메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 28, Issue 3, 2000, Pages 421-439

Chasing Plato

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 84997968048     PISSN: 00905917     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1177/0090591700028003006     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (8)

References (28)
  • 1
    • 84997879242 scopus 로고
    • Plato Oxoniensis
    • For a witty version of how the needs of each age result in certain interpretations of Plato, see, Noting interpretations ranging from Plato as proto-Christian to Plato as a planner for “the reconstruction of society in post-war Europe” (91), he observes that “there are as many ‘Platos’ as there are philosophical movements” (94)
    • For a witty version of how the needs of each age result in certain interpretations of Plato, see T. M. Robinson, “Plato Oxoniensis,” University of Toronto Quarterly 37 (1967): 90–102. Noting interpretations ranging from Plato as proto-Christian to Plato as a planner for “the reconstruction of society in post-war Europe” (91), he observes that “there are as many ‘Platos’ as there are philosophical movements” (94).
    • (1967) University of Toronto Quarterly , vol.37 , pp. 90-102
    • Robinson, T.M.1
  • 2
    • 84998171150 scopus 로고
    • An extraordinarily helpful book on the history of Platonic interpretation is Eugene Tigerstadt's, Stockholm, Sweden: Almqvist & Wiksell
    • An extraordinarily helpful book on the history of Platonic interpretation is Eugene Tigerstadt's Interpreting Plato (Stockholm, Sweden: Almqvist & Wiksell, 1976).
    • (1976) Interpreting Plato
  • 3
    • 0002189480 scopus 로고
    • See also, ed. Charles L. Griswold Jr., New York: Routledge
    • See also Platonic Writings, Platonic Readings, ed. Charles L. Griswold Jr. (New York: Routledge, 1988).
    • (1988) Platonic Writings, Platonic Readings
  • 4
    • 84997920748 scopus 로고
    • ed. and trans. L. G. Westerlink, Amsterdam, I have slightly altered Westerlink's translation in a few places, 28
    • Anonymous Prolegomena to Platonic Philosophy, ed. and trans. L. G. Westerlink (Amsterdam, 1962), 4. I have slightly altered Westerlink's translation in a few places, 28.
    • (1962) Anonymous Prolegomena to Platonic Philosophy , pp. 4
  • 5
    • 0004056394 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • These thinkers are much more complicated than these labels imply; however, I merely want to suggest that these labels get regularly attached to these thinkers. For example, Josiah Ober notes that Vlastos presents “the ‘Socrates’ depicted in Plato's early dialogues as a quasi-liberal who respected Athenian constitutional arrangements and appreciated the freedom, openness, and diversity of Athenian society.”, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • These thinkers are much more complicated than these labels imply; however, I merely want to suggest that these labels get regularly attached to these thinkers. For example, Josiah Ober notes that Vlastos presents “the ‘Socrates’ depicted in Plato's early dialogues as a quasi-liberal who respected Athenian constitutional arrangements and appreciated the freedom, openness, and diversity of Athenian society.” Ober, Political Dissent in Democratic Athens (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1998), 158.
    • (1998) Political Dissent in Democratic Athens , pp. 158
    • Ober1
  • 6
    • 0003448197 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • While there is no shortage of recognition of Leo Strauss's conservatism, for one example, see, New York: St. Martin's
    • While there is no shortage of recognition of Leo Strauss's conservatism, for one example, see Shadia B. Drury, Leo Strauss and the American Right (New York: St. Martin's, 1997).
    • (1997) Leo Strauss and the American Right
    • Drury, S.B.1
  • 7
    • 0005812519 scopus 로고
    • The question of Platonic chronology is a lively field. On Vlastos's chronological views, see, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, esp. chap
    • The question of Platonic chronology is a lively field. On Vlastos's chronological views, see Socrates: Ironist and Moral Philosopher (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1991), esp. chap.
