-
2
-
-
33644688430
-
What Happens When Someone Acts?
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
J. David Velleman, “What Happens When Someone Acts?” in his The Possibility of Practical Reason (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000): 123-143
-
(2000)
The Possibility of Practical Reason
, pp. 123-143
-
-
David Velleman, J.1
-
3
-
-
0347494099
-
Free Will as Involving Determination andInconceivable Without It
-
as reprintedin BernardBerofsky, ed, New York: Harper & Row, 65-66
-
R. E. Hobart, “Free Will as Involving Determination andInconceivable Without It,” as reprintedin BernardBerofsky, ed., Free Will and Determinism (New York: Harper & Row, 1966): 63-95, esp. 65-66.
-
(1966)
Free Will and Determinism
, pp. 63-95
-
-
Hobart, R.E.1
-
4
-
-
84928871930
-
-
As for the provision of fully sufficient conditions, though, see my qualifications below in remarks about core elements of autonomy. AlfredR. Mele also pursues a strategy of seeking sufficient (but perhaps not necessary) conditions for certain forms of autonomy. And Mele addresses issues about the historical backgroundof autonomy, issues that, as I explain below, I put aside here
-
As for the provision of fully sufficient conditions, though, see my qualifications below in remarks about core elements of autonomy. AlfredR. Mele also pursues a strategy of seeking sufficient (but perhaps not necessary) conditions for certain forms of autonomy. And Mele addresses issues about the historical backgroundof autonomy, issues that, as I explain below, I put aside here
-
-
-
-
7
-
-
0010475612
-
-
CSLI Publications, and my
-
CSLI Publications, 1999; and my Faces of Intention.
-
(1999)
Faces of Intention
-
-
-
10
-
-
84928871932
-
-
Andit wouldbe amodel of what I have called“core features of human agency, I point to a similar idea in talking about “strong forms of agency” in “A Desire of One's Own,” 222 n. 3
-
Andit wouldbe amodel of what I have called“core features of human agency.” See my “Reflection, Planning, andT emporally ExtendedAgency,” 35-36. I point to a similar idea in talking about “strong forms of agency” in “A Desire of One's Own,” 222 n. 3.
-
Reflection, Planning, Andt Emporally Extendedagency
, pp. 35-36
-
-
-
12
-
-
0004225907
-
-
New York: Cambridge University Press, For relatedid eas
-
Harry Frankfurt, Necessity, Volition, and Love (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1999). For relatedid eas
-
(1999)
Necessity, Volition, and Love
-
-
Frankfurt, H.1
-
13
-
-
0001245384
-
Acting Freely
-
Gerald Dworkin, “Acting Freely,” Nôus 4 (1970): 367-383
-
(1970)
Nôus
, vol.4
, pp. 367-383
-
-
Dworkin, G.1
-
14
-
-
0009378125
-
Freedom andDesire
-
Wright Neely, “Freedom andDesire,” Philosophical Review 83 (1974): 32-54
-
(1974)
Philosophical Review
, vol.83
, pp. 32-54
-
-
Neely, W.1
-
15
-
-
33644673658
-
Reason andAutonomy
-
Paul, Miller, and Paul, eds
-
Keith Lehrer, “Reason andAutonomy,” in Paul, Miller, and Paul, eds., Autonomy, 177-198.
-
Autonomy
, pp. 177-198
-
-
Lehrer, K.1
-
16
-
-
0346275693
-
Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person
-
Frankfurt, It is interesting to note that in this passage Frankfurt appeals to something the agent is do ing-namely, securing the citedconformity
-
Frankfurt, “Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person,” in his The Importance of What We Care About, 20. (It is interesting to note that in this passage Frankfurt appeals to something the agent is doing-namely, securing the citedconformity.)
-
The Importance of What We Care About
, vol.20
-
-
-
17
-
-
0001862709
-
Identification andWholehearted ness
-
Frankfurt points to this condition of explanatory role in his
-
Frankfurt points to this condition of explanatory role in his “Identification andWholehearted ness,” in The Importance of What We Care About, 163.
