-
1
-
-
0002430002
-
Cross-Purposes: The Liberal-Communitarian Debate
-
And, as Charles Taylor points out, outrage is an important political passion. See, ed. Nancy Rosenblum (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
And, as Charles Taylor points out, outrage is an important political passion. See Charles Taylor, “Cross-Purposes: The Liberal-Communitarian Debate,” Liberalism and the Moral Life, ed. Nancy Rosenblum (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989), 174.
-
(1989)
Liberalism and the Moral Life
, pp. 174
-
-
Taylor, C.1
-
2
-
-
0003576528
-
-
“From both [liberal and republican] perspectives, human rights and popular sovereignty do not so much mutually complement as compete with each other”, [hereafter, BFN] [Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
-
“From both [liberal and republican] perspectives, human rights and popular sovereignty do not so much mutually complement as compete with each other” (Jürgen Habermas, Between Facts and Norms [hereafter, BFN] [Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996], 99).
-
(1996)
Between Facts and Norms
, pp. 99
-
-
Habermas, J.1
-
3
-
-
0035540178
-
Constitutional Democracy: A Paradoxical Union of Contradictory Principles?
-
The claim of social contractual co-originality is belied by the fact that when Habermas turns to elucidate the basic rights of citizens, their private rights come first and their citizenship rights second. Habermas assures us that the first three categories of rights, which “anticipate only that [the parties] will be future users and addressees of the law”, (this issue)] [hereafter, CD], come first just “in mente.” Thus far, the parties have only achieved “clarity regarding the enterprise they have resolved upon with their entrance into a practice of constitution making” (CD, p. 777). They are not yet done. “Because they want to ground an association of citizens who make their own laws, it next occurs to them that they need a fourth category of rights, so they can mutually recognize one another also as the authors of these rights as well as of law in general” (CD, p. 777)
-
The claim of social contractual co-originality is belied by the fact that when Habermas turns to elucidate the basic rights of citizens, their private rights come first and their citizenship rights second. Habermas assures us that the first three categories of rights, which “anticipate only that [the parties] will be future users and addressees of the law” (Jürgen Habermas, “Constitutional Democracy: A Paradoxical Union of Contradictory Principles?” Political Theory [2001 (this issue)] [hereafter, CD], p. 777), come first just “in mente.” Thus far, the parties have only achieved “clarity regarding the enterprise they have resolved upon with their entrance into a practice of constitution making” (CD, p. 777). They are not yet done. “Because they want to ground an association of citizens who make their own laws, it next occurs to them that they need a fourth category of rights, so they can mutually recognize one another also as the authors of these rights as well as of law in general” (CD, p. 777).
-
(2001)
Political Theory
, pp. 777
-
-
Habermas, J.1
-
4
-
-
0004349272
-
Cross Purposes
-
Once they have clarified the full list of rights, private and public, all the rights are created simultaneously, “in a single stroke.” Until that moment of simultaneity, Habermas insists, “nothing has actually happened.” Hasn't it? The priority of private rights is repeatedly on display in Between Facts and Norms, where Habermas claims to be working from a position of co-originality but nonetheless repeatedly puts law at the center and participation at the margins of his account. Might not the order of our thinking have implications for our future practice of politics and the operation of our political imagination? As Charles Taylor points out, the starting point of our thinking about politics reflects a set of ontological commitments or assumptions that we ignore at our peril, and passim)
-
Once they have clarified the full list of rights, private and public, all the rights are created simultaneously, “in a single stroke.” Until that moment of simultaneity, Habermas insists, “nothing has actually happened.” Hasn't it? The priority of private rights is repeatedly on display in Between Facts and Norms, where Habermas claims to be working from a position of co-originality but nonetheless repeatedly puts law at the center and participation at the margins of his account. Might not the order of our thinking have implications for our future practice of politics and the operation of our political imagination? As Charles Taylor points out, the starting point of our thinking about politics reflects a set of ontological commitments or assumptions that we ignore at our peril (Taylor, “Cross Purposes,” 164 and passim).
