메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 28, Issue 1, 1985, Pages 27-50

Text and context: Skinner, hobbes and theistic natural law

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 84954601259     PISSN: 0018246X     EISSN: 14695103     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S0018246X0000220X     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (11)

References (73)
  • 1
    • 84972213772 scopus 로고
    • On the concept of ‘revolution’ in this context, see J. Pocock, Politics, language and time: essays on political thought and history (New York
    • On the concept of ‘revolution’ in this context, see J. Pocock, Politics, language and time: essays on political thought and history (New York, 1973). p. 3.
    • (1973) , pp. 3
  • 2
    • 77954116608 scopus 로고
    • Hobbes's Leviathan
    • Q. Skinner, ‘Hobbes's Leviathan’, Historical Journal, Vii, 2 (1976), 333.
    • (1976) Historical Journal , vol.7 , Issue.2 , pp. 333
    • Skinner, Q.1
  • 3
    • 0039403925 scopus 로고
    • The context of Hobbes's theory of political obligation', in Cranston and Peters
    • New York Skinner does not explain what is involved in the distinction between 'deontological' and 'rationalist-utilitarian' but it seems clear that he takes them to be mutually exclusive
    • Q. Skinner, 'The context of Hobbes's theory of political obligation', in Cranston and Peters, Hobbes and Rousseau (New York, 1972), p. 141. Skinner does not explain what is involved in the distinction between 'deontological' and 'rationalist-utilitarian' but it seems clear that he takes them to be mutually exclusive.
    • (1972) Hobbes and Rousseau , pp. 141
    • Skinner, Q.1
  • 4
    • 0003771927 scopus 로고
    • Natural rights theories: their origin and development
    • Cambridge
    • R. Tuck, Natural rights theories: their origin and development, (Cambridge, 1979), p. 102.
    • (1979) , pp. 102
    • Tuck, R.1
  • 5
    • 84972262752 scopus 로고
    • A discourse: wherein it is examined what is particularly lawful during the confusions and revolutions of governments
    • London preface
    • Anthony Ascham, A discourse: wherein it is examined what is particularly lawful during the confusions and revolutions of governments (London 1648). preface.
    • (1648)
    • Anthony Ascham1
  • 6
    • 85055358610 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Context
    • Skinner, ‘Context’, p. 131.
    • Skinner1
  • 7
    • 85055358610 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Context
    • Skinner, ‘Context’, p. 131.
    • Skinner1
  • 8
    • 84971912970 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Discourse
    • Ascham, Discourse, p. 98.
    • Ascham1
  • 9
    • 84971912970 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Discourse
    • Ascham, Discourse, p. 23.
    • Ascham1
  • 10
    • 62249204155 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Natural rights
    • Tuck, Natural rights, pp. 121–123.
    • Tuck1
  • 11
    • 80054336393 scopus 로고
    • The case of the commonwealth of England
    • London
    • Marchamont Nedham, The case of the commonwealth of England (London, 1650).
    • (1650)
    • Marchamont Nedham1
  • 12
    • 85055358610 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Context
    • Skinner, ‘Context’, p. 135.
    • Skinner1
  • 13
    • 84900930811 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Case of the commonwealth
    • Nedham, Case of the commonwealth, p. 103.
    • Nedham1
  • 14
    • 0039398856 scopus 로고
    • The ideological context of Hobbes's political thought
    • Skinner, ‘The ideological context of Hobbes's political thought’, Historical Journal, 9, 3 (1966), 292.
    • (1966) Historical Journal , vol.9 , Issue.3 , pp. 292
    • Skinner1
  • 15
    • 33745305053 scopus 로고
    • Table talk
    • (London
    • John Selden, Table talk (London, 1689), p. 30.
    • (1689) , pp. 30
    • Selden, J.1
  • 16
    • 84972196815 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A possible exception is Matthew Wren's
    • Monarchy asserted of 1659. But even if we take Wren to be the only true Hobbist with the correct line on Hobbes - we are then faced with the problem of the other so-called Hobbists. If ‘history’ gives us conflicting evidence with regard to interpretation - we must in the end rely on our own interpretation
    • A possible exception is Matthew Wren's Monarchy asserted of 1659. But even if we take Wren to be the only true Hobbist with the correct line on Hobbes - we are then faced with the problem of the other so-called Hobbists. If ‘history’ gives us conflicting evidence with regard to interpretation - we must in the end rely on our own interpretation.
  • 17
    • 84972131358 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A persuasive to a mutual compliance
    • Oxford 1652 [1651
    • Francis Osborne, A persuasive to a mutual compliance (Oxford, 1652 [1651 ?]) p. 10.
