메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 5, Issue 1, 1999, Pages 1-44

Rescue and harm: Discussion of Peter Unger's Living High and Letting Die

(1)  Kamm, F M a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 84990300989     PISSN: 13523252     EISSN: 14698048     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S1352325299501018     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (9)

References (39)
  • 2
    • 85022796077 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at least insofar as he describes the latter as the complete denial that intuitions about cases reveal any moral truth. See id. at 13. In the same paragraph, however, he also describes negativism, not as a methodological principle about intuitions, but as the attempt to bring about consistency between seemingly conflicting intuitions by denying the duty to aid quite generally, rather than extending the duty to aid quite generally. This makes negativism a substantive position about aiding: We need not suffer any loss to reduce mortal loss. Substantive negativism also liberates us from what it takes to be negatively distorted (i.e., non-truth tracking) intuitions about cases, only it sees these as the ones that tell us to aid. These are the very ones that Unger thinks are positively (i.e., truth tracking) distorted.
    • Unger contrasts his position on intuitions with what he calls negativism, at least insofar as he describes the latter as the complete denial that intuitions about cases reveal any moral truth. See id. at 13. In the same paragraph, however, he also describes negativism, not as a methodological principle about intuitions, but as the attempt to bring about consistency between seemingly conflicting intuitions by denying the duty to aid quite generally, rather than extending the duty to aid quite generally. This makes negativism a substantive position about aiding: We need not suffer any loss to reduce mortal loss. Substantive negativism also liberates us from what it takes to be negatively distorted (i.e., non-truth tracking) intuitions about cases, only it sees these as the ones that tell us to aid. These are the very ones that Unger thinks are positively (i.e., truth tracking) distorted.
    • Unger contrasts his position on intuitions with what he calls negativism
  • 4
    • 85022873233 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, why, they ask, do nonconsequentialists say that we may redirect a trolley to save six from being killed by it when we foresee this will kill one, if we may not save six from the trolley by pushing someone in front of it? As we shall see, Unger repeats this criticism but goes beyond it. He tries to show that sometimes we would say it is permissible to push someone in front of a trolley to save six and sometimes we would say it is impermissible, and this (he claims) is a clear inconsistency. Insofar as he tries to change our responses to acts on the basis of altering what he believes are morally irrelevant features of the context, his technique is like “framing” used by cognitive psychologists Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky. See my Moral Intuitions, Cognitive Psychology, and the Harming-versus-Not-Aiding Distinction, ETHICS, cviii
    • Consequentialists have often accused nonconsequentialists of being inconsistent. For example, why, they ask, do nonconsequentialists say that we may redirect a trolley to save six from being killed by it when we foresee this will kill one, if we may not save six from the trolley by pushing someone in front of it? As we shall see, Unger repeats this criticism but goes beyond it. He tries to show that sometimes we would say it is permissible to push someone in front of a trolley to save six and sometimes we would say it is impermissible, and this (he claims) is a clear inconsistency. Insofar as he tries to change our responses to acts on the basis of altering what he believes are morally irrelevant features of the context, his technique is like “framing” used by cognitive psychologists Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky. See my Moral Intuitions, Cognitive Psychology, and the Harming-versus-Not-Aiding Distinction, ETHICS, cviii (1998).
    • (1998) Consequentialists have often accused nonconsequentialists of being inconsistent
  • 6
    • 85022861557 scopus 로고
    • Famine, Affluence, and Morality, reprinted in 22-36 (W. Aiken & H. LaFollette eds., 1977); and Peter Singer, PRACTICAL ETHICS (2d ed. ).
    • In Famine, Affluence, and Morality, reprinted in WORLD HUNGER AND MORAL OBLIGATION 22-36 (W. Aiken & H. LaFollette eds., 1977); and Peter Singer, PRACTICAL ETHICS (2d ed. 1993).
    • (1993) WORLD HUNGER AND MORAL OBLIGATION
  • 7
    • 49549087050 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For detailed discussion of that issue, see, 2 MORALITY
    • For detailed discussion of that issue, see F.M. Kamm, 2 MORALITY, MORTALITY chs. 1-5 (1996).
    • (1996) MORTALITY , pp. 1-5
    • Kamm, F.M.1
  • 8
    • 85022791240 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The first step, I believe, is a sounder way than the second of seeing whether a factor has an effect in the original Sedan. This is because if a factor is “exported” into the Envelope Case, as in the second step, it may have no effect in its new context, but this will not show it had no effect on its home ground. (This is due to what I call the Principle of Contextual Interaction.) For discussion of these points, see
    • The first step, I believe, is a sounder way than the second of seeing whether a factor has an effect in the original Sedan. This is because if a factor is “exported” into the Envelope Case, as in the second step, it may have no effect in its new context, but this will not show it had no effect on its home ground. (This is due to what I call the Principle of Contextual Interaction.) For discussion of these points, see Kamm, MORTALITY note 8.
    • MORTALITY note , pp. 8
    • Kamm1
  • 10
    • 85022745103 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 28.
    • Id. , pp. 28