    • (1991) Socrates: Ironist and Moral Philosopher
  • 8
    • 0042559877 scopus 로고
    • Re-reading Plato: The Problem of Platonic Chronology
    • For a persuasive critique of Vlastos's position, see especially, Jacob Howland's essay, Autumn
    • For a persuasive critique of Vlastos's position, see especially, Jacob Howland's essay “Re-reading Plato: The Problem of Platonic Chronology,” Phoenix 45 (Autumn 1991): 189–214.
    • (1991) Phoenix , vol.45 , pp. 189-214
  • 9
    • 80053699697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • E Pluribus Unum: On the Platonic ‘Corpus,’
    • Charles L. Griswold Jr. notes many problems of chronological assumptions in his review of Charles Kahn's Plato and the Socratic Dialogue and even more tellingly points out the many opposing views that Kahn—and most “developmentalists”—consistently overlook
    • Charles L. Griswold Jr. notes many problems of chronological assumptions in his review of Charles Kahn's Plato and the Socratic Dialogue and even more tellingly points out the many opposing views that Kahn—and most “developmentalists”—consistently overlook. Griswold, “E Pluribus Unum: On the Platonic ‘Corpus,’” Ancient Philosophy 19 (1999): 361–397.
    • (1999) Ancient Philosophy , vol.19 , pp. 361-397
    • Griswold1
  • 10
    • 0004243325 scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • Leo Strauss, The City and Man (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1964), 59–60.
    • (1964) The City and Man , pp. 59-60
    • Strauss, L.1
  • 14
    • 0004144149 scopus 로고
    • For various readings that take Plato's recommendations seriously, and hence view them as threatening to democracy, see, Boston: Little Brown, chap 2
    • For various readings that take Plato's recommendations seriously, and hence view them as threatening to democracy, see Sheldon Wolin, Politics and Vision (Boston: Little Brown, 1960), chap 2
    • (1960) Politics and Vision
    • Wolin, S.1
  • 15
    • 0003850824 scopus 로고
    • and, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • and Jean Bethke Elshtain, Public Man, Private Woman (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1981), 20–41.
    • (1981) Public Man, Private Woman , pp. 20-41
    • Elshtain, J.B.1
  • 16
    • 0004158377 scopus 로고
    • For a reading that views Plato's recommendation as ironic, and hence a warning to philosophy by philosophy, see, Albany: State University of New York Press
    • For a reading that views Plato's recommendation as ironic, and hence a warning to philosophy by philosophy, see Mary Nichols, Socrates and the Political Community: An Ancient Debate (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1987).
    • (1987) Socrates and the Political Community: An Ancient Debate
    • Nichols, M.1
  • 20
    • 84997876392 scopus 로고
    • Western Civ
    • New York: Simon & Schuster, Bloom takes comfort in the fact that he has been attacked by Arthur Schlesinger for being a reactionary, while Walker Percy has accused him of being “a nihilist.” He states that “this equilibrium of criticism reassures me that I am in the right way” (19)
    • Allan Bloom, “Western Civ,” in Giants and Dwarves: Essays 1960–1990 (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1990), 13–31. Bloom takes comfort in the fact that he has been attacked by Arthur Schlesinger for being a reactionary, while Walker Percy has accused him of being “a nihilist.” He states that “this equilibrium of criticism reassures me that I am in the right way” (19).
    • (1990) Giants and Dwarves: Essays 1960–1990 , pp. 13-31
    • Bloom, A.1
  • 21
    • 33845668654 scopus 로고
    • The Illegality of the Constitution
    • There is a certain similarity between the machinations of Athena in the Eumenides and the appeals of the Federalists during the American founding. After all, according to the Articles of Confederation, changes to the Articles could only be made by unanimous consent of the states. The Federalists, however, perhaps illegally claimed that the Constitution could be ratified by nine of thirteen states. As one constitutional scholar has written, “[The] foundation of American legality was itself the product of a blatant and conscious illegality. But this illegality is indeed a paradox and not a contradiction. … Every legal system is governed, at the end, by principles whose authority cannot be found in law.”, I am grateful to my colleague Keith E. Whittington for pointing out this article to me
    • There is a certain similarity between the machinations of Athena in the Eumenides and the appeals of the Federalists during the American founding. After all, according to the Articles of Confederation, changes to the Articles could only be made by unanimous consent of the states. The Federalists, however, perhaps illegally claimed that the Constitution could be ratified by nine of thirteen states. As one constitutional scholar has written, “[The] foundation of American legality was itself the product of a blatant and conscious illegality. But this illegality is indeed a paradox and not a contradiction. … Every legal system is governed, at the end, by principles whose authority cannot be found in law.” Richard S. Kay, “The Illegality of the Constitution,” Constitutional Commentary 4 (1987): 57–58. I am grateful to my colleague Keith E. Whittington for pointing out this article to me.
