메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 15, Issue 2, 1981, Pages 161-184

‘Objective’ Interests and the Sociology of Power

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 84972714375     PISSN: 00380385     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1177/003803858101500202     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (96)

References (35)
  • 5
    • 0000977278 scopus 로고
    • ‘On the Neo-Elitist Critique of Community Power’
    • For example and
    • For example, R. M. Merelman, ‘On the Neo-Elitist Critique of Community Power’, American Political Science Review, 62, 1968, pp. 451-60; and
    • (1968) American Political Science Review , vol.62 , pp. 451-460
    • Merelman, R.M.1
  • 7
    • 84959631151 scopus 로고
    • ‘The Two Faces of Power’
    • ‘Decisions and Non-decisions: An Analytical Framework’, American Political Science Review, 57, 1963, pp. 641-51; and Power and Poverty: Theory and Practice, New York, 1970
    • P. Bachrach and M. S. Baratz, ‘The Two Faces of Power’, American Political Science Review, 56, 1962, pp. 947-52; ‘Decisions and Non-decisions: An Analytical Framework’, American Political Science Review, 57, 1963, pp. 641-51; and Power and Poverty: Theory and Practice, New York, 1970.
    • (1962) American Political Science Review , vol.56 , pp. 947-952
    • Bachrach, P.1    Baratz, M.S.2
  • 11
    • 0000368780 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ‘Essentially Contested Concepts’
    • pp. 167-98. See also W. B. Gallie, Philosophy and the Historical Understanding, 1964, chap. 8. For a criticism of Lukes's use of Gallie, see K. I. MacDonald, ‘Is ‘power’ essentially contested?’, British Journal of Political Science, 6, 1976, pp. 380-2. Lukes's reply (BJPS, 7, 1977, pp. 418-9) seems to concede that there are differences between his and Gallie's uses of the phrase ‘essentially contested’, but argues, with some justification in my view, that MacDonald wholly misses the point of his (Lukes's) argument
    • W. B. Gallie, ‘Essentially Contested Concepts’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 56, 1955-6, pp. 167-98. See also W. B. Gallie, Philosophy and the Historical Understanding, 1964, chap. 8. For a criticism of Lukes's use of Gallie, see K. I. MacDonald, ‘Is ‘power’ essentially contested?’, British Journal of Political Science, 6, 1976, pp. 380-2. Lukes's reply (BJPS, 7, 1977, pp. 418-9) seems to concede that there are differences between his and Gallie's uses of the phrase ‘essentially contested’, but argues, with some justification in my view, that MacDonald wholly misses the point of his (Lukes's) argument.
    • Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society , vol.56 , pp. 1955-1956
    • Gallie, W.B.1
  • 13
    • 84972647162 scopus 로고
    • and John Gray, ‘Power, Structure and the State’, mimeo, Department of Government, University of Essex, 1977
    • K. I. MacDonald, Government and Opposition, 1975, and John Gray, ‘Power, Structure and the State’, mimeo, Department of Government, University of Essex, 1977.
    • (1975) Government and Opposition
    • MacDonald, K.I.1
  • 14
    • 0344658703 scopus 로고
    • ‘Relativism: Cognitive and Moral’
    • 1974, reprinted in S. Lukes, Essays in Social Theory, London
    • S. Lukes, ‘Relativism: Cognitive and Moral’, in Supplementary Procedings of the Aristotelian Society, 1974, reprinted in S. Lukes, Essays in Social Theory, London, 1977, pp. 154-74.
    • (1977) Supplementary Procedings of the Aristotelian Society , pp. 154-174
    • Lukes, S.1
  • 15
    • 84947348599 scopus 로고
    • See cha
    • See S. Lukes, Power, 1977, cha p. 6.
    • (1977) Power , pp. 6.
    • Lukes, S.1
  • 19
    • 84972718544 scopus 로고
    • S. Lukes, Power, 10, 1976, p. 47.
    • (1976) Power , vol.10 , pp. 47.
    • Lukes, S.1
  • 21
    • 84977205480 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ‘The Concept of Interest in Politics’
    • See
    • See Grenville Wall, ‘The Concept of Interest in Politics’, Politics and Society, 5, 14, pp. 487-510.
    • Politics and Society , vol.5 , Issue.14 , pp. 487-510
    • Grenville, W.1
  • 22
    • 84972684791 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ‘The Concept of Interest in Politics’
    • A. Bradshaw, ‘The Concept of Interest in Politics’, Politics and Society, 5, 14, p. 122.
    • Politics and Society , vol.5 , Issue.14 , pp. 122.
    • Bradshaw, A.1
  • 24
  • 25
  • 26
  • 27
    • 84972698551 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 18th Brumaire
    • K. Marx, 18th Brumaire.
    • Marx, K.1
  • 28
    • 84972695012 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • p. 34. It is not, of course, my purpose to argue here that such despair is necessarily misplaced, but rather, that Lukes's use of Gramsci is incompatible with it
    • S. Lukes, p. 34. It is not, of course, my purpose to argue here that such despair is necessarily misplaced, but rather, that Lukes's use of Gramsci is incompatible with it.
