenpolitik 1939-1945 (Stuttgart, 1961); C. Madajczyk, Die deutsche Besatzungspolitik in Polen 1939-1945 (Wiesbaden, ).
    • On the Generalplan Ost envisaged by the Reichssichereitshauptamt and the German occupation regime in Poland see M. Rössler, Generalplan Ost (Berlin, 1993); B. Wasser, Himmlers Raumplanung im Osten. Der Generalplan Ost in Polen 1940-1944 (Basel, 1993); and the classical, still valuable works by M. Broszat, Nationalsozialistische Polenpolitik 1939-1945 (Stuttgart, 1961); C. Madajczyk, Die deutsche Besatzungspolitik in Polen 1939-1945 (Wiesbaden, 1967).
    • (1967) On the Generalplan Ost envisaged by the Reichssichereitshauptamt and the German occupation regime in Poland
  • 35
    • 84923529184 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the Generalplan Ost envisaged by the Reichssichereitshauptamt and the German occupation regime in Poland note 10, at
    • Cf. Carty, Carl Schmitt's Critique, On the Generalplan Ost envisaged by the Reichssichereitshauptamt and the German occupation regime in Poland note 10, at 43.
    • Carl Schmitt's Critique , pp. 43
    • Carty1
  • 36
    • 85011471578 scopus 로고
    • The manifesto was published in the Giornale d'Italia, the official fascist press organ on 14 July
    • Author's translation (emphasis added). The manifesto was published in the Giornale d'Italia, the official fascist press organ on 14 July 1938.
    • (1938) Author's translation (emphasis added).
  • 37
    • 85011458689 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Carl Schmitt's Critique, Author's translation (emphasis added). note 10, at
    • Carty, Carl Schmitt's Critique, Author's translation (emphasis added). note 10, at 27.
    • Carty1
  • 39
    • 85011516111 scopus 로고
    • A. Verdross & B. Simma, Universelles Völkerrecht (Berlin, 1976); G. Abi-Saab, International Law and the International Community: the Long Road to Universality, in R. Macdonald (Ed.), Essays in Honour of Wang Tieya 31 (London, ).
    • Also the title of the leading German textbook of international law, A. Verdross & B. Simma, Universelles Völkerrecht (Berlin, 1976); G. Abi-Saab, International Law and the International Community: the Long Road to Universality, in R. Macdonald (Ed.), Essays in Honour of Wang Tieya 31 (London, 1994).
    • (1994) Also the title of the leading German textbook of international law
  • 40
    • 85011503286 scopus 로고
    • ('GATT') was rather, to use the expression of Picone, the “inner universalization of the capitalistic system,” see P. Picone, Diritto internazionale dell'economia e costituzione economica dell'ordinamento internazionale, XVI Comunicazioni e Studi
    • What was established with the International Monetary Fund, the World bank and the General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade ('GATT') was rather, to use the expression of Picone, the “inner universalization of the capitalistic system,” see P. Picone, Diritto internazionale dell'economia e costituzione economica dell'ordinamento internazionale, XVI Comunicazioni e Studi 137 (1980).
    • (1980) What was established with the International Monetary Fund, the World bank and the General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade , pp. 137
  • 41
    • 85011458698 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • L'Etat importé, l'occidentalisation de l'ordre politique (Paris, 1992); O.C. Okafor, After Martyrdom: International Law, Sub-State Groups, and the Construction of Legitimate Statehood in Africa, 41 Harv. Int'l L. J.
    • On this issue see B. Badie, L'Etat importé, l'occidentalisation de l'ordre politique (Paris, 1992); O.C. Okafor, After Martyrdom: International Law, Sub-State Groups, and the Construction of Legitimate Statehood in Africa, 41 Harv. Int'l L. J. 503 (2000).
    • (2000) , pp. 503
    • Badie, B.1
  • 42
    • 0006546109 scopus 로고
    • 2nd Edn., at 44 (Paris, 1994); M. Dumoulin, Plans des temps de guerre pour l'Europe d'après-guerre 1940-1947 (Brussels, ).
    • Cf. P. Gerbet, La construction de l'Europe, 2nd Edn., at 44 (Paris, 1994); M. Dumoulin, Plans des temps de guerre pour l'Europe d'après-guerre 1940-1947 (Brussels, 1993).
    • (1993) La construction de l'Europe
    • Gerbet, P.1
  • 43
    • 0006097663 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a pleading of the recovery of the normative dimension of liberal international political theory see C. Reus-Smit, 12 EJIL
    • For a pleading of the recovery of the normative dimension of liberal international political theory see C. Reus-Smit, The Strange Death of Liberal International Theory, 12 EJIL 573 (2001).
    • (2001) The Strange Death of Liberal International Theory , pp. 573
  • 44
    • 85011516106 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see H.G. Preusse, Regional Integration in the Nineties, 28 JWT 147 (1994); J.H. Jackson, Perspectives on Regionalism in Trade Relations, 27 L. & Pol'y Int'l Bus. 873 (1996); H.A. Grigera Naón, Sovereignty and Regionalism, in id., at 1073. Contra S. Hobe, Völkerrecht im Zeitalter der Globalisierung, 37 Archiv des Völkerrechts 253, according to whom the proliferation of regional groups would characterize a transitional era pointing at a better and in time full integration in the world economic system. This theory views the phenomenon of trade regionalism as “building blocks” instead of “stumbling blocks,” for a recent view on this see S. Cho, Breaking the Barrier Between Regionalism and Multilateralism: A New Perspective on Trade Regionalism, 42 Harv. Int'l L. J. 419 (2001).
