메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 11, Issue 2, 1992, Pages 6-20

First Amendment Challenges to Hate Crime Legislation: Where’s the Speech?

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 84953494356     PISSN: 0731129X     EISSN: 19375948     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1080/0731129X.1992.9991917     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (48)

References (72)
  • 1
    • 0001007312 scopus 로고
    • Sticks and Stones Can Put You in fail, But Can Words Increase Your Sentence? Constitutional and Policy Dilemmas of Ethnic Intimidation Laws
    • Gellman, Sticks and Stones Can Put You in fail, But Can Words Increase Your Sentence? Constitutional and Policy Dilemmas of Ethnic Intimidation Laws, 39 Ucla L. Rev. 333 (1991).
    • (1991) Ucla L. Rev , vol.39 , pp. 333
    • Gellman1
  • 2
    • 84953540651 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id. at 344.
  • 3
    • 77957682222 scopus 로고
    • One of the ordinances used in the attempt to bar members of the American Nazi Party from marching in Skokie, Illinois. See, 578 F.2d 1197, 1199
    • One of the ordinances used in the attempt to bar members of the American Nazi Party from marching in Skokie, Illinois. See Collin v. Smith, 578 F.2d 1197, 1199 (1978).
    • (1978) Collin v. Smith
  • 4
    • 78149353074 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • While we have rejected the view that an apparently limitless variety of conduct can be labeled “speech” whenever the person engaging in the conduct intends thereby to express an idea, we have acknowledged that conduct may be sufficiently imbued with elements of communication to fall within the scope of the [First Amendment]. In deciding whether particular conduct possesses sufficient communicative elements to bring the First Amendment into play, we have asked whether an intent to convey a particularized message was present, and whether the likelihood was great that the message would be understood by those who viewed it., 491 U.S. 397, 404, (internal quotation marks and citations omitted)
    • While we have rejected the view that an apparently limitless variety of conduct can be labeled “speech” whenever the person engaging in the conduct intends thereby to express an idea, we have acknowledged that conduct may be sufficiently imbued with elements of communication to fall within the scope of the [First Amendment]. In deciding whether particular conduct possesses sufficient communicative elements to bring the First Amendment into play, we have asked whether an intent to convey a particularized message was present, and whether the likelihood was great that the message would be understood by those who viewed it. Texas v. Johnson, 491 U.S. 397, 404 (1989) (internal quotation marks and citations omitted)
    • (1989) Texas v. Johnson
  • 5
    • 84953456384 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also, 485 N.W.2d. at 814 n.15 (activity covered by hate crime legislation is not “expressive conduct” protected by the First Amendment).
    • see also Wisconsin v. Mitchell, 485 N.W.2d. at 814 n.15 (activity covered by hate crime legislation is not “expressive conduct” protected by the First Amendment).
    • Wisconsin v. Mitchell
  • 8
    • 78149353074 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 491 U.S. 397
    • Texas v. Johnson, 491 U.S. 397 (1989).
    • (1989) Texas v. Johnson
  • 9
    • 84953540652 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1, at, emphasis added), quoted in Mitchell, 485 N.W.2d at 812.
    • Gellman, supra note 1, at 363 (emphasis added), quoted in Mitchell, 485 N.W.2d at 812.
    • Gellman1
  • 10
    • 84953540653 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1, at, After this article was prepared, the Supreme Court of Ohio held a law similar to the ADL model to be unconstitutional.
    • Gellman, supra note 1, at 362. After this article was prepared, the Supreme Court of Ohio held a law similar to the ADL model to be unconstitutional.
    • Gellman1
  • 11
    • 84953458567 scopus 로고
    • See, 64 Ohio St. 3d 566, The Ohio Court’s rationale for invalidating the law was the same as that adopted by the Wisconsin Court—namely, that by enhancing a penalty due to the motive of the defendant the statute creates a “thought crime” in violation ofthe First Amendment.