-
-
-
Taylor1
-
5
-
-
84997954362
-
-
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, [hereafter, IO], Here Habermas seems to echo Stephen Holmes: constitutions may be usefully compared to the rules of a game and even to the rules of grammar. While regulative rules (for instance “no smoking”) govern pre-existent activities, constitutive rules (for instance, “bishops move diagonally”) make a practice possible for the first time. … Constitutions do not merely limit power; they can create and organize power as well as give it direction.…When a constituent assembly establishes a decision procedure, rather than restrict a preexistent will, it actually creates a framework in which the nation can, for the first time, have a will— hence: co-originality?, quoted in Jeremy Waldron, “Precommitment and Disagreement,” Constitutionalism: Philosophical Foundations, ed. Larry Alexander [Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, As Waldron points out, however, the view of constitutional rules as constitutive does not, as such, remove them from the purview of democratic revision and review; that is, it does not secure co-originality as Habermas conceives of it, for it leaves the priority of democracy over constitutionalism intact. Indeed, Waldron points out, democracies often revise the rules of their games, often amid disagreement, as is evidenced by majority but not unanimous decisions in referenda, parliamentary votes, or judicial decisions (pp. 292–94). Constitutive rules require merely that a democracy not change the rules in the very middle of the game's being played. That is, we cannot revise the rules of elections in the middle of the election, “Bush v. Gore notwithstanding,” (as Waldron said in a personal communication)— although if, as Dworkin argues in Law's Empire (Oxford, UK: Hart, 1998), all interpretation involves innovation, even such midstream rule changes are de facto probably unavoidable
-
Jürgen Habermas, The Inclusion of the Other (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1998 [hereafter, IO]), 259. Here Habermas seems to echo Stephen Holmes: constitutions may be usefully compared to the rules of a game and even to the rules of grammar. While regulative rules (for instance “no smoking”) govern pre-existent activities, constitutive rules (for instance, “bishops move diagonally”) make a practice possible for the first time. … Constitutions do not merely limit power; they can create and organize power as well as give it direction.…When a constituent assembly establishes a decision procedure, rather than restrict a preexistent will, it actually creates a framework in which the nation can, for the first time, have a will— hence: co-originality? (Stephen Holmes, Passions and Constraints, quoted in Jeremy Waldron, “Precommitment and Disagreement,” Constitutionalism: Philosophical Foundations, ed. Larry Alexander [Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1998], 290). As Waldron points out, however, the view of constitutional rules as constitutive does not, as such, remove them from the purview of democratic revision and review; that is, it does not secure co-originality as Habermas conceives of it, for it leaves the priority of democracy over constitutionalism intact. Indeed, Waldron points out, democracies often revise the rules of their games, often amid disagreement, as is evidenced by majority but not unanimous decisions in referenda, parliamentary votes, or judicial decisions (pp. 292–94). Constitutive rules require merely that a democracy not change the rules in the very middle of the game's being played. That is, we cannot revise the rules of elections in the middle of the election, “Bush v. Gore notwithstanding,” (as Waldron said in a personal communication)— although if, as Dworkin argues in Law's Empire (Oxford, UK: Hart, 1998), all interpretation involves innovation, even such midstream rule changes are de facto probably unavoidable.
-
(1998)
Passions and Constraints
, pp. 290
-
-
Holmes, S.1
-
6
-
-
0003840036
-
-
Actually, to be more precise, unenforced and unenforceable laws have certain interpellative effects, too. On the impact of seldom enforced antisodomy laws, for example, see, New York: Columbia University Press, and passim
-
Actually, to be more precise, unenforced and unenforceable laws have certain interpellative effects, too. On the impact of seldom enforced antisodomy laws, for example, see Richard Mohr, Gays/Justice: A Study of Ethics, Society and Law (New York: Columbia University Press, 1988), 67 and passim.
-
(1988)
Gays/Justice: A Study of Ethics, Society and Law
, pp. 67
-
-
Mohr, R.1
-
7
-
-
0006523304
-
-
For a wonderful critique (which I do not take up here) of the conservative effects of Habermas's deployment of the subjunctive as if in his work, see, Durham, NC: Duke University Press
-
For a wonderful critique (which I do not take up here) of the conservative effects of Habermas's deployment of the subjunctive as if in his work, see Eric O. Clarke, Virtuous Vice: Homoeroticism and the Public Sphere (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2000).