  • 12
    • 85022791768 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Unpublished paper presented at the New York University Colloquium on Law, Philosophy, and Social Theory
    • Liam Murphy, Institutions and the Demands of Justice. Unpublished paper presented at the New York University Colloquium on Law, Philosophy, and Social Theory, 1997.
    • (1997) Institutions and the Demands of Justice
    • Murphy, L.1
  • 15
    • 85022787534 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For more detail on this and other points in this article, see, Institutions and the Demands of Justice note note note
    • For more detail on this and other points in this article, see Kamm, Faminine Ethics, Institutions and the Demands of Justice note note note 6.
    • Faminine Ethics , pp. 6
    • Kamm1
  • 18
    • 85022799213 scopus 로고
    • I first tried to show this in my article Supererogation and Obligation, J. PHIL. (March 1985), reprinted in. For an expanded version, see Kamm, THE REJECTION OF CONSEQUENTIALISM note note 8, ch.
    • I first tried to show this in my article Supererogation and Obligation, J. PHIL. (March 1985), reprinted in THE PHILOSOPHER'S ANNUAL (1985). For an expanded version, see Kamm, THE REJECTION OF CONSEQUENTIALISM note note 8, ch. 12.
    • (1985) THE PHILOSOPHER'S ANNUAL , pp. 12
  • 21
    • 0040866644 scopus 로고
    • flip side
    • I focused on this aspect of the Trolley Case in my first attempt to explain it. See F.M. Kamm, Harming Some to Save Others, PHIL. STUD. (November ).
    • I focused on this “flip side” aspect of the Trolley Case in my first attempt to explain it. See F.M. Kamm, Harming Some to Save Others, PHIL. STUD. (November 1989).
    • (1989)
  • 23
    • 85022855803 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 100.
    • Id. , pp. 100
  • 24
    • 85022742433 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • which Unger also describes, is just a way, I believe, of creating cases with several options. See id.
    • The method of aptly combining cases, which Unger also describes, is just a way, I believe, of creating cases with several options. See id. at 106-14.
    • The method of aptly combining cases , pp. 106-114
  • 27
    • 85022745989 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 28
    • 85022851817 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I first discussed the lazy Susan cases in Harming Some to Save Others, Id. note 48. See also, 8, for additional discussion.
    • I first discussed the lazy Susan cases in Harming Some to Save Others, Id. note 48. See also Kamm, Id. note 8, for additional discussion.
    • Id. note
    • Kamm1
  • 29
    • 85022888001 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In his, David Lewis accepts that varying grouping and protophysics accounts for our intuitions, but he denies that these factors are morally irrelevant. See, vi. I deny that the factors account for our intuitions and that the factors are morally relevant.
    • In his review of Unger's book, David Lewis accepts that varying grouping and protophysics accounts for our intuitions, but he denies that these factors are morally irrelevant. See EUREKA STREET, vi (1996). I deny that the factors account for our intuitions and that the factors are morally relevant.
    • (1996) review of Unger's book
    • STREET, E.1
  • 31
    • 85022856109 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I have described this principle in detail in id. and in in BLACKWELL'S GUIDE TO ETHICAL THEORY (H. LaFollette ed., forthcoming ).
    • I have described this principle in detail in id. and in Nonconsequentialism, in BLACKWELL'S GUIDE TO ETHICAL THEORY (H. LaFollette ed., forthcoming 1999).
    • (1999) Nonconsequentialism
  • 33
    • 85022807484 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In 2 MORTALITY, The Problem of Abortion and the Doctrine of Double Effect note 8, I describe the major emendation to this description of the PPH, that sometimes diversion of people from threat or threat from people is not sufficient for the greater good; but, I claim, when it is nevertheless permissible to redirect, this is because (a) diversion produces what I call the “structural equivalent of the greater good,” and (b) while we divert only because the further effect occurs, we do not divert in order to produce that further effect.
    • In 2 MORALITY, MORTALITY, The Problem of Abortion and the Doctrine of Double Effect note 8, I describe the major emendation to this description of the PPH, that sometimes diversion of people from threat or threat from people is not sufficient for the greater good; but, I claim, when it is nevertheless permissible to redirect, this is because (a) diversion produces what I call the “structural equivalent of the greater good,” and (b) while we divert only because the further effect occurs, we do not divert in order to produce that further effect.
    • MORALITY
  • 35
    • 85022900831 scopus 로고
    • Unger notes that we might not redirect when on balance we only maximize utility by a smaller amount than a foot. I have discussed the question of what is an “irrelevant utility” in such cases (and in others as well) in detail first in BIOETHICS (1987), and in F.M. Kamm, 1 MORALITY, chs.
    • Unger notes that we might not redirect when on balance we only maximize utility by a smaller amount than a foot. I have discussed the question of what is an “irrelevant utility” in such cases (and in others as well) in detail first in BIOETHICS (1987), and in F.M. Kamm, 1 MORALITY, MORTALITY (1993), chs. 5-10.
    • (1993) MORTALITY , pp. 5-10
  • 37
    • 26444586750 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MORTALITY note note 48, and Kamm, MORTALITY note note
    • See Kamm, Harming Some to Save Others, MORTALITY note note 48, and Kamm, MORTALITY note note 8.
    • Harming Some to Save Others , pp. 8
    • Kamm1
  • 39
    • 85022836115 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • He says (p. 166).
    • He says , pp. 166


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.