-
The Importance of What We Care About
, pp. 163
-
-
-
18
-
-
33644683482
-
Autonomy, Necessity andLove
-
Frankfurt's, For a helpful discussion of some issues of Frankfurt interpretation that I am skirting over here
-
Frankfurt's “Autonomy, Necessity andLove” in his Necessity, Volition, and Love, 129-141. For a helpful discussion of some issues of Frankfurt interpretation that I am skirting over here
-
Necessity, Volition, and Love
, pp. 129-141
-
-
-
19
-
-
84928871936
-
Autonomy, Duress, andCoercion
-
Paul, Miller, andPaul, eds
-
James Stacey Taylor, “Autonomy, Duress, andCoercion,” in Paul, Miller, andPaul, eds., Autonomy, 129 n. 5.
-
Autonomy
, vol.129
, Issue.5
-
-
Taylor, J.S.1
-
21
-
-
84928859978
-
Wallace endorses similar objections in his “Caring, Reflexivity, and the Structure of Volition
-
Monika Betzler and Barbara Guckes, eds, Berlin: Akademie Verlag
-
R. Jay Wallace endorses similar objections in his “Caring, Reflexivity, and the Structure of Volition,” in Monika Betzler and Barbara Guckes, eds., Autonomes Handeln (Berlin: Akademie Verlag, 2000): 218-222.
-
(2000)
Autonomes Handeln
, pp. 218-222
-
-
Jay, R.1
-
22
-
-
1642505214
-
-
Watson
-
Watson, “Free Agency,” 218.
-
Free Agency
, pp. 218
-
-
-
23
-
-
33644677974
-
-
Talk of agential authority comes from my, talk of wiggles in the psychic stew comes, I admit, from my “Reflection, Planning, andTemporally ExtendedAgency
-
Talk of agential authority comes from my “Two Problems About Human Agency”; talk of wiggles in the psychic stew comes, I admit, from my “Reflection, Planning, andTemporally ExtendedAgency,” 38.
-
Two Problems about Human Agency
, pp. 38
-
-
-
24
-
-
84928871937
-
-
Watson notes that there are elements in Frankfurt's essay-in particular, Frankfurt's talk of an agent who “identifies himself decisively with one of his first-order desires”-that suggest that it is not conative hierarchy that is do ing the main theoretical work but, rather, the idea of decisive identification
-
Watson notes that there are elements in Frankfurt's essay-in particular, Frankfurt's talk of an agent who “identifies himself decisively with one of his first-order desires”-that suggest that it is not conative hierarchy that is doing the main theoretical work but, rather, the idea of decisive identification.
-
-
-
-
25
-
-
84928852460
-
Identification, Decision, and Treating as a Reason
-
But, Watson remarks, if “notions of acts of identification and of decisive commitment… are the crucial notions, it is unclear why these acts of identification cannot themselves be of the first order…. ” (The quote from Frankfurt is in Watson's “Free Agency,” at 218, while the quote from Watson is at 219.) I discuss this exchange between Frankfurt and Watson in
-
But, Watson remarks, if “notions of acts of identification and of decisive commitment… are the crucial notions, it is unclear why these acts of identification cannot themselves be of the first order…. ” (The quote from Frankfurt is in Watson's “Free Agency,” at 218, while the quote from Watson is at 219.) I discuss this exchange between Frankfurt and Watson in “Identification, Decision, and Treating as a Reason,” in my Faces of Intention, 188-190.
-
Faces of Intention
, pp. 188-190
-
-
-
26
-
-
1642505214
-
-
Watson
-
Watson, “Free Agency,” 216.
-
Free Agency
, pp. 216
-
-
-
27
-
-
1642505214
-
-
Watson
-
Watson, “Free Agency,” 219.
-
Free Agency
, pp. 219
-
-
-
28
-
-
84928871938
-
-
Frankfurt made this point in conversation
-
Frankfurt made this point in conversation. Also see
-
-
-
-
30
-
-
33644681362
-
The Faintest Passion
-
Frankfurt
-
Frankfurt, “The Faintest Passion,” in his Necessity, Volition, and Love, 103-105.
-
Necessity, Volition, and Love
, pp. 103-105
-
-
-
33
-
-
84928871939
-
-
Bratman, for my strategy for avoiding this difficulty within my own account
-
Bratman, “Reflection, Planning, andTemporally ExtendedAgency,” 49, for my strategy for avoiding this difficulty within my own account.
-
Reflection, Planning, Andtemporally Extendedagency
, vol.49
-
-
-
34
-
-
33644670994
-
Free Action and Free Will
-
Watson, A Desire of One's Own
-
Watson, “Free Action and Free Will,” Mind 96 (1987): 150. Also see my “A Desire of One's Own,” 227.