    • The phenomenon of economic regionalism has reached such proportions that it could no longer be excluded as a possible alternative system to the World Trade Organization, see H.G. Preusse, Regional Integration in the Nineties, 28 JWT 147 (1994); J.H. Jackson, Perspectives on Regionalism in Trade Relations, 27 L. & Pol'y Int'l Bus. 873 (1996); H.A. Grigera Naón, Sovereignty and Regionalism, in id., at 1073. Contra S. Hobe, Völkerrecht im Zeitalter der Globalisierung, 37 Archiv des Völkerrechts 253 (1999), according to whom the proliferation of regional groups would characterize a transitional era pointing at a better and in time full integration in the world economic system. This theory views the phenomenon of trade regionalism as “building blocks” instead of “stumbling blocks,” for a recent view on this see S. Cho, Breaking the Barrier Between Regionalism and Multilateralism: A New Perspective on Trade Regionalism, 42 Harv. Int'l L. J. 419 (2001).
    • (1999) The phenomenon of economic regionalism has reached such proportions that it could no longer be excluded as a possible alternative system to the World Trade Organization
  • 45
    • 85011468379 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On this issue see among others A.A. An-Na'im, Human Rights in the Muslim World, 3 Harvard Human Rights Journal 13 (1990); Y. Ghai, Human Rights and Governance, The Asia Debate, 15 Australian Yearbook of International Law 1 (1994); T.M. Franck, Is Personal Freedom a Western Value?, 91 AJIL
    • Of course, the more macroscopic debate is the one on the so called “human rights relativity.” On this issue see among others A.A. An-Na'im, Human Rights in the Muslim World, 3 Harvard Human Rights Journal 13 (1990); Y. Ghai, Human Rights and Governance, The Asia Debate, 15 Australian Yearbook of International Law 1 (1994); T.M. Franck, Is Personal Freedom a Western Value?, 91 AJIL 593 (1997).
    • (1997) Of course, the more macroscopic debate is the one on the so called “human rights relativity.” , pp. 593
  • 46
    • 85011495722 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • in K. Dicke (Ed.), Berichte der deutschen Gesellschaft für Völkerrecht 427 (Heidelberg, 1999). See also the Symposium held at the Heidelberg Max-Planck-Institut on the occasion of Frowein's 65th birthday, Grenzüberschreitende Konstitutionalisierungsprozesse, 59 ZaöRV
    • Cf. J.A. Frowein, Die Konstitutionalisierung des Völkerrechts, in K. Dicke (Ed.), Berichte der deutschen Gesellschaft für Völkerrecht 427 (Heidelberg, 1999). See also the Symposium held at the Heidelberg Max-Planck-Institut on the occasion of Frowein's 65th birthday, Grenzüberschreitende Konstitutionalisierungsprozesse, 59 ZaöRV 901 (1999).
    • (1999) Die Konstitutionalisierung des Völkerrechts , pp. 901
    • Frowein, J.A.1
  • 47
    • 85011433469 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some of those who hold him in high esteem try to actualize his thesis in the framework of that current of thought known as the “conservative revolution,” which aims at the reestablishment of a “Christian Europe,” on this subject see Carty, Carl Schmitt's Critique, Die Konstitutionalisierung des Völkerrechts note 10, at
    • Another matter is Schmitt's possible influence on the debate on the development of Europe. Some of those who hold him in high esteem try to actualize his thesis in the framework of that current of thought known as the “conservative revolution,” which aims at the reestablishment of a “Christian Europe,” on this subject see Carty, Carl Schmitt's Critique, Die Konstitutionalisierung des Völkerrechts note 10, at 74.
    • Another matter is Schmitt's possible influence on the debate on the development of Europe. , pp. 74
  • 48
    • 85011442619 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id., at
    • Carty, id., at 56.
    • Carty1
  • 49
    • 85011495502 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 87 AJIL 205 (1993); A.-M. Slaughter, A.S. Tulumello & S. Wood, International Law and International Relations Theory: A New Generation of Interdisciplinary Scholarship, 92 AJIL 367 ; A.-M. Slaughter, International Law and International Relations, 285 Recueil des cours 9 (2000).
    • Cf. A.-M. Slaughter, International Law and International Relations Theory: A Dual Agenda, 87 AJIL 205 (1993); A.-M. Slaughter, A.S. Tulumello & S. Wood, International Law and International Relations Theory: A New Generation of Interdisciplinary Scholarship, 92 AJIL 367 (1998); A.-M. Slaughter, International Law and International Relations, 285 Recueil des cours 9 (2000).
    • (1998) International Law and International Relations Theory: A Dual Agenda
    • Slaughter, A.-M.1
  • 50
    • 85011495907 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • International Law and International Relations Theory: A Dual Agenda note 9, at
    • The expression is used by Koskenniemi, International Law and International Relations Theory: A Dual Agenda note 9, at 33.
    • The expression is used by Koskenniemi , pp. 33
  • 51
    • 85011495928 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The expression is used by Koskenniemi note
    • 51, at
    • Cf. Reus-Smit, The expression is used by Koskenniemi note 51, at 586.
    • Reus-Smit1
  • 52
    • 85011434897 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The expression is used by Koskenniemi note
    • 9, at 467. See also S. Marks, Big Brother is Bleeping Us-With the Message that Ideology Doesn't Matter, 12 EJIL
    • Cf. S. Marks, The expression is used by Koskenniemi note 9, at 467. See also S. Marks, Big Brother is Bleeping Us-With the Message that Ideology Doesn't Matter, 12 EJIL 109 (2001).
    • (2001) , pp. 109
    • Marks, S.1
  • 53
    • 85011442598 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The expression is used by Koskenniemi note 9, at
    • Koskenniemi, The expression is used by Koskenniemi note 9, at 34.
    • Koskenniemi1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.