    • Francis Osborne1
  • 18
    • 84972131345 scopus 로고
    • Eight reasons categorical
    • London
    • Albertus Warren, Eight reasons categorical (London, 1653), p. 5.
    • (1653) , pp. 5
    • Albertus Warren1
  • 19
    • 84972281765 scopus 로고
    • The royalist reformed
    • London
    • Albertus Warren, The royalist reformed (London, 1650), p. 26.
    • (1650) , pp. 26
    • Albertus Warren1
  • 20
    • 84972281746 scopus 로고
    • The grounds of the laws of England
    • London dedication
    • Michael Hawke, The grounds of the laws of England (London, 1657), dedication.
    • (1657)
    • Michael Hawke1
  • 21
    • 80052728255 scopus 로고
    • Killing is murder and no murder
    • London
    • Michael Hawke, Killing is murder and no murder (London, 1657), p. 7.
    • (1657) , pp. 7
    • Michael Hawke1
  • 22
    • 84972196793 scopus 로고
    • The right of dominion
    • London
    • Michael Hawke, The right of dominion (London, 1655), p. 22.
    • (1655) , pp. 22
    • Michael Hawke1
  • 23
    • 84972398409 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The grounds of obedience and government
    • no place of publication given
    • Thomas White, The grounds of obedience and government (no place of publication given, 165[9]), p. 44.
    • , vol.165 , Issue.9 , pp. 44
    • Thomas White1
  • 24
    • 84972173892 scopus 로고
    • Of obedience and government
    • London preface
    • John Hall, Of obedience and government (London, 1654), preface.
    • (1654)
    • John Hall1
  • 25
    • 84972250844 scopus 로고
    • Euctatus Philodemius
    • London J. W. Packer (The transformation of Anglicanism, Manchester, 1969, p. 178) suggests that Philodemius is the pseudonym for Anthony Ascham although, despite a search for which I am grateful, he has been unable to locate the evidence for this suggestion; nor have I
    • Euctatus Philodemius, The original and end of civil power (London, 1649), p. 15. J. W. Packer (The transformation of Anglicanism, Manchester, 1969, p. 178) suggests that Philodemius is the pseudonym for Anthony Ascham although, despite a search for which I am grateful, he has been unable to locate the evidence for this suggestion; nor have I.
    • (1649) The original and end of civil power , pp. 15
  • 26
    • 62249204155 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Natural rights
    • 84 Selden, Table talk, p. 41
    • Tuck, Natural rights, p. 82. 84 Selden, Table talk, p. 41.
    • Tuck1
  • 27
    • 84972220569 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Although the Tew writers
    • didn't publish until the 1640s and so could have been influenced by Hobbes, Selden's published work predates that of Hobbes. Strictly speaking, the discussion of influence remains - as in most cases - speculative; we don't know much of what Hobbes was thinking prior to 1628. People can be influential without ever publishing at all
    • Although the Tew writers didn't publish until the 1640s and so could have been influenced by Hobbes, Selden's published work predates that of Hobbes. Strictly speaking, the discussion of influence remains - as in most cases - speculative; we don't know much of what Hobbes was thinking prior to 1628. People can be influential without ever publishing at all.
  • 28
    • 62249204155 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Natural rights
    • ch. 5
    • Tuck, Natural rights, ch. 5.
    • Tuck1
  • 31
    • 84972478522 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Tuck is misleading to suggest that Warrender found the basis of natural law in God's will; this is but one of the possibilities Warrender entertains as the ultimate ground of obligation. See Warrender ch. 13. 90 Tuck, Natural rights, p. 131
    • Tuck is misleading to suggest that Warrender found the basis of natural law in God's will; this is but one of the possibilities Warrender entertains as the ultimate ground of obligation. See Warrender, The political theory of Hobbes, p. 11 and ch. 13. 90 Tuck, Natural rights, p. 131.
    • The political theory of Hobbes , pp. 11
  • 34
    • 84972196895 scopus 로고
    • Molesworth (London Emphasis in original.) E.W. iv xiii
    • Hobbes. The English works of Thomas Hobbes, ed., Molesworth (London, 1889), 1. (Emphasis in original.) E.W. iv xiii.
    • (1889) The English works of Thomas Hobbes , vol.1
    • Hobbes1
  • 35
  • 37
    • 84972131372 scopus 로고
    • review of Warrender's The political philosophy of Hobbes
    • Dowling, R. E., review of Warrender's The political philosophy of Hobbes, Australasian Journal of Politics, 1958, p. 226.
