-
1
-
-
84921965613
-
-
Priest (1993), p. 53.
-
(1993)
, pp. 53
-
-
Priest1
-
2
-
-
84921980868
-
-
Hegel (1955), p. 460.
-
(1955)
, pp. 460
-
-
Hegel1
-
3
-
-
84921956944
-
-
Restall (2004).
-
(2004)
-
-
Restall1
-
6
-
-
84921993560
-
-
see also
-
see also Beall (2005).
-
(2005)
-
-
Beall1
-
7
-
-
84921965616
-
-
See, sect. 9.7
-
See Priest (2001), sect. 9.7.
-
(2001)
-
-
Priest1
-
8
-
-
84921967359
-
-
See, sect. 8.5
-
See Priest (2002), sect. 8.5.
-
(2002)
-
-
Priest1
-
9
-
-
84921983274
-
-
especially ch. 7
-
Priest, (2005), especially ch. 7.
-
(2005)
-
-
Priest1
-
10
-
-
84921959193
-
-
As
-
As Shapiro (2004), p. 339
-
(2004)
, pp. 339
-
-
Shapiro1
-
11
-
-
84921979577
-
-
sect. 6
-
Mortensen (2002), sect. 6.
-
(2002)
-
-
Mortensen1
-
12
-
-
84921991531
-
-
Pears (1972), pp. 93-4.
-
(1972)
, pp. 93-4
-
-
Pears1
-
13
-
-
84921954765
-
-
For example
-
For example, Harman (1972);
-
(1972)
-
-
Harman1
-
14
-
-
84921950257
-
-
ch. 8
-
Hacking (1975), ch. 8.
-
(1975)
-
-
Hacking1
-
15
-
-
84921971483
-
-
They can be found, in effect, in
-
They can be found, in effect, in Priest (1982).
-
(1982)
-
-
Priest1
-
16
-
-
84921941016
-
-
ch. 2, sects. 4, 5
-
Priest and Routley (1983), ch. 2, sects. 4, 5.
-
(1983)
-
-
Priest1
Routley2
-
17
-
-
84921984875
-
-
sect. 1.2
-
Routley et al. (1982), sect. 1.2.
-
(1982)
-
-
Routley1
-
18
-
-
84921980974
-
-
sect. 1.5
-
Routley et al. (1982), sect. 1.5.
-
(1982)
-
-
Routley1
-
19
-
-
84921953940
-
-
Lewis (1973).
-
Stalnaker (1968); Lewis (1973).
-
(1968)
-
-
Stalnaker1
-
20
-
-
84921959157
-
-
sect. 2.10
-
Routley et al. (1982), sect. 2.10.
-
(1982)
-
-
Routley1
-
21
-
-
84921944705
-
-
sect. 5.2.1
-
Anderson and Belnap (1975), sect. 5.2.1
-
(1975)
-
-
Anderson1
Belnap2
-
22
-
-
84921939635
-
-
sect. 1.4.
-
Routley et al. (1982), sect. 1.4.
-
(1982)
-
-
Routley1
-
24
-
-
84921966232
-
-
Priest (1980).
-
(1980)
-
-
Priest1
-
26
-
-
84921987838
-
-
Lucas (1961).
-
(1961)
-
-
Lucas1
-
27
-
-
84921976075
-
-
of reprint
-
Dummett (1963), p. 195 of reprint.
-
(1963)
, pp. 195
-
-
Dummett1
-
29
-
-
84921974166
-
-
ch. 18
-
Wang (1962), ch. 18.
-
(1962)
-
-
Wang1
-
30
-
-
84921984701
-
-
ch. 8
-
Priest (2001), ch. 8.
-
(2001)
-
-
Priest1
-
31
-
-
84921964278
-
-
sect. 8.1
-
Priest (2002), sect. 8.1.
-
(2002)
-
-
Priest1
-
32
-
-
84921981600
-
-
sect. 10.5
-
Priest (1995), sect. 10.5.
-
(1995)
-
-
Priest1
-
33
-
-
84921957625
-
-
Shapiro (2002), p. 828.
-
(2002)
, pp. 828
-
-
Shapiro1
-
35
-
-
84921960542
-
-
Guest (1969), p. 454.
-
(1969)
, pp. 454
-
-
Guest1
-
36
-
-
84921951458
-
-
Fuller (1969), pp. 65-6.
-
(1969)
, pp. 65-66
-
-
Fuller1
-
37
-
-
84921944694
-
-
Fitzgerald (1966), p. 137.
-
(1966)
, pp. 137
-
-
Fitzgerald1
-
38
-
-
84921970534
-
-
Hintikka (1971), p. 102.
-
(1971)
, pp. 102
-
-
Hintikka1
-
40
-
-
84921996784
-
-
sect. 4.3
-
Hare (1963), sect. 4.3.