    • Lukes, S.1
  • 29
    • 84972720692 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In his recent book London, 1979, Stewart Clegg advocates a revision of Lukes's view of power by abandoning this ‘primitive’ causal concept of power altogether. This is a revision in the opposite direction from my own, which is designed to produce a more thoroughly and consistently causal conception than that offered by Lukes himself
    • In his recent book, The Theory of Power and Organisation, London, 1979, Stewart Clegg advocates a revision of Lukes's view of power by abandoning this ‘primitive’ causal concept of power altogether. This is a revision in the opposite direction from my own, which is designed to produce a more thoroughly and consistently causal conception than that offered by Lukes himself.
    • The Theory of Power and Organisation
  • 30
    • 0003917413 scopus 로고
    • distinction between ‘power to’ and ‘power over’ here, corresponds closely to Anthony distinction between a ‘broad’ sense of power, a logical component of the idea of ‘action’ itself, and a ‘narrow’ sense, proper to interactions between a plurality of actors. (See his ‘Remarks on the Theory of Power’ in London
    • My distinction between ‘power to’ and ‘power over’ here, corresponds closely to Anthony Giddens's distinction between a ‘broad’ sense of power, a logical component of the idea of ‘action’ itself, and a ‘narrow’ sense, proper to interactions between a plurality of actors. (See his ‘Remarks on the Theory of Power’ in A. Giddens, Studies in Social and Political Theory, London, 1977, pp. 347-8).
    • (1977) Studies in Social and Political Theory , pp. 347-348
    • Giddens, A.1
  • 34
    • 84972725214 scopus 로고
    • Oxford An important difference, however, is in the conceptual link which Wright makes between class-capacities and interests (p. 98). Although Wright explicitly denies that attributions of ‘fundamental’ class interests make ‘an ahistorical moralistic claim’, it is not clear that he has a coherent alternative to this. Sometimes his position seems to approach that of Lukes, basing interest-ascriptions on conditional hypotheses about how classes would behave under conditions of autonomy (‘in the absence of the mystification and distortions of capitalist relations’). Elsewhere, it seems that his conception is closer to the Lukacsian one, in which not merely hypothetical conditions are supposed, but also a hypothetical (ideal-typical) rational class-actor (‘if workers had a scientific understanding of the contradictions of capitalism, they would in fact engage in struggles for socialism’). See E. O. Wright, pp. 87 ff
    • Erik Olin Wright, Causal Power, Oxford, 1975, p. 99. An important difference, however, is in the conceptual link which Wright makes between class-capacities and interests (p. 98). Although Wright explicitly denies that attributions of ‘fundamental’ class interests make ‘an ahistorical moralistic claim’, it is not clear that he has a coherent alternative to this. Sometimes his position seems to approach that of Lukes, basing interest-ascriptions on conditional hypotheses about how classes would behave under conditions of autonomy (‘in the absence of the mystification and distortions of capitalist relations’). Elsewhere, it seems that his conception is closer to the Lukacsian one, in which not merely hypothetical conditions are supposed, but also a hypothetical (ideal-typical) rational class-actor (‘if workers had a scientific understanding of the contradictions of capitalism, they would in fact engage in struggles for socialism’). See E. O. Wright, pp. 87 ff.
    • (1975) Causal Power , pp. 99
    • Erik, O.W.1
  • 35
    • 84972720582 scopus 로고
    • There are some interesting parallels between my treatment of the agency/structure problem, here, and that given by Lukes himself, but, of course, in much greater detail and depth, in his essay ‘Power and Structure’ (in London I depart from him, though, in a number of respects. First, he tends, in my view, to conflate the concepts of ‘power’ and ‘agency’. For me, agency is the exercise of power, whereas the possession of a power is (principally) a structural property of an agent (individual or collective)
    • There are some interesting parallels between my treatment of the agency/structure problem, here, and that given by Lukes himself, but, of course, in much greater detail and depth, in his essay ‘Power and Structure’ (in C. S. Lukes, Essays in Social Theory, London, 1978, pp. 3-29). I depart from him, though, in a number of respects. First, he tends, in my view, to conflate the concepts of ‘power’ and ‘agency’. For me, agency is the exercise of power, whereas the possession of a power is (principally) a structural property of an agent (individual or collective).
    • (1978) Essays in Social Theory , pp. 3-29
    • Lukes, C.S.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.