메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 18, Issue , 1992, Pages 333-354

Justice and the good from a eudaimonistic standpoint

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 84972716601     PISSN: 01914537     EISSN: 1461734x     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1177/019145379201800307     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (2)

References (22)
  • 2
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Harvard University Press
    • J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice, 1971, Cambridge, Harvard University Press, p. 129.
    • (1971) A Theory of Justice , pp. 129
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 3
    • 84972722673 scopus 로고
    • With the choice of this dichotomy, Dworkin presents a liberal, yet non-deontological conception of justice ‘a conception of justice as liberal equality. Cf. R. Dworkin, Foundations of Liberal Equality, The Tanner Lectures on Human Values, Vol. VII, Salt Lake City, University of Utah Press
    • Dworkin characterizes his own view of justice as continuous with a comprehensive and defensible view of the good. With the choice of this dichotomy, Dworkin presents a liberal, yet non-deontological conception of justice ‘a conception of justice as liberal equality. Cf. R. Dworkin, Foundations of Liberal Equality, The Tanner Lectures on Human Values, Vol. VII, Salt Lake City, University of Utah Press, 1990, p. 67.
    • (1990) Dworkin characterizes his own view of justice as continuous with a comprehensive and defensible view of the good , pp. 67
  • 4
    • 0009396776 scopus 로고
    • Frankfurt, Suhrkamp, pp. 103ff., J. Habermas, Faktizitat und Geltung. Beiträgezur Diskurstheorie des Rechts und des demokratischen Rechtstaats, 1992.
    • Cf. J. Habermas, Erlaüterungen zur Diskursethik, 1991, Frankfurt, Suhrkamp, pp. 103ff., J. Habermas, Faktizitat und Geltung. Beiträgezur Diskurstheorie des Rechts und des demokratischen Rechtstaats, 1992.
    • (1991) Erlaüterungen zur Diskursethik
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 5
    • 84972674005 scopus 로고
    • Boston, Beacon Press Vol. II, ch. V, 3. Cf. also J. Habermas, Erlarterungen zur Diskursethik, p. 39.
    • Cf. J. Habermas, Theory of Communicative Action, 1984, Boston, Beacon Press, Vol. I, p. 20-21, Vol. II, ch. V, 3. Cf. also J. Habermas, Erlarterungen zur Diskursethik, p. 39.
    • (1984) Theory of Communicative Action , vol.1 , pp. 20-21
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 9
    • 84972722649 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In fact, the crucial factor determining the rightness of a norm would not be the discursively generated “rational consensus,” but ultimately the factual absence of contradictions between two lists of propositions, i.e., the one which contains descriptions of the effects of a generalized observance of the norm and the one which contains descriptions of what each person wants. Discourse heuiistically could help us draft, edit or refine the two lists’ the lists of the projected effects of the norm and the list which records what each participant wants-but could add or subtract nothing to the absence or existence of contradictions between items on the two lists. It would be helpful in preparing the decision, irrelevant in determining it.
    • In this case it would be hard to make sense of what is discourse-theoretic about the Diskursethik. In fact, the crucial factor determining the rightness of a norm would not be the discursively generated “rational consensus,” but ultimately the factual absence of contradictions between two lists of propositions, i.e., the one which contains descriptions of the effects of a generalized observance of the norm and the one which contains descriptions of what each person wants. Discourse heuiistically could help us draft, edit or refine the two lists’ the lists of the projected effects of the norm and the list which records what each participant wants-but could add or subtract nothing to the absence or existence of contradictions between items on the two lists. It would be helpful in preparing the decision, irrelevant in determining it.
    • In this case it would be hard to make sense of what is discourse-theoretic about the Diskursethik
  • 12
    • 0346873379 scopus 로고
    • In “The priority of Right and Ideas of the Good
