-
1
-
-
84972213772
-
-
On the concept of ‘revolution’ in this context, see J. Pocock, Politics, language and time: essays on political thought and history (New York
-
On the concept of ‘revolution’ in this context, see J. Pocock, Politics, language and time: essays on political thought and history (New York, 1973). p. 3.
-
(1973)
, pp. 3
-
-
-
2
-
-
77954116608
-
Hobbes's Leviathan
-
Q. Skinner, ‘Hobbes's Leviathan’, Historical Journal, Vii, 2 (1976), 333.
-
(1976)
Historical Journal
, vol.7
, Issue.2
, pp. 333
-
-
Skinner, Q.1
-
3
-
-
0039403925
-
The context of Hobbes's theory of political obligation', in Cranston and Peters
-
New York Skinner does not explain what is involved in the distinction between 'deontological' and 'rationalist-utilitarian' but it seems clear that he takes them to be mutually exclusive
-
Q. Skinner, 'The context of Hobbes's theory of political obligation', in Cranston and Peters, Hobbes and Rousseau (New York, 1972), p. 141. Skinner does not explain what is involved in the distinction between 'deontological' and 'rationalist-utilitarian' but it seems clear that he takes them to be mutually exclusive.
-
(1972)
Hobbes and Rousseau
, pp. 141
-
-
Skinner, Q.1
-
4
-
-
0003771927
-
Natural rights theories: their origin and development
-
Cambridge
-
R. Tuck, Natural rights theories: their origin and development, (Cambridge, 1979), p. 102.
-
(1979)
, pp. 102
-
-
Tuck, R.1
-
5
-
-
84972262752
-
A discourse: wherein it is examined what is particularly lawful during the confusions and revolutions of governments
-
London preface
-
Anthony Ascham, A discourse: wherein it is examined what is particularly lawful during the confusions and revolutions of governments (London 1648). preface.
-
(1648)
-
-
Anthony Ascham1
-
6
-
-
85055358610
-
Context
-
Skinner, ‘Context’, p. 131.
-
-
-
Skinner1
-
7
-
-
85055358610
-
Context
-
Skinner, ‘Context’, p. 131.
-
-
-
Skinner1
-
8
-
-
84971912970
-
Discourse
-
Ascham, Discourse, p. 98.
-
-
-
Ascham1
-
9
-
-
84971912970
-
Discourse
-
Ascham, Discourse, p. 23.
-
-
-
Ascham1
-
10
-
-
62249204155
-
Natural rights
-
Tuck, Natural rights, pp. 121–123.
-
-
-
Tuck1
-
11
-
-
80054336393
-
The case of the commonwealth of England
-
London
-
Marchamont Nedham, The case of the commonwealth of England (London, 1650).
-
(1650)
-
-
Marchamont Nedham1
-
12
-
-
85055358610
-
Context
-
Skinner, ‘Context’, p. 135.
-
-
-
Skinner1
-
13
-
-
84900930811
-
Case of the commonwealth
-
Nedham, Case of the commonwealth, p. 103.
-
-
-
Nedham1
-
14
-
-
0039398856
-
The ideological context of Hobbes's political thought
-
Skinner, ‘The ideological context of Hobbes's political thought’, Historical Journal, 9, 3 (1966), 292.
-
(1966)
Historical Journal
, vol.9
, Issue.3
, pp. 292
-
-
Skinner1
-
15
-
-
33745305053
-
Table talk
-
(London
-
John Selden, Table talk (London, 1689), p. 30.
-
(1689)
, pp. 30
-
-
Selden, J.1
-
16
-
-
84972196815
-
A possible exception is Matthew Wren's
-
Monarchy asserted of 1659. But even if we take Wren to be the only true Hobbist with the correct line on Hobbes - we are then faced with the problem of the other so-called Hobbists. If ‘history’ gives us conflicting evidence with regard to interpretation - we must in the end rely on our own interpretation
-
A possible exception is Matthew Wren's Monarchy asserted of 1659. But even if we take Wren to be the only true Hobbist with the correct line on Hobbes - we are then faced with the problem of the other so-called Hobbists. If ‘history’ gives us conflicting evidence with regard to interpretation - we must in the end rely on our own interpretation.
-
-
-
-
17
-
-
84972131358
-
A persuasive to a mutual compliance
-
Oxford 1652 [1651
-
Francis Osborne, A persuasive to a mutual compliance (Oxford, 1652 [1651 ?]) p. 10.
-
-
-
Francis Osborne1
-
18
-
-
84972131345
-
Eight reasons categorical
-
London
-
Albertus Warren, Eight reasons categorical (London, 1653), p. 5.
-
(1653)
, pp. 5
-
-
Albertus Warren1
-
19
-
-
84972281765
-
The royalist reformed
-
London
-
Albertus Warren, The royalist reformed (London, 1650), p. 26.