    • See State v. Wyant, 64 Ohio St. 3d 566 (1992). The Ohio Court’s rationale for invalidating the law was the same as that adopted by the Wisconsin Court—namely, that by enhancing a penalty due to the motive of the defendant the statute creates a “thought crime” in violation ofthe First Amendment.
    • (1992) State v. Wyant
  • 12
    • 26444504270 scopus 로고
    • Motive and Criminal Liability
    • Winter/Spring
    • Husak, Motive and Criminal Liability, CRIM. JUST. ETHICS (Winter/Spring 1989), at 3.
    • (1989) CRIM. JUST. ETHICS , pp. 3
    • Husak1
  • 13
    • 84953540654 scopus 로고
    • 112 S.Ct.
    • 112 S.Ct. 1093 (1992).
    • (1992) , pp. 1093
  • 14
    • 84953540655 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id. at 1095.
  • 15
    • 84953540656 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id. at 1098.
  • 16
    • 84953540657 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id. at 1097-98.
  • 17
    • 84953540658 scopus 로고
    • relying on, 463 U.S. 939
    • (relying on Barclay v. Florida, 463 U.S. 939 (1983)).
    • (1983) Barclay v. Florida
  • 18
    • 78149353074 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, 491 U.S.
    • See Texas v. Johnson, 491 U.S. at 406-07
    • Texas v. Johnson , pp. 406-407
  • 20
    • 81355128997 scopus 로고
    • Flag Desecration: A Case Study in the Roles of Categorization and Balancing in First Amendment Analysis
    • I want to also emphasize that I am invoking the expressive conduct test only as an analogy, and am in no way suggesting that racial violence would qualify as expressive conduct under Supreme Court precedent. Even the most expressive form or racial violence—for instance, a beating that is intended to and does convey a particular message to its victim (e.g., don’t come into this neighborhood again) is much further removed from the realm of legitimate public discourse than is the typically symbolic conduct qualifying as expressive conduct (e.g., draft card burning and flag desecration). Thus while it may be appropriate to borrow the step from the expressive conduct cases by which it is determined whether the regulation is aimed at the expressive element of the conduct, it would be singularly inappropriate to apply the remainder of the test to hate crime legislation. Under this test, even if the government shows an interest unrelated to the suppression of speech, this interest is (theoretically at least) balanced against the expressive interests of the person wishing to engage in the conduct. (I say theoretically, because this balancing step has in practice been a mere incantation with no speech protective bite. See
    • I want to also emphasize that I am invoking the expressive conduct test only as an analogy, and am in no way suggesting that racial violence would qualify as expressive conduct under Supreme Court precedent. Even the most expressive form or racial violence—for instance, a beating that is intended to and does convey a particular message to its victim (e.g., don’t come into this neighborhood again) is much further removed from the realm of legitimate public discourse than is the typically symbolic conduct qualifying as expressive conduct (e.g., draft card burning and flag desecration). Thus while it may be appropriate to borrow the step from the expressive conduct cases by which it is determined whether the regulation is aimed at the expressive element of the conduct, it would be singularly inappropriate to apply the remainder of the test to hate crime legislation. Under this test, even if the government shows an interest unrelated to the suppression of speech, this interest is (theoretically at least) balanced against the expressive interests of the person wishing to engage in the conduct. (I say theoretically, because this balancing step has in practice been a mere incantation with no speech protective bite. See Ely, Flag Desecration: A Case Study in the Roles of Categorization and Balancing in First Amendment Analysis, 88 Harv. L. Rev. 1482 (1975)
    • (1975) Harv. L. Rev , vol.88 , pp. 1482
    • Ely1
  • 21
    • 79751507249 scopus 로고
    • Inc., 111 S. Ct., Thus even though the United States might have had a speechneutral reason relating to the efficient administration of the draft for forbidding draftcard burning, the draft card burner’s interest in effective expression was weighed against this interest (and, erroneously I believe, found wanting).
    • Barnes v. Glen Theatre, Inc., 111 S. Ct. 2456 (1991)). Thus even though the United States might have had a speechneutral reason relating to the efficient administration of the draft for forbidding draftcard burning, the draft card burner’s interest in effective expression was weighed against this interest (and, erroneously I believe, found wanting).