-
(1963)
-
-
Hare1
-
41
-
-
84921972110
-
-
ch. 4, sect. 3
-
Priest and Routley (1983), ch. 4, sect. 3.
-
(1983)
-
-
Priest1
Routley2
-
42
-
-
84921948969
-
-
ch. 6
-
Boyer (1949), ch. 6.
-
(1949)
-
-
Boyer1
-
43
-
-
84921956916
-
-
chs. 7, 8
-
Ilyenkov (1977), chs. 7, 8.
-
(1977)
-
-
Ilyenkov1
-
44
-
-
84921984225
-
-
sect. 8.3
-
Priest (2001), sect. 8.3.
-
(2001)
-
-
Priest1
-
45
-
-
84921983360
-
-
Dunn and Restall (2002), p. 10.
-
(2002)
, pp. 10
-
-
Dunn1
Restall2
-
46
-
-
84921976397
-
-
ch. 5, esp
-
Dummett (1977), ch. 5, esp. p. 197.
-
(1977)
, pp. 197
-
-
Dummett1
-
47
-
-
84921942922
-
-
Carroll (1895)
-
(1895)
-
-
Carroll1
-
48
-
-
84921983311
-
-
For details of these and other inconsistent theories in the history of science, see, ch. 5
-
For details of these and other inconsistent theories in the history of science, see Priest and Routley (1983), ch. 5.
-
(1983)
-
-
Priest1
Routley2
-
49
-
-
84921948546
-
-
This argument can be found, for example, in
-
This argument can be found, for example, in Popper (1940), pp. 316-17
-
(1940)
, pp. 316-317
-
-
Popper1
-
50
-
-
84921981244
-
Dialetheism is outrageous-at least to the spirit of contemporary philosophy
-
What In, xv
-
What In Contradiction actually says (p. xv) is 'Dialetheism is outrageous-at least to the spirit of contemporary philosophy.'
-
Contradiction actually says
-
-
-
51
-
-
84921992102
-
-
2001, and
-
Priest (1995, 2001, and 2006).
-
(1995)
-
-
Priest1
-
52
-
-
84921947486
-
-
Some details of these can be found in, ch. 4
-
Some details of these can be found in Priest and Routley (1983), ch. 4
-
(1983)
-
-
Priest, R.1
-
53
-
-
84921981532
-
-
see, The theory of truth required for an account of validity is, of course, a different matter
-
see Davies (1981), pp. 193-201. The theory of truth required for an account of validity is, of course, a different matter.
-
(1981)
, pp. 193-201
-
-
Davies1
-
54
-
-
84921984546
-
-
See Davidson (1967), p. 314.
-
(1967)
, pp. 314
-
-
Davidson1
-
55
-
-
84921960589
-
-
of reprint
-
Tarski (1936), p. 164 of reprint.
-
(1936)
, pp. 164
-
-
Tarski1
-
56
-
-
84921983224
-
-
One might also note that Davidson himself has rejected the whole notion of conceptual relativism; see
-
One might also note that Davidson himself has rejected the whole notion of conceptual relativism; see Davidson (1973).
-
(1973)
-
-
Davidson1
-
57
-
-
84921960779
-
In fact, he claims that it must be finitely axiomatisable
-
But this seems to me not to be right
-
Davidson (1965). In fact, he claims that it must be finitely axiomatisable. But this seems to me not to be right.
-
(1965)
-
-
Davidson1
-
58
-
-
84921970532
-
-
Peano (1906) p. 157.
-
(1906)
, pp. 157
-
-
Peano1
-
59
-
-
84921985525
-
-
See e.g.
-
See e.g. C. Parsons (1974).
-
(1974)
-
-
Parsons, C.1
-
60
-
-
84921970494
-
-
Introduction, ch. 2
-
Russell and Whitehead (1910), vol. I, Introduction, ch. 2.
-
(1910)
, vol.1
-
-
Russell, W.1
-
61
-
-
84921941769
-
-
See e.g
-
See e.g. Thompson (1962).
-
(1962)
-
-
Thompson1
-
62
-
-
84921992904
-
-
For the connection, see
-
For the connection, see Yablo (1982).
-
(1982)
-
-
Yablo1
-
63
-
-
84921976351
-
-
The point is wittily made by
-
The point is wittily made by Popper (1954).
-
(1954)
-
-
Popper1
-
64
-
-
84921959990
-
-
For some further telling criticisms along the same lines, see
-
For some further telling criticisms along the same lines, see Gupta (1982).
-
(1982)
-
-
Gupta1
-
65
-
-
84921939226
-
-
For references and an excellent discussion, see
-
For references and an excellent discussion, see Burge (1979).
-
(1979)
-
-
Burge1
-
66
-
-
84921942089
-
-
This line is taken by, e.g. , Fitch (1964), Kripke
-
This line is taken by, e.g. van Fraassen (1970), Fitch (1964), Kripke (1975).