    • (1987) Constitutional Commentary , vol.4 , pp. 57-58
    • Kay, R.S.1
  • 22
    • 84998091129 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Apology, 30e.
    • Apology , pp. 30e
  • 23
    • 84967096720 scopus 로고
    • trans. John Cummings, New York: Continuum, “The Concept of Enlightenment” and “Excursus I: Odysseus or Myth and Enlightenment.” Rocco is content to summarize Horkheimer and Adorno's view of Odysseus without subjecting it to the “critical” vision he recommends throughout his book
    • Max Horkheimer and Theodor W. Adorno, Dialectic of Enlightenment, trans. John Cummings (New York: Continuum, 1991), “The Concept of Enlightenment” and “Excursus I: Odysseus or Myth and Enlightenment.” Rocco is content to summarize Horkheimer and Adorno's view of Odysseus without subjecting it to the “critical” vision he recommends throughout his book.
    • (1991) Dialectic of Enlightenment
    • Horkheimer, M.1    Adorno, T.W.2
  • 24
    • 60949170610 scopus 로고
    • Transcending Humanity
    • On the implications of this choice, see Martha C. Nussbaum's, New York: Oxford University Press, Horkheimer and Adorno are so unwilling to perceive any redeeming features in antiquity in general, and of Odysseus in particular, that they assert one of Odysseus' primary objectives is that of “self-preservation.” They are correct that he attempts to preserve his “self” in resisting the lure of the lotus-eaters and other temptations that threaten his self-consciousness, but they do not recognize that this priority does not justify the attempt to go beyond the limits of life itself
    • On the implications of this choice, see Martha C. Nussbaum's “Transcending Humanity” in Love's Knowledge (New York: Oxford University Press, 1990), 365–91. Horkheimer and Adorno are so unwilling to perceive any redeeming features in antiquity in general, and of Odysseus in particular, that they assert one of Odysseus' primary objectives is that of “self-preservation.” They are correct that he attempts to preserve his “self” in resisting the lure of the lotus-eaters and other temptations that threaten his self-consciousness, but they do not recognize that this priority does not justify the attempt to go beyond the limits of life itself.
    • (1990) Love's Knowledge , pp. 365-391
  • 25
    • 0004134693 scopus 로고
    • Adorno was generally opposed to participation in politics, arguing for a need to withdraw to one's “own house,” a view which extended, to the surprise of the New Left, to the student movement in the 1960s. He argued that a contemplative “nicht-mitzumanchen” was preferable to an all-consuming “mitmachen.” See, Boston: Little Brown
    • Adorno was generally opposed to participation in politics, arguing for a need to withdraw to one's “own house,” a view which extended, to the surprise of the New Left, to the student movement in the 1960s. He argued that a contemplative “nicht-mitzumanchen” was preferable to an all-consuming “mitmachen.” See Martin Jay, The Dialectical Imagination: A History of the Frankfurt School, 1923–1950 (Boston: Little Brown, 1973), 291
    • (1973) The Dialectical Imagination: A History of the Frankfurt School, 1923–1950 , pp. 291
    • Jay, M.1
  • 28
    • 0010316731 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Meno, 80e, 81c-e. I have used G.M.A. Grube's translation in, ed. John M. Cooper, Indianapolis, IN: Hackett
    • Meno, 80e, 81c-e. I have used G.M.A. Grube's translation in Plato: Complete Works, ed. John M. Cooper (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1997).
    • (1997) Plato: Complete Works


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.