    • (1991) Barnes v. Glen Theatre , pp. 2456
  • 22
    • 77951918378 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, 391 U.S. at, The potential for making a weak government interest giveway to a person’s interest in symbolic expression, long an important and legitimate formof public discourse, may well be appropriate. Any message conveyed by violence, however, is another matter. Thus if the state can point to interests for enhancing the penaltyforracially motivated crimes that are unrelated to the punishment of abstract beliefs, as Iwill argue that it can, it would be inappropriate to weigh this interest against the expressive interests in engaging in racial violence.
    • See United States v. O’Brien, 391 U.S. at 381. The potential for making a weak government interest giveway to a person’s interest in symbolic expression, long an important and legitimate formof public discourse, may well be appropriate. Any message conveyed by violence, however, is another matter. Thus if the state can point to interests for enhancing the penaltyforracially motivated crimes that are unrelated to the punishment of abstract beliefs, as Iwill argue that it can, it would be inappropriate to weigh this interest against the expressive interests in engaging in racial violence.
    • United States v. O’Brien , pp. 381
  • 23
    • 84886946240 scopus 로고
    • A Constitutional Roadmap to the Regulation of Campus Hate Speech
    • See, 163
    • See Weinstein, A Constitutional Roadmap to the Regulation of Campus Hate Speech, 38 Wayne L. Rev. 163, 164-90 (1991).
    • (1991) Wayne L. Rev , vol.38 , pp. 164-190
    • Weinstein1
  • 25
    • 0002368255 scopus 로고
    • The Moral Worth of Retribution
    • F. Schoeman ed., Indeed, in some contexts a retributivist ceiling—the concept that a defendant should not be punished in excess of his blameworthiness—is constitutionally required.
    • Moore, The Moral Worth of Retribution, in Responsibility, Character And The Emotions 179-219 (F. Schoeman ed. 1987). Indeed, in some contexts a retributivist ceiling—the concept that a defendant should not be punished in excess of his blameworthiness—is constitutionally required.
    • (1987) Responsibility, Character And The Emotions , pp. 179-219
    • Moore1
  • 26
    • 79961220613 scopus 로고
    • See, 433 U.S. 584, 597-98, (in finding imposition of death penalty for rape of adult women to be “disproportionate punishment” in violation of the Eighth Amendment prohibition of cruel or unusual punishment, Court relies in part upon its judgment that rape is not comparable to murder “in terms of moral depravity”).
    • See Coker v. Georgia, 433 U.S. 584, 597-98 (1977) (in finding imposition of death penalty for rape of adult women to be “disproportionate punishment” in violation of the Eighth Amendment prohibition of cruel or unusual punishment, Court relies in part upon its judgment that rape is not comparable to murder “in terms of moral depravity”).
    • (1977) Coker v. Georgia
  • 28
    • 0004194369 scopus 로고
    • Hart coined this term to describe Lord Patrick Devlin’s position in his, that moral norms can legitimately be enforced regardless of their objective validity to protect the glue that binds the community—a position with which Hart disagrees.
    • Hart coined this term to describe Lord Patrick Devlin’s position in his The Enforcement Of Morals (1959) that moral norms can legitimately be enforced regardless of their objective validity to protect the glue that binds the community—a position with which Hart disagrees.
    • (1959) The Enforcement Of Morals
  • 30
    • 72649092102 scopus 로고
    • 478 U.S. 186, 196
    • Bowers v. Hardwick, 478 U.S. 186, 196 (1986)
    • (1986) Bowers v. Hardwick
  • 31
    • 79751507249 scopus 로고
    • see also, 111 S.Ct. 2456, 2462, (opinion of Rehnquist CJ., joined by O’Connor and Kennedy, J.J.)
    • see also Barnes v. Glen Theater, 111 S.Ct. 2456, 2462 (1991) (opinion of Rehnquist CJ., joined by O’Connor and Kennedy, J.J.)
    • (1991) Barnes v. Glen Theater
  • 32
    • 84953540659 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id., (opinion of Scalia, J.).