-
(2000)
Virtuous Vice: Homoeroticism and the Public Sphere
-
-
Clarke, E.O.1
-
8
-
-
0007316099
-
Constitutional Authorship
-
L. Alexander (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press
-
Frank I. Michelman, “Constitutional Authorship,” Constitutionalism: Philosophical Foundations, ed. L. Alexander (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1998), 64–98.
-
(1998)
Constitutionalism: Philosophical Foundations
, pp. 64-98
-
-
Michelman, F.I.1
-
9
-
-
84997971834
-
-
This is a problem with a history, posed also by, [New York: Penguin, and Jacques Derrida
-
This is a problem with a history, posed also by Sieyés, Rousseau, Hannah Arendt (On Revolution, [New York: Penguin, 1970 (hereafter, OR)], 183–84) and Jacques Derrida.
-
(1970)
On Revolution
, pp. 183-184
-
-
Sieyés1
Rousseau2
Arendt, H.3
-
10
-
-
84952401799
-
Declarations of Independence
-
It is the problem of authorization in the absence of foundational grounds, the problem of how to stop the cycle of revolution and stabilize political order, the problem, as Derrida puts it, of what to put “in the place of the last instance”, at 10). Rousseau solved the problem by way of the lawgiver, a good man prior to good law, whose agency enables law's inauguration. But this was no solution, since the lawgiver merely deepens rather than resolves the tension between law and democracy
-
It is the problem of authorization in the absence of foundational grounds, the problem of how to stop the cycle of revolution and stabilize political order, the problem, as Derrida puts it, of what to put “in the place of the last instance” (Jacques Derrida, “Declarations of Independence,” New Political Science 15 [1987]: 7–15 at 10). Rousseau solved the problem by way of the lawgiver, a good man prior to good law, whose agency enables law's inauguration. But this was no solution, since the lawgiver merely deepens rather than resolves the tension between law and democracy.
-
(1987)
New Political Science
, vol.15
, pp. 7-15
-
-
Derrida, J.1
-
11
-
-
84997858378
-
-
How can the people be free when they need the guidance of a lawgiver?, [Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, forthcoming], chap. 1.) Michelman also responds to the law versus democracy problem by turning to a good man prior to good law: Justice Brennan (Frank I. Michelman, Brennan and Democracy, [Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, Arendt argued that America never really faced the abyss of infinite regress because many local and state constitutions and compacts predated the new federal constitution and were able to funnel power to it and secure it, before being themselves undone by it (OR, chaps. 4 and 6)
-
How can the people be free when they need the guidance of a lawgiver? (See Alan Keenan, Democracy in Question: Rethinking Democratic Openness in a Time of Political Closure [Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, forthcoming], chap. 1.) Michelman also responds to the law versus democracy problem by turning to a good man prior to good law: Justice Brennan (Frank I. Michelman, Brennan and Democracy, [Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1999]). Arendt argued that America never really faced the abyss of infinite regress because many local and state constitutions and compacts predated the new federal constitution and were able to funnel power to it and secure it, before being themselves undone by it (OR, chaps. 4 and 6).
-
(1999)
Democracy in Question: Rethinking Democratic Openness in a Time of Political Closure
-
-
Keenan, A.1
-
12
-
-
0004341165
-
Contingent Foundations
-
OR (chap. 5), ed. Seyla Benhabib, Judith Butler, Nancy Fraser, and Drucilla Cornell (New York: Routledge
-
OR (chap. 5); Judith Butler, “Contingent Foundations,” Feminist Contentions, ed. Seyla Benhabib, Judith Butler, Nancy Fraser, and Drucilla Cornell (New York: Routledge, 1995).
-
(1995)
Feminist Contentions
-
-
Butler, J.1
-
13
-
-
18844383525
-
Hannah Arendt: From an Interview
-
October 26
-
Hannah Arendt, “Hannah Arendt: From an Interview” New York Review of Books 25, no. 16 (October 26, 1978): 18.