-
(1650)
, pp. 26
-
-
Albertus Warren1
-
20
-
-
84972281746
-
The grounds of the laws of England
-
London dedication
-
Michael Hawke, The grounds of the laws of England (London, 1657), dedication.
-
(1657)
-
-
Michael Hawke1
-
21
-
-
80052728255
-
Killing is murder and no murder
-
London
-
Michael Hawke, Killing is murder and no murder (London, 1657), p. 7.
-
(1657)
, pp. 7
-
-
Michael Hawke1
-
22
-
-
84972196793
-
The right of dominion
-
London
-
Michael Hawke, The right of dominion (London, 1655), p. 22.
-
(1655)
, pp. 22
-
-
Michael Hawke1
-
23
-
-
84972398409
-
The grounds of obedience and government
-
no place of publication given
-
Thomas White, The grounds of obedience and government (no place of publication given, 165[9]), p. 44.
-
, vol.165
, Issue.9
, pp. 44
-
-
Thomas White1
-
24
-
-
84972173892
-
Of obedience and government
-
London preface
-
John Hall, Of obedience and government (London, 1654), preface.
-
(1654)
-
-
John Hall1
-
25
-
-
84972250844
-
Euctatus Philodemius
-
London J. W. Packer (The transformation of Anglicanism, Manchester, 1969, p. 178) suggests that Philodemius is the pseudonym for Anthony Ascham although, despite a search for which I am grateful, he has been unable to locate the evidence for this suggestion; nor have I
-
Euctatus Philodemius, The original and end of civil power (London, 1649), p. 15. J. W. Packer (The transformation of Anglicanism, Manchester, 1969, p. 178) suggests that Philodemius is the pseudonym for Anthony Ascham although, despite a search for which I am grateful, he has been unable to locate the evidence for this suggestion; nor have I.
-
(1649)
The original and end of civil power
, pp. 15
-
-
-
26
-
-
62249204155
-
Natural rights
-
84 Selden, Table talk, p. 41
-
Tuck, Natural rights, p. 82. 84 Selden, Table talk, p. 41.
-
-
-
Tuck1
-
27
-
-
84972220569
-
Although the Tew writers
-
didn't publish until the 1640s and so could have been influenced by Hobbes, Selden's published work predates that of Hobbes. Strictly speaking, the discussion of influence remains - as in most cases - speculative; we don't know much of what Hobbes was thinking prior to 1628. People can be influential without ever publishing at all
-
Although the Tew writers didn't publish until the 1640s and so could have been influenced by Hobbes, Selden's published work predates that of Hobbes. Strictly speaking, the discussion of influence remains - as in most cases - speculative; we don't know much of what Hobbes was thinking prior to 1628. People can be influential without ever publishing at all.
-
-
-
-
28
-
-
62249204155
-
Natural rights
-
ch. 5
-
Tuck, Natural rights, ch. 5.
-
-
-
Tuck1
-
31
-
-
84972478522
-
-
Tuck is misleading to suggest that Warrender found the basis of natural law in God's will; this is but one of the possibilities Warrender entertains as the ultimate ground of obligation. See Warrender ch. 13. 90 Tuck, Natural rights, p. 131
-
Tuck is misleading to suggest that Warrender found the basis of natural law in God's will; this is but one of the possibilities Warrender entertains as the ultimate ground of obligation. See Warrender, The political theory of Hobbes, p. 11 and ch. 13. 90 Tuck, Natural rights, p. 131.
-
The political theory of Hobbes
, pp. 11
-
-
-
34
-
-
84972196895
-
-
Molesworth (London Emphasis in original.) E.W. iv xiii
-
Hobbes. The English works of Thomas Hobbes, ed., Molesworth (London, 1889), 1. (Emphasis in original.) E.W. iv xiii.
-
(1889)
The English works of Thomas Hobbes
, vol.1
-
-
Hobbes1
-
37
-
-
84972131372
-
review of Warrender's The political philosophy of Hobbes
-
Dowling, R. E., review of Warrender's The political philosophy of Hobbes, Australasian Journal of Politics, 1958, p. 226.
-
(1958)
Australasian Journal of Politics
, pp. 226
-
-
Dowling, R.E.1
-
41
-
-
84972368471
-
Hobbes is not a wolf in sheep's clothing although he may be a wolf in wolf's clothing
-
By announcing his departures from earlier theorists and proclaiming his novelties of method and argument he can hardly be said to be engaged in concealment. His treatment of the role of God is discussed below
-
Hobbes is not a wolf in sheep's clothing although he may be a wolf in wolf's clothing. By announcing his departures from earlier theorists and proclaiming his novelties of method and argument he can hardly be said to be engaged in concealment. His treatment of the role of God is discussed below.