    • Id. at 2467-68 (opinion of Scalia, J.).
  • 33
    • 84953540660 scopus 로고
    • Thus in Paris Adult Theater the Court was dealing with obscenity, which it had long ago held to be outside the protection of the First Amendment. See, 354 U.S. 476, Similarly in Bowers the Court held that there was no fundamental right to engage in homosexual sodomy.
    • Thus in Paris Adult Theater the Court was dealing with obscenity, which it had long ago held to be outside the protection of the First Amendment. See Roth v. United States, 354 U.S. 476, 480 (1957). Similarly in Bowers the Court held that there was no fundamental right to engage in homosexual sodomy.
    • (1957) Roth v. United States , pp. 480
  • 34
    • 84953540661 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In, however, Chief Justice Rehnquisf s plurality opinion did find the societal interest in maintaining morality sufficient grounds to outlaw nude dancing, which Rehnquist acknowledged qualified as expressive conduct, 111 S.Ct. at
    • In Barnes, however, Chief Justice Rehnquisf s plurality opinion did find the societal interest in maintaining morality sufficient grounds to outlaw nude dancing, which Rehnquist acknowledged qualified as expressive conduct “within the outer perimeters of the First Amendment, though… only marginally so” (111 S.Ct. at 2460)
    • within the outer perimeters of the First Amendment, though… only marginally so , pp. 2460
    • Barnes1
  • 35
    • 79961220613 scopus 로고
    • 433 U.S. 584, 598
    • Coker v. Georgia, 433 U.S. 584, 598 (1977).
    • (1977) Coker v. Georgia
  • 36
    • 84953468788 scopus 로고
    • For more on the subject of the First Amendment implications of punishing threats, see
    • For more on the subject of the First Amendment implications of punishing threats, see K. Greenawalt, Speech, Crime, And The Uses Of Language 90-109 (1989).
    • (1989) Speech, Crime, And The Uses Of Language , pp. 90-109
    • Greenawalt, K.1
  • 37
    • 84953540662 scopus 로고
    • See R.A.V. v. City of St. Paul, 112 S.Ct., is speech protected by the First Amendment).
    • See R.A.V. v. City of St. Paul, 112 S.Ct. 2538, 2548 (1992) (“messages based on virulent notions of racial supremacy” is speech protected by the First Amendment).
    • (1992) messages based on virulent notions of racial supremacy , pp. 2538-2548
  • 38
    • 77950496257 scopus 로고
    • See, 395 U.S. 444, 447
    • See Brandenburg v. Ohio, 395 U.S. 444, 447 (1969).
    • (1969) Brandenburg v. Ohio
  • 39
    • 84953540663 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, supra note 20 at
    • See Weinstein, supra note 20 at 176-80.
    • Weinstein1
  • 40
    • 79953870302 scopus 로고
    • See generally, 485 U.S. 46, 55, (First Amendment forbids recovery by public figure for intentional infliction of emotional distress caused by publication, unless public figure can also show that the publication contains a false statement of fact made with knowledge of its falsity or reckless disregard as to whether or not it was true.)
    • See generally Hustler Magazine v. Falwell, 485 U.S. 46, 55 (1988) (First Amendment forbids recovery by public figure for intentional infliction of emotional distress caused by publication, unless public figure can also show that the publication contains a false statement of fact made with knowledge of its falsity or reckless disregard as to whether or not it was true.)
    • (1988) Hustler Magazine v. Falwell
  • 41
    • 84953468001 scopus 로고
    • The Constitutional Concept of Public Discourse: Outrageous Opinion, Democratic Deliberation, and Hustler Magazine v. Falwell
    • Professor Robert Post makes this point well in his insightful article, 603
    • Professor Robert Post makes this point well in his insightful article The Constitutional Concept of Public Discourse: Outrageous Opinion, Democratic Deliberation, and Hustler Magazine v. Falwell, 103 Harv. L. Rev. 603, 662-63 (1990).