-
(1987)
Mind
, vol.96
, pp. 150-227
-
-
-
35
-
-
60950582938
-
Incommensurability andAgency
-
as reprintedin his, Oxford: Oxford University Press, I discuss this trio of possibilities in “A Desire of One's Own.” 25
-
Joseph Raz, “Incommensurability andAgency,” as reprintedin his Engaging Reason (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999): 46-66. I discuss this trio of possibilities in “A Desire of One's Own.” 25.
-
(1999)
Engaging Reason
, pp. 46-66
-
-
Raz, J.1
-
36
-
-
0004071138
-
-
Cambridge, MA: HarvardUniversity Press
-
Robert Nozick, Philosophical Explanations (Cambridge, MA: HarvardUniversity Press, 1981): 446-450.
-
(1981)
Philosophical Explanations
, pp. 446-450
-
-
Nozick, R.1
-
37
-
-
0002287875
-
Leading a Life
-
Talk of the shape of a life comes from Charles Taylor, Ruth Chang, ed, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
Talk of the shape of a life comes from Charles Taylor, “Leading a Life,” in Ruth Chang, ed., Incommensurability, Incomparability, and Practical Reason (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1997): 183.
-
(1997)
Incommensurability, Incomparability, and Practical Reason
, pp. 183
-
-
-
39
-
-
0003740191
-
-
New York: OxfordUniversity Press, and my
-
Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons (New York: OxfordUniversity Press, 1984): 206-208; and my
-
(1984)
Reasons and Persons
, pp. 206-208
-
-
Parfit, D.1
-
48
-
-
84928871941
-
-
I think there is also another reason for such reflexivity, one associatedwith the concern about reasoning to which I allude in note 34 and the essays cited there
-
I think there is also another reason for such reflexivity, one associatedwith the concern about reasoning to which I allude in note 34 and the essays cited there.
-
-
-
-
49
-
-
0009285661
-
-
A closely relatedid ea is in
-
A closely relatedid ea is in Keith Lehrer, Self-Trust, 100-102;
-
Self-Trust
, pp. 100-102
-
-
Lehrer, K.1
-
50
-
-
33644673818
-
-
For the basic idea of seeing intentions as reflexive
-
Keith Lehrer “Reason andAutonomy,” 187-191. For the basic idea of seeing intentions as reflexive
-
Reason Andautonomy
, pp. 187-191
-
-
Lehrer, K.1
-
51
-
-
0004176779
-
-
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, However, my appeal here to reflexivity is not part of a view that, like Harman's, sees all “positive” intentions in this way. Further, because my appeal to reflexivity is against a backgroundof a Lockean story of agential authority, together with a Frankfurtian appeal to satisfaction, the job of such reflexivity within my account of autonomy is considerably more limited than its job within Lehrer's
-
Gilbert Harman, Change in View (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1986): 85-88. However, my appeal here to reflexivity is not part of a view that, like Harman's, sees all “positive” intentions in this way. Further, because my appeal to reflexivity is against a backgroundof a Lockean story of agential authority, together with a Frankfurtian appeal to satisfaction, the job of such reflexivity within my account of autonomy is considerably more limited than its job within Lehrer's.
-
(1986)
Change in View
, pp. 85-88
-
-
Harman, G.1
-
52
-
-
84928871943
-
-
I shouldemphasize that the relevant notion of stability here is in part a normative one: It will involve norms of reasonable stability. It is an important question how exactly to understand such reasonable stability. For some efforts in this direction
-
I shouldemphasize that the relevant notion of stability here is in part a normative one: It will involve norms of reasonable stability. It is an important question how exactly to understand such reasonable stability. For some efforts in this direction, see my “Toxin, Temptation, and the Stability of Intention”
-
Toxin, Temptation, and the Stability of Intention
-
-
-
53
-
-
84928871944
-
-
Note that the appeal to reasonable stability is not an appeal to “volitional necessities” in the sense invokedby Frankfurt in his “Autonomy, Necessity, andLove
-
“T emptation Revisited.” Note that the appeal to reasonable stability is not an appeal to “volitional necessities” in the sense invokedby Frankfurt in his “Autonomy, Necessity, andLove,” 138.
-
T Emptation Revisited
, pp. 138
-
-
-
54
-
-
84928858670
-
-
For references and further discussion
-
For references and further discussion, see my “A Desire of One's Own.”