-
(1978)
New York Review of Books
, vol.25
, Issue.16
, pp. 18
-
-
Arendt, H.1
-
14
-
-
21444437077
-
The Liberal/Democratic Divide: On Rawls' Political Liberalism
-
The wording is, at 117). The point is not that Rawls would not object to these inequalities, he would, but he would not ask whether they might be remnants or traces of an earlier practice of slavery supposedly left behind by enlightened constitutionalism (Political Liberalism [New York: Columbia University Press, 1996], xxix)
-
The wording is Sheldon Wolin's (“The Liberal/Democratic Divide: On Rawls' Political Liberalism,” Political Theory 24, no. 1 [1996]: 97–142 at 117). The point is not that Rawls would not object to these inequalities, he would, but he would not ask whether they might be remnants or traces of an earlier practice of slavery supposedly left behind by enlightened constitutionalism (Political Liberalism [New York: Columbia University Press, 1996], xxix).
-
(1996)
Political Theory
, vol.24
, Issue.1
, pp. 97-142
-
-
Wolin's, S.1
-
15
-
-
0004345227
-
Liberal/Democratic Divide
-
Wolin, “Liberal/Democratic Divide,” 108.
-
-
-
Wolin1
-
17
-
-
0004236696
-
-
For a reading of Tocqueville's Indians as always already dead, see, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, chap. 7
-
For a reading of Tocqueville's Indians as always already dead, see William Connolly, The Ethos of Pluralization (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1995), chap. 7
-
(1995)
The Ethos of Pluralization
-
-
Connolly, W.1
-
18
-
-
0345774502
-
Bowling Blind: Post Liberal Civil Society and the Worlds of Neo-Tocquevillean Social Theory
-
[Online]
-
Michael Shapiro, “Bowling Blind: Post Liberal Civil Society and the Worlds of Neo-Tocquevillean Social Theory,” Theory & Event [Online] 1, no. 1 (1997). Available from: http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/theory_&_event/.
-
(1997)
Theory & Event
, vol.1
, Issue.1
-
-
Shapiro, M.1
-
19
-
-
0141494758
-
-
For a compelling analysis of freedom as an-arche, see, innovative reading of Machiavelli: Between Form and Event: Machiavelli's, Dordrecht, the Netherlands: Kluwer
-
For a compelling analysis of freedom as an-arche, see Miguel Vatter's innovative reading of Machiavelli: Between Form and Event: Machiavelli's Theory of Political Freedom (Dordrecht, the Netherlands: Kluwer, 2000).
-
(2000)
Theory of Political Freedom
-
-
Vatter's, M.1
-
20
-
-
0002873467
-
Norm and Form: The Constitutionalising of Democracy
-
ed. J. Peter Euben, John R. Wallach, and Josiah Ober (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press
-
Sheldon Wolin, “Norm and Form: The Constitutionalising of Democracy,” Athenian Political Thought and the Reconstruction of American Democracy, ed. J. Peter Euben, John R. Wallach, and Josiah Ober (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1994).
-
(1994)
Athenian Political Thought and the Reconstruction of American Democracy
-
-
Wolin, S.1
-
21
-
-
0007531846
-
-
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press
-
See Richard Flathman, The Practice of Rights (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1976)
-
(1976)
The Practice of Rights
-
-
Flathman, R.1
-
22
-
-
0003954872
-
-
New York: Free Press, Flathman emphasizes the practiced character of rights; Warner calls attention to (among other things) their normalizing power and the ways in which satisfaction with rights works against the generation of power as action in concert
-
Michael Warner, The Trouble with Normal (New York: Free Press, 2000). Flathman emphasizes the practiced character of rights; Warner calls attention to (among other things) their normalizing power and the ways in which satisfaction with rights works against the generation of power as action in concert.
-
(2000)
The Trouble with Normal
-
-
Warner, M.1
-
23
-
-
34548693123
-
Deconstruction in America: An Interview with Jacques Derrida
-
(Jacques Derrida, “Deconstruction in America: An Interview with Jacques Derrida,” Critical Exchange 17 [1985]: 24–25).
-
(1985)
Critical Exchange
, vol.17
, pp. 24-25
-
-
Derrida, J.1
-
24
-
-
0003983498
-
-
See also my discussion of these issues by way of, in Bonnie Honig, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, chap. 4
-
See also my discussion of these issues by way of Derrida and Arendt in Bonnie Honig, Political Theory and the Displacement of Politics (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1993), chap. 4.