    • (1990) Harv. L. Rev , vol.103 , pp. 662-663
  • 42
    • 84953580029 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 112 S.Ct. 2538.
    • 112 S.Ct , pp. 2538
  • 43
    • 84953540664 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id. at 2541-42.
  • 44
    • 84953540665 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id. at 2547.
  • 45
    • 84953540666 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id. at 2543.
  • 46
    • 84953540667 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id., The Court acknowledges that government has more leeway to make content-based distinctions “in the context of proscribable speech than in the area of fully protected speech.
    • Id. at 2545-47. The Court acknowledges that government has more leeway to make content-based distinctions “in the context of proscribable speech than in the area of fully protected speech.
  • 47
    • 84953540668 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id., By way of example the Court gives two bases that would support singling out a subset of unprotected speech for special prohibition: 1) “When the basis for the content discrimination consists entirely of the very reason the entire class of speech at issue is proscribable,” id.; and 2) “the subclass happens to be associated with particular ’secondary effects’ of the speech so that the regulation is justified without reference to the content of the speech.” Id. at 2546 (emphasis in original; citations and internal quotations omitted). In these situations the selective proscription is consistent with the First Amendment because “no significant danger of idea or viewpoint discrimination exists.
    • Id. at 2545. By way of example the Court gives two bases that would support singling out a subset of unprotected speech for special prohibition: 1) “When the basis for the content discrimination consists entirely of the very reason the entire class of speech at issue is proscribable,” id.; and 2) “the subclass happens to be associated with particular ’secondary effects’ of the speech so that the regulation is justified without reference to the content of the speech.” Id. at 2546 (emphasis in original; citations and internal quotations omitted). In these situations the selective proscription is consistent with the First Amendment because “no significant danger of idea or viewpoint discrimination exists.
  • 48
    • 84953540669 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id., The Court acknowledges that there may be other bases for constitutionally singling out subsets of proscribable speech. “Indeed, to validate such selectivity (where totally proscribable speech is at issue) ie may not even be necessary to identify any particular ‘neutral’ basis, so long as the nature of the content discrimination is such that there is no realistic possibility that official suppression of ideas is afoot.
    • Id. at 2545. The Court acknowledges that there may be other bases for constitutionally singling out subsets of proscribable speech. “Indeed, to validate such selectivity (where totally proscribable speech is at issue) ie may not even be necessary to identify any particular ‘neutral’ basis, so long as the nature of the content discrimination is such that there is no realistic possibility that official suppression of ideas is afoot.
  • 49
    • 84953540670 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id. at 2547.
  • 50
    • 84953540671 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id. at 2548.
  • 52
    • 84953540672 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1, at
    • Gellman, supra note 1, at 368.
    • Gellman1
  • 53
    • 84953474214 scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., 458 U.S. 375, (holding that 42 U.S.C. §1981, which bars racial discrimination in the making of contracts, requires a showing of an intent to discriminate, and suggesting that all other civil rights provisions stemming of the Civil Rights Act of 1866 so require).
    • See, e.g., General Building Contractors Assoc. v. Pennsylvania, 458 U.S. 375 (1982) (holding that 42 U.S.C. §1981, which bars racial discrimination in the making of contracts, requires a showing of an intent to discriminate, and suggesting that all other civil rights provisions stemming of the Civil Rights Act of 1866 so require).
    • (1982) General Building Contractors Assoc. v. Pennsylvania
  • 55
    • 84881923517 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 485 N.W.2d at
    • Mitchell, 485 N.W.2d at 817.
    • Mitchell , pp. 817
  • 56
    • 84953540673 scopus 로고
    • What a State may not constitutionally bring about by means of a criminal statute is likewise beyond the reach of its civil law.
    • 376 U.S.
    • “What a State may not constitutionally bring about by means of a criminal statute is likewise beyond the reach of its civil law….” New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254, 277 (1964)
    • (1964) New York Times Co. v. Sullivan , pp. 254-277
  • 57
    • 84953540674 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 485 N.W.2d at, (Title VII and similar antidiscrimination statues make “slight incursions into free speech.”)