-
-
-
-
44
-
-
84972315026
-
-
Works, ed Keble, rev. Church and Paget, 7th edition (Oxford
-
Hooker, R., Works, ed., Keble, rev. Church and Paget, 7th edition (Oxford, 1889), 1, 334.
-
(1889)
, vol.1
, pp. 334
-
-
Hooker, R.1
-
46
-
-
84972266786
-
-
Oxford
-
Suarez, F., Selectionsfor three works, in Classics of International Law, Oxford 1927), vol. 20, p. 197.
-
(1927)
Selectionsfor three works, in Classics of International Law
, vol.20
, pp. 197
-
-
Suarez, F.1
-
47
-
-
84972266816
-
Perhaps because of this famous passage scholars
-
disagree about Grotius's position in the history of political thought. d'Entrèves sees him as the beginning of ‘rationalist’ hence secular modern natural law (. Natural law, 2nd edition (London, 1970), p. 55). Pollock (postscript to Sir H. Maine, Ancient law, (London 1930), p. 120) and Rommen (The natural law, trans. T. Hanley (St. Louis, 1949), p. 70) emphasize links to earlier Scholastic thought as does A. H. Chroust (‘ Hugo Grotius and the Scholastic natural law tradition’, The New Scholasticism, xvn, 1943, p. 125). The latter explains this passage as a rationalist rebuke of voluntarism and nominalism while Rommen (p. 72) sees Grotius as an exponent of voluntarism
-
Perhaps because of this famous passage scholars disagree about Grotius's position in the history of political thought. d'Entrèves sees him as the beginning of ‘rationalist’ hence secular modern natural law (.Natural law, 2nd edition (London, 1970), p. 55). Pollock (postscript to Sir H. Maine, Ancient law, (London 1930), p. 120) and Rommen (The natural law, trans. T. Hanley (St. Louis, 1949), p. 70) emphasize links to earlier Scholastic thought as does A. H. Chroust (‘ Hugo Grotius and the Scholastic natural law tradition’, The New Scholasticism, xvn, 1943, p. 125). The latter explains this passage as a rationalist rebuke of voluntarism and nominalism while Rommen (p. 72) sees Grotius as an exponent of voluntarism.
-
-
-
-
48
-
-
84972266780
-
perceptively treated in Largarde
-
This issue is See also J. T. McNeill, ‘Natural law in the teaching of the reformers’, The Journal of Religion, xxvi (1946), 177–8; J. W. Allen, ‘The political conceptions of Luther’, in Tudor Studies, ed., Seton-Watson (London, 1924), p. 101
-
This issue is perceptively treated in Largarde, Recherches, p. 25. See also J. T. McNeill, ‘Natural law in the teaching of the reformers’, The Journal of Religion, xxvi (1946), 177–8; J. W. Allen, ‘The political conceptions of Luther’, in Tudor Studies, ed., Seton-Watson (London, 1924), p. 101.
-
Recherches
, pp. 25
-
-
-
50
-
-
24444434256
-
-
2nd edition (Harmondsworth
-
Peters, R., Hobbes, 2nd edition (Harmondsworth, 1967) p. 245.
-
(1967)
Hobbes
, pp. 245
-
-
Peters, R.1
-
52
-
-
84972216025
-
Hugo Grotius
-
Chroust, ‘Hugo Grotius’, p. 114.
-
-
-
Chroust1
-
54
-
-
84972264854
-
-
No case is made here to establish links between Suarez and Hobbes. Hobbes had, of course, read at least some of Suarez's work and described it as ‘amongst the many sorts of madness’. England generally was also familiar with him since James I publicly burnt his treatise Defensio Fidei in front of St Paul's church in London. See J. B. Scott's introduction to Suarez xx, 20a
-
No case is made here to establish links between Suarez and Hobbes. Hobbes had, of course, read at least some of Suarez's work and described it as ‘amongst the many sorts of madness’. England generally was also familiar with him since James I publicly burnt his treatise Defensio Fidei in front of St Paul's church in London. See J. B. Scott's introduction to Suarez, Selections, in Classics, xx, 20a.
-
Selections, in Classics
-
-
-
57
-
-
84965792310
-
-
ch. 2, par. 5: 'if I cannot but wish to receive good… how should I look to have any part of my desire herein satisfied unless myself be careful to satisfy the like desire, which is undoubtedly in other men, being of one and the same nature?… from which relation of equality… what several rules and canons natural reason hath drawn, for direction of life, no man is ignorant
-
Locke, Second treatise, ch. 2, par. 5: 'if I cannot but wish to receive good… how should I look to have any part of my desire herein satisfied unless myself be careful to satisfy the like desire, which is undoubtedly in other men, being of one and the same nature?… from which relation of equality… what several rules and canons natural reason hath drawn, for direction of life, no man is ignorant. '
-
Second treatise
-
-
Locke1
-
59
-
-
0004085243
-
-
Cambridge Natural law, p. 40; see also Rommen, The natural law, p. 75
-
Gierke, Political theories of the Middle Ages (Cambridge, 1927), p. 80-90; Natural law, p. 40; see also Rommen, The natural law, p. 75.