-
(1993)
Political Theory and the Displacement of Politics
-
-
Derrida1
Arendt2
-
25
-
-
0012595340
-
-
Building on Cohen and Arato, Habermas uses the term “dual orientation” to describe the democratic actor's coupling of her agitation on behalf of her own agenda with a reflexive concern to “revitalize and enlarge civil society” (BFN, 370). It does not occur to him that the two parts of this orientation might conflict. What if care for the public sphere or the common good requires a commitment to practices of genealogy and critique that demand that we commit ourselves to forms of social upheaval that make it impossible to sustain practices of public reason? What if the rights-centered pressures of public reason get in the way of political efforts at world building? What if care for the world presses us to frame arguments in such a way that our immediate agenda may be lost (as when racial activists, seeking to enter “racism” into liberal lexicons, refuse to translate all of their claims of harm into individual wrongs, even though that translation might be efficacious in the moment)? (I have in mind here Dorothy Roberts's argument against the current foster care system in the United States, that it not only harms individual children but also commits a racial harm, stigmatizing African Americans generally, since the vast majority of children in the system are black, New York: Basic Books
-
Building on Cohen and Arato, Habermas uses the term “dual orientation” to describe the democratic actor's coupling of her agitation on behalf of her own agenda with a reflexive concern to “revitalize and enlarge civil society” (BFN, 370). It does not occur to him that the two parts of this orientation might conflict. What if care for the public sphere or the common good requires a commitment to practices of genealogy and critique that demand that we commit ourselves to forms of social upheaval that make it impossible to sustain practices of public reason? What if the rights-centered pressures of public reason get in the way of political efforts at world building? What if care for the world presses us to frame arguments in such a way that our immediate agenda may be lost (as when racial activists, seeking to enter “racism” into liberal lexicons, refuse to translate all of their claims of harm into individual wrongs, even though that translation might be efficacious in the moment)? (I have in mind here Dorothy Roberts's argument against the current foster care system in the United States, that it not only harms individual children but also commits a racial harm, stigmatizing African Americans generally, since the vast majority of children in the system are black. See Dorothy Roberts, Shattered Bonds: The Color of Child Welfare [New York: Basic Books, 2001].)
-
(2001)
Shattered Bonds: The Color of Child Welfare
-
-
Roberts, D.1
-
26
-
-
0004063810
-
-
points out, a politics that “suggests that the most recent identities [rights, achievements, constitutional decisions] are also the most true, natural or advanced” is one that “discourages proponents from cultivating that partial, comparative sense of contingency in their own identities from which responsiveness to new claims of difference might proceed”, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press
-
As William Connolly points out, a politics that “suggests that the most recent identities [rights, achievements, constitutional decisions] are also the most true, natural or advanced” is one that “discourages proponents from cultivating that partial, comparative sense of contingency in their own identities from which responsiveness to new claims of difference might proceed” (Why I Am Not a Secularist [Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1999], 71).
-
(1999)
Why I Am Not a Secularist
, pp. 71
-
-
Connolly, W.1
-
27
-
-
0003932294
-
-
stresses the importance of contextualism to political theory and likes the Canadian “notwithstanding clause” for its apparent sensitivity to context, Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press
-
Joseph Carens stresses the importance of contextualism to political theory and likes the Canadian “notwithstanding clause” for its apparent sensitivity to context (Culture, Citizenship, and Community: A Contextual Exploration of Justice As Evenhandedness [Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 2000]).
-
(2000)
Culture, Citizenship, and Community: A Contextual Exploration of Justice As Evenhandedness
-
-
Carens, J.1
-
28
-
-
84997927126
-
-
For a more ambivalent account of the notwithstanding clause than the one presented by me here or by, see my review of Carens in, Spring
-
For a more ambivalent account of the notwithstanding clause than the one presented by me here or by Carens, see my review of Carens in Polity 33, no. 3 (Spring 2001): 479–85.
-
(2001)
Polity
, vol.33
, Issue.3
, pp. 479-485
-
-
Carens1
|