    • Rawls illustrates five ideas of the good that satisfy this condition and on which the theory of justice can thus freely draw: a) the idea of “goodness as rationality,” b) the idea of “primary goods,” c) the idea of “permissible conceptions of the good,”d) the ideaof “political virtues,” e) the idea of the good for a political society as such.” Cf. J. Rawls, “The Priority of Right and Ideas of the Good,” in Philosophy and Public Affairs
    • In “The priority of Right and Ideas of the Good,” Rawls illustrates five ideas of the good that satisfy this condition and on which the theory of justice can thus freely draw: a) the idea of “goodness as rationality,” b) the idea of “primary goods,” c) the idea of “permissible conceptions of the good,”d) the ideaof “political virtues,” e) the idea of the good for a political society as such.” Cf. J. Rawls, “The Priority of Right and Ideas of the Good,” in Philosophy and Public Affairs, 1988, Vol. 17, n. 4, pp. 253-73.
    • (1988) , vol.17 , Issue.4 , pp. 253
  • 13
    • 84935547375 scopus 로고
    • Justice as Fairness: Political not Metaphysical
    • J. Rawls, “The Priority of Right and Ideas of the Good,” J. Rawls, “The Idea of an Overlapping Consensus,” in Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 1987, Vol. 7, n. 1, pp. 1-25; R. Rorty, “The Priority of Democracy over Philosophy,” in R. Vaughan (ed.), The Virginia Statute of Religious Freedom: Two Hundred Years After, 1988, Madison, University of Wisconsin Press, pp. 262-68.
    • Cf. J. Rawls, “Justice as Fairness: Political not Metaphysical,” in Philosophy and Public Affairs, 1985, pp. 223-51; J. Rawls, “The Priority of Right and Ideas of the Good,” in Philosophy and Public Affairs, J. Rawls, “The Idea of an Overlapping Consensus,” in Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 1987, Vol. 7, n. 1, pp. 1-25; R. Rorty, “The Priority of Democracy over Philosophy,” in R. Vaughan (ed.), The Virginia Statute of Religious Freedom: Two Hundred Years After, 1988, Madison, University of Wisconsin Press, pp. 262-68.
    • (1985) in Philosophy and Public Affairs , pp. 223
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 14
    • 0004284007 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Cambridge University Press
    • C. Larmore, Patterns of Moral Complexity, 1987, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, pp. 52-53.
    • (1987) Patterns of Moral Complexity , pp. 52-53
    • Larmore, C.1
  • 15
    • 0004238625 scopus 로고
    • New York, Basic Books, ch. 13
    • Cf. M. Walzer, Spheres of Justice, 1983, New York, Basic Books, ch. 13.
    • (1983) Spheres of Justice
    • Walzer, M.1
  • 16
    • 84972618951 scopus 로고
    • Three Paths in Moral Philosophy
    • Cambridge, Harvard University Press
    • Cf. also, “Three Paths in Moral Philosophy,” in M. Walzer, Interpretation and Social Criticism, 1987, Cambridge, Harvard University Press.
    • (1987) Interpretation and Social Criticism
    • Walzer, M.1
  • 17
    • 84936068266 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass., Harvard University Press
    • Cf. R. Dworkin, Law's Empire, 1986, Cambridge, Mass., Harvard University Press, pp. 228-32.
    • (1986) Law's Empire , pp. 228
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 18
    • 0004123406 scopus 로고
    • Notre Dame, University of Notre Dame Press
    • A. Maclntyre, After Virtue, 1981, Notre Dame, University of Notre Dame Press, pp. 228-32.
    • (1981) After Virtue , pp. 228
    • Maclntyre, A.1
  • 21
    • 84972607074 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The same point is made by Maclntyre in his discussion of the concept of a practice in relation to the notion of a skill (Cf. A. Maclntyre, After Virtue, pp. 180-81) and his account of the model of challenge, understood as ‘the model of the quest,” has no aesthetic connotation.
    • This, however, seems hardly sufficient to qualify the model of challenge as an aesthetic view of the good life. The same point is made by Maclntyre in his discussion of the concept of a practice in relation to the notion of a skill (Cf. A. Maclntyre, After Virtue, pp. 180-81) and his account of the model of challenge, understood as ‘the model of the quest,” has no aesthetic connotation.
    • This, however, seems hardly sufficient to qualify the model of challenge as an aesthetic view of the good life


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.