    • Mitchell, 485 N.W.2d at 817 (Title VII and similar antidiscrimination statues make “slight incursions into free speech.”)
    • Mitchell1
  • 59
    • 84953540676 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id. at 615.
  • 60
    • 84881923517 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 485 N.W.2d at
    • Mitchell, 485 N.W.2d at 815-16
    • Mitchell , pp. 815-816
  • 61
    • 84953540677 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • accord, supra note 1, at
    • accord Gellman, supra note 1, at 358-62.
    • Gellman1
  • 62
    • 67649092644 scopus 로고
    • It could be argued that epithets used during a fight do not, ironically, qualify as “fighting words” because the use of even the most insulting language could not possibly lead to a fight now that violence has already broken out. But the avoidance of violence is only one of the rationales that the Court gave in finding face-to-face insults to be without First Amendment protection, the other being the prevention of emotional injury. See, 315 U.S. 568, 572
    • It could be argued that epithets used during a fight do not, ironically, qualify as “fighting words” because the use of even the most insulting language could not possibly lead to a fight now that violence has already broken out. But the avoidance of violence is only one of the rationales that the Court gave in finding face-to-face insults to be without First Amendment protection, the other being the prevention of emotional injury. See Chaplinsky, v. New Hampshire, 315 U.S. 568, 572 (1942).
    • (1942) Chaplinsky, v. New Hampshire
  • 63
    • 84953540678 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For more on the rationale and scope of the fighting words doctrine, see, supra note 20, at, and sources cited therein.
    • For more on the rationale and scope of the fighting words doctrine, see Weinstein, supra note 20, at 185-87 and sources cited therein.
    • Weinstein1
  • 65
    • 84455201030 scopus 로고
    • The First Amendment problem of using evidence of a person’s expression, beliefs, or associations is not limited to hate crime prosecutions. In addition to the Dawsoncase discussed in the text accompanying notes 13 to 17, supra, see, 469 U.S. 45, (membership in Aryan Brotherhood whose members had sworn to lie for each other used to impeachment defense witness in criminal prosecution)
    • The First Amendment problem of using evidence of a person’s expression, beliefs, or associations is not limited to hate crime prosecutions. In addition to the Dawsoncase discussed in the text accompanying notes 13 to 17, supra, see United States v. Abel, 469 U.S. 45 (1984) (membership in Aryan Brotherhood whose members had sworn to lie for each other used to impeachment defense witness in criminal prosecution)
    • (1984) United States v. Abel
  • 66
    • 73049098066 scopus 로고
    • 597 F.2d 1170, 9th Cir.
    • United States v. Giese, 597 F.2d 1170 (9th Cir. 1979)
    • (1979) United States v. Giese
  • 67
    • 84953540679 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • in prosecution for bombing of army recruiting center, book entitled, which contained fingerprints of the defendant and three co-conspirators, used as physical evidence corroborating association among defendants).
    • (in prosecution for bombing of army recruiting center, book entitled From The Movement Toward Revolution, which contained fingerprints of the defendant and three co-conspirators, used as physical evidence corroborating association among defendants).
    • From The Movement Toward Revolution
  • 70
    • 77951970422 scopus 로고
    • Toward First Amendment Limitations on the Introduction of Evidence: The Problem of United States v. Rosenberg
    • Quint, Toward First Amendment Limitations on the Introduction of Evidence: The Problem of United States v. Rosenberg, 86 Yale L.J. 1622 (1977)
    • (1977) Yale L.J , vol.86 , pp. 1622
    • Quint1
  • 71
    • 84953540681 scopus 로고
    • The Statutory and Constitutional Limits of Using Protected Speech as Evidence of Unlawful Motive Under the National Labor Relations Act
    • White
    • White, The Statutory and Constitutional Limits of Using Protected Speech as Evidence of Unlawful Motive Under the National Labor Relations Act, 53 Ohio St. L.J. (1992).
    • (1992) Ohio St. L.J , vol.53
  • 72
    • 84953540682 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 485 N.W.2d
    • 485 N.W.2d at 809.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.