    • (1958) Australasian Journal of Politics , pp. 226
    • Dowling, R.E.1
  • 41
    • 84972368471 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hobbes is not a wolf in sheep's clothing although he may be a wolf in wolf's clothing
    • By announcing his departures from earlier theorists and proclaiming his novelties of method and argument he can hardly be said to be engaged in concealment. His treatment of the role of God is discussed below
    • Hobbes is not a wolf in sheep's clothing although he may be a wolf in wolf's clothing. By announcing his departures from earlier theorists and proclaiming his novelties of method and argument he can hardly be said to be engaged in concealment. His treatment of the role of God is discussed below.
  • 44
    • 84972315026 scopus 로고
    • Works, ed Keble, rev. Church and Paget, 7th edition (Oxford
    • Hooker, R., Works, ed., Keble, rev. Church and Paget, 7th edition (Oxford, 1889), 1, 334.
    • (1889) , vol.1 , pp. 334
    • Hooker, R.1
  • 47
    • 84972266816 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Perhaps because of this famous passage scholars
    • disagree about Grotius's position in the history of political thought. d'Entrèves sees him as the beginning of ‘rationalist’ hence secular modern natural law (. Natural law, 2nd edition (London, 1970), p. 55). Pollock (postscript to Sir H. Maine, Ancient law, (London 1930), p. 120) and Rommen (The natural law, trans. T. Hanley (St. Louis, 1949), p. 70) emphasize links to earlier Scholastic thought as does A. H. Chroust (‘ Hugo Grotius and the Scholastic natural law tradition’, The New Scholasticism, xvn, 1943, p. 125). The latter explains this passage as a rationalist rebuke of voluntarism and nominalism while Rommen (p. 72) sees Grotius as an exponent of voluntarism
    • Perhaps because of this famous passage scholars disagree about Grotius's position in the history of political thought. d'Entrèves sees him as the beginning of ‘rationalist’ hence secular modern natural law (.Natural law, 2nd edition (London, 1970), p. 55). Pollock (postscript to Sir H. Maine, Ancient law, (London 1930), p. 120) and Rommen (The natural law, trans. T. Hanley (St. Louis, 1949), p. 70) emphasize links to earlier Scholastic thought as does A. H. Chroust (‘ Hugo Grotius and the Scholastic natural law tradition’, The New Scholasticism, xvn, 1943, p. 125). The latter explains this passage as a rationalist rebuke of voluntarism and nominalism while Rommen (p. 72) sees Grotius as an exponent of voluntarism.
  • 48
    • 84972266780 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • perceptively treated in Largarde
    • This issue is See also J. T. McNeill, ‘Natural law in the teaching of the reformers’, The Journal of Religion, xxvi (1946), 177–8; J. W. Allen, ‘The political conceptions of Luther’, in Tudor Studies, ed., Seton-Watson (London, 1924), p. 101
    • This issue is perceptively treated in Largarde, Recherches, p. 25. See also J. T. McNeill, ‘Natural law in the teaching of the reformers’, The Journal of Religion, xxvi (1946), 177–8; J. W. Allen, ‘The political conceptions of Luther’, in Tudor Studies, ed., Seton-Watson (London, 1924), p. 101.
    • Recherches , pp. 25
  • 50
    • 24444434256 scopus 로고
    • 2nd edition (Harmondsworth
    • Peters, R., Hobbes, 2nd edition (Harmondsworth, 1967) p. 245.
    • (1967) Hobbes , pp. 245
    • Peters, R.1
  • 52
    • 84972216025 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hugo Grotius
    • Chroust, ‘Hugo Grotius’, p. 114.
    • Chroust1
  • 54
    • 84972264854 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • No case is made here to establish links between Suarez and Hobbes. Hobbes had, of course, read at least some of Suarez's work and described it as ‘amongst the many sorts of madness’. England generally was also familiar with him since James I publicly burnt his treatise Defensio Fidei in front of St Paul's church in London. See J. B. Scott's introduction to Suarez xx, 20a
    • No case is made here to establish links between Suarez and Hobbes. Hobbes had, of course, read at least some of Suarez's work and described it as ‘amongst the many sorts of madness’. England generally was also familiar with him since James I publicly burnt his treatise Defensio Fidei in front of St Paul's church in London. See J. B. Scott's introduction to Suarez, Selections, in Classics, xx, 20a.
    • Selections, in Classics
  • 57
    • 84965792310 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ch. 2, par. 5: 'if I cannot but wish to receive good… how should I look to have any part of my desire herein satisfied unless myself be careful to satisfy the like desire, which is undoubtedly in other men, being of one and the same nature?… from which relation of equality… what several rules and canons natural reason hath drawn, for direction of life, no man is ignorant
    • Locke, Second treatise, ch. 2, par. 5: 'if I cannot but wish to receive good… how should I look to have any part of my desire herein satisfied unless myself be careful to satisfy the like desire, which is undoubtedly in other men, being of one and the same nature?… from which relation of equality… what several rules and canons natural reason hath drawn, for direction of life, no man is ignorant. '
    • Second treatise
    • Locke1
  • 59
    • 0004085243 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge Natural law, p. 40; see also Rommen, The natural law, p. 75
    • Gierke, Political theories of the Middle Ages (Cambridge, 1927), p. 80-90; Natural law, p. 40; see also Rommen, The natural law, p. 75.