-
A Desire of Ones Own.”
-
-
-
55
-
-
84928871945
-
-
seeing deliberation as primarily first-order, but also seeing the valuings that enter into deliberation as involving conative hierarchy, my view is in the spirit of certain aspects of Simon Blackburn's approach to these matters. (I provide a different treatment of the relevant hierarchy, however. And my view remains neutral with respect to the basic debate between cognitivist approaches and expressivist approaches of the sort championedby Blackburn
-
In seeing deliberation as primarily first-order, but also seeing the valuings that enter into deliberation as involving conative hierarchy, my view is in the spirit of certain aspects of Simon Blackburn's approach to these matters. (I provide a different treatment of the relevant hierarchy, however. And my view remains neutral with respect to the basic debate between cognitivist approaches and expressivist approaches of the sort championedby Blackburn.)
-
-
-
-
56
-
-
0010840474
-
-
Blackburn, (Oxford andNew York: Clarendon/OxfordUniversity Press, Blackburn's remarks about a “staircase of practical and emotional ascent” are at 9; his remarks about valuing are at 67-68; and his remarks about deliberation are at
-
Blackburn, RulingPassions: A Theory of Practical Reasoning (Oxford andNew York: Clarendon/OxfordUniversity Press, 1998). (Blackburn's remarks about a “staircase of practical and emotional ascent” are at 9; his remarks about valuing are at 67-68; and his remarks about deliberation are at 250-256.)
-
(1998)
Rulingpassions: A Theory of Practical Reasoning
, pp. 250-256
-
-
-
57
-
-
84928871946
-
-
andothers have notedin correspondence and conversation
-
As Samuel Scheffler and others have notedin correspondence and conversation.
-
-
-
Scheffler, S.1
-
58
-
-
84928856560
-
-
Gilbert Harman argues that (1) “positive intentions are self-referential,” so (2) all creatures who have positive intentions have higher-order conative attitudes, and so (3) “Frankfurt's appeal to second-order volitions is not the key to distinguishing autonomy from nonautonomy.” Though I would not defend a simple appeal to second-order volitions as this “key,” my remarks in the text do point to a response on Frankfurt's behalf to this criticism. Frankfurt can say that what provides the key is the capacity for broad conative hierarchy, a capacity that goes beyondthe hierarchy built into the purported reflexivity of positive intentions, as reprintedin his ExplainingV alue and Other Essays in Moral Philosophy (Oxford: OxfordUniversity Press
-
Gilbert Harman argues that (1) “positive intentions are self-referential,” so (2) all creatures who have positive intentions have higher-order conative attitudes, and so (3) “Frankfurt's appeal to second-order volitions is not the key to distinguishing autonomy from nonautonomy.” Though I would not defend a simple appeal to second-order volitions as this “key,” my remarks in the text do point to a response on Frankfurt's behalf to this criticism. Frankfurt can say that what provides the key is the capacity for broad conative hierarchy, a capacity that goes beyondthe hierarchy built into the purported reflexivity of positive intentions. See Gilbert Harman, “DesiredDesires,” as reprintedin his ExplainingV alue and Other Essays in Moral Philosophy (Oxford: OxfordUniversity Press, 2000): 122-126.
-
(2000)
Desireddesires
, pp. 122-126
-
-
Harman, G.1
-
59
-
-
84928871947
-
-
For ease of exposition, in the discussion to follow of reasons for broad hierarchy I will simply speak of hierarchy where I mean broadhierarchy. Also, I do not claim that the pressures to be discussed exhaust the field. There may be other pressures for conative hierarchy that wouldneedto be considered in a more extensive discussion
-
For ease of exposition, in the discussion to follow of reasons for broad hierarchy I will simply speak of hierarchy where I mean broadhierarchy. Also, I do not claim that the pressures to be discussed exhaust the field. There may be other pressures for conative hierarchy that wouldneedto be considered in a more extensive discussion.
-
-
-
-
61
-
-
84928861061
-
-
Frankfurt, “Reply to, in Sarah Buss andLee Overton, eds., Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
-
Frankfurt, “Reply to Michael E. Bratman,” in Sarah Buss andLee Overton, eds., Contours of Agency (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2002): 88.
