메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 38, Issue 4, 1986, Pages 546-576

The theory of games and the balance of power

(1)  Wagner, R Harrison a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 84975994663     PISSN: 00438871     EISSN: 10863338     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.2307/2010166     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (62)

References (20)
  • 6
    • 84976204490 scopus 로고
    • The Theory of Games and the Balance of Power
    • Evidence for this assertion is presented in, Washington, DC, September, (subsequently revised)
    • Evidence for this assertion is presented in R. Harrison Wagner, “The Theory of Games and the Balance of Power,” Annual Meetings of the American Political Science Association, Washington, DC, September 1984 (subsequently revised).
    • (1984) Annual Meetings of the American Political Science Association
    • Wagner, R.H.1
  • 10
    • 84976145097 scopus 로고
    • New York: Knopf
    • Organski, World Politics (New York: Knopf, 1958), 271–338
    • (1958) Organski, World Politics , pp. 271-338
  • 11
    • 0004266156 scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • A.F.K. Organski and Jacek Kugler, The War Ledger (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1980), 13–63.
    • (1980) The War Ledger , pp. 13-63
    • Organski, A.F.K.1    Kugler, J.2
  • 12
    • 9744259566 scopus 로고
    • From Balance to Deterrence: A Theoretical Analysis
    • July
    • Arthur Lee Burns, “From Balance to Deterrence: A Theoretical Analysis,” World Politics 9 (July 1957), 494–529.
    • (1957) World Politics , vol.9 , pp. 494-529
    • Lee Burns, A.1
  • 13
    • 0000558986 scopus 로고
    • Sequential Equilibria
    • For a discussion of this and related issues, see, July, I would like to acknowledge Robert Powell's help in defining the endpoints of this game and the players' payoff functions
    • For a discussion of this and related issues, see David Kreps and Robert Wilson, “Sequential Equilibria,” Econometrica 50 (July 1982), 863–94. I would like to acknowledge Robert Powell's help in defining the endpoints of this game and the players' payoff functions.
    • (1982) Econometrica , vol.50 , pp. 863-894
    • Kreps, D.1    Wilson, R.2
  • 14
    • 85050175350 scopus 로고
    • Theoretical Analysis of the Balance of Power
    • Burns (fn. 11). See also, July
    • Burns (fn. 11). See also Morton Kaplan, Arthur Burns, and Richard Quandt, “Theoretical Analysis of the Balance of Power,” Behavioral Science 5 (July 1960), 240–52.
    • (1960) Behavioral Science , vol.5 , pp. 240-252
    • Kaplan, M.1    Burns, A.2    Quandt, R.3
  • 15
    • 84976108536 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Theory of the Balance of Power
    • Both Robert Powell and Emerson Niou have independently pointed out to me that, if the victim is allowed to make a preemptive transfer of just enough resources to the unopposed attacker to give it R/2 units, it will lose fewer resources, and will thus prefer to make this transfer. Moreover, if the opposed attacker would like to acquire resources peacefully, then it, too, will prefer this outcome, and this, rather than the outcome described in the text, is the only equilibrium. (For a development of this idea, see, forthcoming.) But what is necessary for the existence of this alternative equilibrium is not simply voluntary transfers, but transfers to which the opposed attacker has no opportunity to respond. Otherwise the reasoning in the text applies, and both the victim and the opposed attacker will prefer to join against the unopposed attacker if it tries to take advantage of the victim's offer. While the rules of the game do not allow voluntary transfers, therefore, the reasoning in the text is consistent with any means of transferring resources from the victim to the unopposed ally that allows the opposed ally to make a counter-offer before the transfer is completed
    • Both Robert Powell and Emerson Niou have independently pointed out to me that, if the victim is allowed to make a preemptive transfer of just enough resources to the unopposed attacker to give it R/2 units, it will lose fewer resources, and will thus prefer to make this transfer. Moreover, if the opposed attacker would like to acquire resources peacefully, then it, too, will prefer this outcome, and this, rather than the outcome described in the text, is the only equilibrium. (For a development of this idea, see Emerson M. S. Niou and Peter C. Ordeshook, “A Theory of the Balance of Power,” Journal of Conflict Resolution, forthcoming.) But what is necessary for the existence of this alternative equilibrium is not simply voluntary transfers, but transfers to which the opposed attacker has no opportunity to respond. Otherwise the reasoning in the text applies, and both the victim and the opposed attacker will prefer to join against the unopposed attacker if it tries to take advantage of the victim's offer. While the rules of the game do not allow voluntary transfers, therefore, the reasoning in the text is consistent with any means of transferring resources from the victim to the unopposed ally that allows the opposed ally to make a counter-offer before the transfer is completed.
    • Journal of Conflict Resolution
    • Niou, E.M.S.1    Ordeshook, P.C.2
  • 16
    • 84925924780 scopus 로고
    • The Decision to Divide Germany and the Origins of the Cold War
    • The quantity of resources with which the victim is left is thus determined by the relation between the rate at which unopposed attackers can absorb resources from their victims and the time required for states to retarget their resources. That is the (somewhat artificial) implication of the particular assumptions made earlier. The specific form of the conclusion is less important than the general point: that the inability of states to prevent their allies from taking advantage of the division of their victims is an important factor in preserving the independence of the victims. The conflict between the U.S. and the U.S.S.R. that arose out of the question of the division of Germany is perhaps a relevant example. See, June
    • The quantity of resources with which the victim is left is thus determined by the relation between the rate at which unopposed attackers can absorb resources from their victims and the time required for states to retarget their resources. That is the (somewhat artificial) implication of the particular assumptions made earlier. The specific form of the conclusion is less important than the general point: that the inability of states to prevent their allies from taking advantage of the division of their victims is an important factor in preserving the independence of the victims. The conflict between the U.S. and the U.S.S.R. that arose out of the question of the division of Germany is perhaps a relevant example. See R. Harrison Wagner. “The Decision to Divide Germany and the Origins of the Cold War,” International Studies Quarterly 24 (June 1980), 155–90.
    • (1980) International Studies Quarterly , vol.24 , pp. 155-190
    • Wagner, R.H.1
  • 17
    • 0003771795 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press
    • Robert Gilpin, War and Change in World Politics (Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 1981).
    • (1981) War and Change in World Politics
    • Gilpin, R.1
  • 18
    • 84976031914 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Waltz (fn. 1), 164.
    • Waltz1
  • 19
    • 84974380232 scopus 로고
    • Cooperation under the Security Dilemma
    • See, for example, January
    • See, for example, Robert Jervis, “Cooperation under the Security Dilemma,” World Politics 30 (January 1978), 167–214.
    • (1978) World Politics , vol.30 , pp. 167-214
    • Jervis, R.1
  • 20
    • 84974185472 scopus 로고
    • The Theory of Games and the Problem of International Cooperation
    • In order to avoid misunderstandings, let me emphasize what should be obvious: that the game analyzed in this article is quite different from either a single-play or a repeated Prisoners' Dilemma game, and therefore the literature on international cooperation based on the analysis of Prisoners' Dilemma games is not relevant to the issues examined here. See also, June
    • In order to avoid misunderstandings, let me emphasize what should be obvious: that the game analyzed in this article is quite different from either a single-play or a repeated Prisoners' Dilemma game, and therefore the literature on international cooperation based on the analysis of Prisoners' Dilemma games is not relevant to the issues examined here. See also R. Harrison Wagner, “The Theory of Games and the Problem of International Cooperation,” American Political Science Review 77 (June 1983), 330–46.
    • (1983) American Political Science Review , vol.77 , pp. 330-346
    • Wagner, R.H.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.