    • (1927) Political theories of the Middle Ages , pp. 80-90
    • Gierke1
  • 60
    • 84972216018 scopus 로고
    • Some commentators have seen in this an Italian connexion but S. R. Letwin pointedly and, I think, correctly notes that ‘ Hobbes did not need Padua to teach him this commonplace ’ - ‘ Hobbes and Christianity’, Daedalus, winter
    • Some commentators have seen in this an Italian connexion but S. R. Letwin pointedly and, I think, correctly notes that ‘ Hobbes did not need Padua to teach him this commonplace ’ - ‘ Hobbes and Christianity’, Daedalus, winter, 1976, p. 10.
    • (1976) , pp. 10
  • 61
    • 84972414506 scopus 로고
    • Compare, for example the synthetical procedure consists ' of the order of speech which begins from primary or most universal propositions, which are manifest of themselves, and proceeds by a perpetual composition of propositions into syllogisms, till at last the learner understand the truth of the conclusion sought after' with Aquinas, Selected political writings, ed., d'Entrèves (Oxford 123: 'reason proceeds from general principles (which are manifest and indemonstrable) to matters of detail'. Note what appears to be the philosophically realist assumptions of both
    • Compare, for example, Hobbes, E.W.I., p. 81: the synthetical procedure consists ' of the order of speech which begins from primary or most universal propositions, which are manifest of themselves, and proceeds by a perpetual composition of propositions into syllogisms, till at last the learner understand the truth of the conclusion sought after' with Aquinas, Selected political writings, ed., d'Entrèves (Oxford, 1948), p. 123: 'reason proceeds from general principles (which are manifest and indemonstrable) to matters of detail'. Note what appears to be the philosophically realist assumptions of both.
    • (1948) , pp. 81
    • Hobbes, E.W.I.1
  • 62
    • 84969280560 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bk. I, ch. I, 1252a
    • Aristotle, Politics, Bk. I, ch. I, 1252a.
    • Politics
    • Aristotle1
  • 63
    • 84945465246 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 184
    • Hobbes, E.W. vii, 3-4; 184.
    • , vol.7 , pp. 3-4
    • Hobbes, E.W.1
  • 64
    • 0042033639 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also E.W.1, 84
    • Hobbes, E.W. 1, 81; see also E.W.1, 84.
    • , vol.1 , pp. 81
    • Hobbes, E.W.1
  • 65
  • 66
    • 84972414477 scopus 로고
    • Consider the following passage from Hobbes's objection to Descartes: ‘reason gives us no conclusion about the nature of things, but only about the terms that designate them, whether, indeed or not there is a convention (arbitrarily made about their meanings) according to which we join these names together.’ in Descartes, Meditations, in The philosophical works, ed., Haldane and Ross (Cambridge
    • Consider the following passage from Hobbes's objection to Descartes: ‘reason gives us no conclusion about the nature of things, but only about the terms that designate them, whether, indeed or not there is a convention (arbitrarily made about their meanings) according to which we join these names together.’ in Descartes, Meditations, in The philosophical works, ed., Haldane and Ross (Cambridge, 1911), 11, 62.
    • (1911) , vol.11 , pp. 62
  • 69
    • 84972403347 scopus 로고
    • Rational action as teleologically appropriate is sometimes referred to as the doctrine of naturalis inclinatio. See Armstrong, R. A., Primary and secondary precepts in Thomistic natural law teaching (The Hague, 1966), pp. 41–2 and Maritain, J., The range of reason (London
    • Rational action as teleologically appropriate is sometimes referred to as the doctrine of naturalis inclinatio. See Armstrong, R. A., Primary and secondary precepts in Thomistic natural law teaching (The Hague, 1966), pp. 41–2 and Maritain, J., The range of reason (London, 1953), pp. 26–9.
    • (1953) , pp. 26-29
  • 70
    • 84875328384 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See the names of virtues and vices… can never by true ground of any ratiocination
    • See Leviathan, p. 40: ‘… the names of virtues and vices… can never by true ground of any ratiocination’.
    • Leviathan , pp. 40
  • 73
    • 0038986820 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is the point of Rommcn's
    • This is the point of Rommcn's, The natural law.
    • The natural law


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.