-
(1927)
Political theories of the Middle Ages
, pp. 80-90
-
-
Gierke1
-
60
-
-
84972216018
-
-
Some commentators have seen in this an Italian connexion but S. R. Letwin pointedly and, I think, correctly notes that ‘ Hobbes did not need Padua to teach him this commonplace ’ - ‘ Hobbes and Christianity’, Daedalus, winter
-
Some commentators have seen in this an Italian connexion but S. R. Letwin pointedly and, I think, correctly notes that ‘ Hobbes did not need Padua to teach him this commonplace ’ - ‘ Hobbes and Christianity’, Daedalus, winter, 1976, p. 10.
-
(1976)
, pp. 10
-
-
-
61
-
-
84972414506
-
-
Compare, for example the synthetical procedure consists ' of the order of speech which begins from primary or most universal propositions, which are manifest of themselves, and proceeds by a perpetual composition of propositions into syllogisms, till at last the learner understand the truth of the conclusion sought after' with Aquinas, Selected political writings, ed., d'Entrèves (Oxford 123: 'reason proceeds from general principles (which are manifest and indemonstrable) to matters of detail'. Note what appears to be the philosophically realist assumptions of both
-
Compare, for example, Hobbes, E.W.I., p. 81: the synthetical procedure consists ' of the order of speech which begins from primary or most universal propositions, which are manifest of themselves, and proceeds by a perpetual composition of propositions into syllogisms, till at last the learner understand the truth of the conclusion sought after' with Aquinas, Selected political writings, ed., d'Entrèves (Oxford, 1948), p. 123: 'reason proceeds from general principles (which are manifest and indemonstrable) to matters of detail'. Note what appears to be the philosophically realist assumptions of both.
-
(1948)
, pp. 81
-
-
Hobbes, E.W.I.1
-
62
-
-
84969280560
-
-
Bk. I, ch. I, 1252a
-
Aristotle, Politics, Bk. I, ch. I, 1252a.
-
Politics
-
-
Aristotle1
-
63
-
-
84945465246
-
-
184
-
Hobbes, E.W. vii, 3-4; 184.
-
, vol.7
, pp. 3-4
-
-
Hobbes, E.W.1
-
64
-
-
0042033639
-
-
see also E.W.1, 84
-
Hobbes, E.W. 1, 81; see also E.W.1, 84.
-
, vol.1
, pp. 81
-
-
Hobbes, E.W.1
-
66
-
-
84972414477
-
-
Consider the following passage from Hobbes's objection to Descartes: ‘reason gives us no conclusion about the nature of things, but only about the terms that designate them, whether, indeed or not there is a convention (arbitrarily made about their meanings) according to which we join these names together.’ in Descartes, Meditations, in The philosophical works, ed., Haldane and Ross (Cambridge
-
Consider the following passage from Hobbes's objection to Descartes: ‘reason gives us no conclusion about the nature of things, but only about the terms that designate them, whether, indeed or not there is a convention (arbitrarily made about their meanings) according to which we join these names together.’ in Descartes, Meditations, in The philosophical works, ed., Haldane and Ross (Cambridge, 1911), 11, 62.
-
(1911)
, vol.11
, pp. 62
-
-
-
69
-
-
84972403347
-
-
Rational action as teleologically appropriate is sometimes referred to as the doctrine of naturalis inclinatio. See Armstrong, R. A., Primary and secondary precepts in Thomistic natural law teaching (The Hague, 1966), pp. 41–2 and Maritain, J., The range of reason (London
-
Rational action as teleologically appropriate is sometimes referred to as the doctrine of naturalis inclinatio. See Armstrong, R. A., Primary and secondary precepts in Thomistic natural law teaching (The Hague, 1966), pp. 41–2 and Maritain, J., The range of reason (London, 1953), pp. 26–9.
-
(1953)
, pp. 26-29
-
-
-
70
-
-
84875328384
-
-
See the names of virtues and vices… can never by true ground of any ratiocination
-
See Leviathan, p. 40: ‘… the names of virtues and vices… can never by true ground of any ratiocination’.
-
Leviathan
, pp. 40
-
-
-
73
-
-
0038986820
-
-
This is the point of Rommcn's
-
This is the point of Rommcn's, The natural law.
-
The natural law
-
-
|