-
(2002)
Contours of Agency
, pp. 88
-
-
Bratman, M.E.1
-
62
-
-
84928871948
-
-
Though Christine Korsgaardshares with Frankfurt an interest in selfconstitution, she also embraces such a model of deliberation when she writes: “When you deliberate, it is as if there were something over and above all your desires, something which is you, and which chooses which desire to act on
-
Though Christine Korsgaardshares with Frankfurt an interest in selfconstitution, she also embraces such a model of deliberation when she writes: “When you deliberate, it is as if there were something over and above all your desires, something which is you, and which chooses which desire to act on” (The Sources of Normativity, 100).
-
The Sources of Normativity
, vol.100
-
-
-
63
-
-
0038907360
-
Self-Constitution in the Ethics of Plato and Kant
-
For Korsgaard's concerns with self-constitution
-
For Korsgaard's concerns with self-constitution, see her “Self-Constitution in the Ethics of Plato and Kant,” Journal of Ethics 3 (1999): 1-29.
-
(1999)
Journal of Ethics
, vol.3
, pp. 1-29
-
-
-
64
-
-
84928851728
-
-
Though Frankfurt himself does not seem so inclined
-
Though Frankfurt himself does not seem so inclined. (See his “Reply to Michael E. Bratman,” 89-90.)
-
Reply to Michael E. Bratman
, pp. 89-90
-
-
-
65
-
-
84928871949
-
-
unpublishedmanuscript. The example to follow comes (with a change in gender) from that paper
-
See her “Caring andInternality,” unpublishedmanuscript. The example to follow comes (with a change in gender) from that paper.
-
Caring Andinternality
-
-
-
66
-
-
33644689785
-
-
reprintedin his Reason and Emotion: Essays on Ancient Moral Psychology and Ethical Theory, Princeton: Princeton University Press, As Cooper puts the view, “non-rational desires will be desires no part of the causal history of which is ever any process (self-conscious or not) of investigation into the truth about what is goodfor oneself” (242). Cooper notes that this is compatible with holding, as Aristotle did, that “non-rational desires carry with them value judgments framedin (at least some of) the very same terms of goodand bad, right and wrong, etc., that also reappear in our rational reflections about what to do and why” (247). (In contrast, I wouldwant to allow for some nonrational desires that do not involve such value judgments.) What is central, Cooper indicates, is “the permanence in human beings and the independence from reason… of the nonrational desires”(249)
-
John Cooper, “Some Remarks on Aristotle's Moral Psychology,” reprintedin his Reason and Emotion: Essays on Ancient Moral Psychology and Ethical Theory (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1999): 237-252. As Cooper puts the view, “non-rational desires will be desires no part of the causal history of which is ever any process (self-conscious or not) of investigation into the truth about what is goodfor oneself” (242). Cooper notes that this is compatible with holding, as Aristotle did, that “non-rational desires carry with them value judgments framedin (at least some of) the very same terms of goodand bad, right and wrong, etc., that also reappear in our rational reflections about what to do and why” (247). (In contrast, I wouldwant to allow for some nonrational desires that do not involve such value judgments.) What is central, Cooper indicates, is “the permanence in human beings and the independence from reason… of the nonrational desires”(249).
-
(1999)
Some Remarks on Aristotles Moral Psychology,”
, pp. 237-252
-
-
Cooper, J.1
-
67
-
-
84928871950
-
-
For a similar focus on this practical problem-though not in the service of a hierarchical model
-
For a similar focus on this practical problem-though not in the service of a hierarchical model-see
-
-
-
-
68
-
-
0003813026
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, chap. 4. Note that the commitments that needto be supported by self-management will include shared commitments-for example, our sharedcommitment to a certain project
-
Martha C. Nussbaum, The Fragility of Goodness: Luck and Ethics in Greek Tragedy and Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986): chap. 4. Note that the commitments that needto be supported by self-management will include shared commitments-for example, our sharedcommitment to a certain project.
-
(1986)
The Fragility of Goodness: Luck and Ethics in Greek Tragedy and Philosophy
-
-
Nussbaum, M.C.1
-
69
-
-
84928854114
-
-
Note that I do not claim that these are the only policies that may be relevant here. For example, as AlfredMele has noted, the agent may also have a policy in favor of simply trying to remove a certain desire
-
“Autonomy and Hierarchy.” Note that I do not claim that these are the only policies that may be relevant here. For example, as AlfredMele has noted, the agent may also have a policy in favor of simply trying to remove a certain desire.
-
Autonomy and Hierarchy
-
-
-
70
-
-
84928871951
-
-
including in some such policies a direct concern with X, as well as with associated desires and what they are for, I am extending (as anticipated earlier) what it is that is accorded subjective normative authority
-
In including in some such policies a direct concern with X, as well as with associated desires and what they are for, I am extending (as anticipated earlier) what it is that is accorded subjective normative authority.
-
-
-
-
71
-
-
84928871952
-
-
Though we, as theorists, can reason in this way, as part of what
-
Though we, as theorists, can reason in this way, as part of what Paul Grice called“creature construction.”
-
Creature Construction
-
-
Grice, P.1
-
72
-
-
0040373496
-
-
Grice's, Presidential Address, 1974, I pursue such a methodology in “Valuing and the Will” and in “Autonomy andHierar-chy,” In “Autonomy andHierarchy” I see self-governing policies as a solution to a pair of pervasive human problems: the needfor self-management and the need to respond to underdetermination by value judgment. 55
-
Grice's “Methodin Philosophical Psychology (from the Banal to the Bizarre)” (Presidential Address), in Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association (1974-1975): 23-53. I pursue such a methodology in “Valuing and the Will” and in “Autonomy andHierar-chy,” In “Autonomy andHierarchy” I see self-governing policies as a solution to a pair of pervasive human problems: the needfor self-management and the need to respond to underdetermination by value judgment. 55.
-
(1975)
Methodin Philosophical Psychology (From the Banal to the Bizarre)
, pp. 23-53
-
-
-
73
-
-
84922428415
-
Self-Anchored Morality
-
J. B. Schneewind, ed, Chicago: Open Court, 198. As I see it, one use of Gricean creature construction is to help us achieve such self-understanding. Note that in locating this question about conative hierarchy within the enterprise of self-understanding, I do not suppose that the basic concern to which our answer to this question appeals must be a concern with self-understanding. Indeed, the relevant concern to which my answer appeals is a concern with the effective pursuit of basic commitments. For a view that sees this basic concern as, in contrast, a concern with self-understanding
-
T. M. Scanlon, “Self-Anchored Morality,” in J. B. Schneewind, ed., Reasons, Ethics, and Society: Themes from Kurt Baier with His Responses (Chicago: Open Court, 1996): 198. As I see it, one use of Gricean creature construction is to help us achieve such self-understanding. Note that in locating this question about conative hierarchy within the enterprise of self-understanding, I do not suppose that the basic concern to which our answer to this question appeals must be a concern with self-understanding. Indeed, the relevant concern to which my answer appeals is a concern with the effective pursuit of basic commitments. For a view that sees this basic concern as, in contrast, a concern with self-understanding, see
-
(1996)
Reasons, Ethics, and Society: Themes from Kurt Baier with His Responses
-
-
Scanlon, T.M.1
-
75
-
-
84928871954
-
-
These roles are multiple and interconnected: They include the organization of thought and action over time, relatedforms of agential authority, and roles in shaping what has subjective normative authority. This contrasts with a thin conception of the will as primarily a matter of deciding what to do in present circumstances
-
These roles are multiple and interconnected: They include the organization of thought and action over time, relatedforms of agential authority, and roles in shaping what has subjective normative authority. This contrasts with a thin conception of the will as primarily a matter of deciding what to do in present circumstances.
-
-
-
-
76
-
-
0004189454
-
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
Susan, Wolf, Freedom within Reason (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990);
-
(1990)
Freedom within Reason
-
-
Susan, W.1
-
78
-
-
84870511885
-
Free Will andAgency at Its Best
-
We needto be careful, though, to remember that our concern here is with autonomy and not directly with moral accountabilityFor a relatedcaveat
-
Gideon Yaffe, “Free Will andAgency at Its Best,” Philosophical Perspectives 14 (2000): 203-229. We needto be careful, though, to remember that our concern here is with autonomy and not directly with moral accountability. For a relatedcaveat
-
(2000)
Philosophical Perspectives
, vol.14
, pp. 203-229
-
-
Yaffe, G.1
-
79
-
-
0009125786
-
Two Faces of Responsibility
-
Gary, Watson, “Two Faces of Responsibility,” Philosophical Topics 24 (1996): 240-241
-
(1996)
Philosophical Topics
, vol.24
, pp. 240-241
-
-
Gary, W.1
|