-
(1970)
-
-
Fraassen, V.1
-
67
-
-
84921992714
-
-
This informal argument, which shows that this position ends up in a tangle, can be made quite precise in terms of an indefinability result which shows that the position is self refuting. See
-
This informal argument, which shows that this position ends up in a tangle, can be made quite precise in terms of an indefinability result which shows that the position is self refuting. See Priest (1987).
-
(1987)
-
-
Priest1
-
68
-
-
84921979948
-
-
Against the myopic view that Cantor et al did not initially suppose all conditions to determine sets, see
-
Against the myopic view that Cantor et al did not initially suppose all conditions to determine sets, see Quine (1973), pp. 102-3.
-
(1973)
, pp. 102-103
-
-
Quine1
-
69
-
-
84921975202
-
-
See e.g.
-
See e.g. Fraenkel, Bar-Hillel, and Levy (1973), pp. 321 ff.
-
(1973)
, pp. 321 ff
-
-
Fraenkel, B.-H.1
Levy2
-
70
-
-
84921959077
-
-
See e.g
-
See e.g. Shoenfield (1967) pp. 238-9;
-
(1967)
, pp. 238-239
-
-
Shoenfield1
-
71
-
-
84921980604
-
-
Devlin (1980) pp. 42-6.
-
(1980)
, pp. 42-46
-
-
Devlin1
-
72
-
-
84921990361
-
exception barring
-
In the terms of, it is merely the version of, called 'strategic withdrawal to a safe domain
-
In the terms of Lakatos (1976), it is merely the version of "exception barring" called 'strategic withdrawal to a safe domain'.
-
(1976)
-
-
Lakatos1
-
73
-
-
84921946602
-
-
Mayberry (1977), p. 31.
-
(1977)
, pp. 31
-
-
Mayberry1
-
74
-
-
84921995490
-
-
See e.g., Bell (1981), Fraenkel, Bar-Hillel, and Levy
-
See e.g. Feferman (1977), Bell (1981), Fraenkel, Bar-Hillel, and Levy (1973), pp. 143-4.
-
(1973)
, pp. 143-144
-
-
Feferman1
-
75
-
-
84921996063
-
-
Fraenkel, Bar-Hillel, and Levy (1973), pp. 143-4.
-
(1973)
, pp. 143-144
-
-
Fraenkel, B.-H.1
Levy2
-
76
-
-
84921958100
-
-
Italics original
-
Bell (1981), p. 356. Italics original.
-
(1981)
, pp. 356
-
-
Bell1
-
77
-
-
84921980281
-
-
For a number of the others, see, ch. 5
-
For a number of the others, see Priest and Routley (1983), ch. 5.
-
(1983)
-
-
Priest, R.1
-
78
-
-
84921994870
-
-
Further details of all these matters can be found in
-
Further details of all these matters can be found in Routley (1977).
-
(1977)
-
-
Routley1
-
79
-
-
84921950778
-
-
See Routley (1977).
-
(1977)
-
-
Routley1
-
80
-
-
84921993338
-
The proof also shows that the theory is non-trivial even if the variable z is allowed to occur in the formula β in (Abs)
-
See
-
See Brady (1989). The proof also shows that the theory is non-trivial even if the variable z is allowed to occur in the formula β in (Abs).
-
(1989)
-
-
Brady1
-
81
-
-
84921969651
-
-
e.g., Kripke (1976), and Priest (1983a ) in which much of the material in this chapter first appeared
-
e.g., C. Parsons (1971), Kripke (1976), and Priest (1983a ) in which much of the material in this chapter first appeared.
-
(1971)
-
-
Parsons, C.1
-
82
-
-
84921963644
-
-
This follows the practice of
-
This follows the practice of Kripke (1976).
-
(1976)
-
-
Kripke1
-
83
-
-
84921983774
-
-
Though their success has been over-rated: see
-
Though their success has been over-rated: see Priest (1979b ).
-
(1979)
-
-
Priest1
-
84
-
-
84921948486
-
-
and Gödel
-
See Smart (1963) and Gödel (1947).
-
(1947)
-
-
Smart1
-
85
-
-
84921986879
-
-
especially ch. 11
-
See Routley (1980), especially ch. 11.
-
(1980)
-
-
Routley1
-
86
-
-
84921969511
-
-
As in Gödel (1947).
-
(1947)
-
-
Gödel1
-
87
-
-
84921985022
-
-
Quine's; see
-
Quine's; see Smart (1963).
-
(1963)
-
-
Smart1
-
88
-
-
84921997305
-
-
Wittgenstein makes the points in e.g. his, For references and discussion, see
-
Wittgenstein makes the points in e.g. his (1956). For references and discussion, see Klenk (1976), pp. 8-18.
-
(1956)
, pp. 8-18
-
-
Klenk1
-
89
-
-
84921954929
-
-
See
-
See Dummett (1977), p. 24.
-
(1977)
, pp. 24
-
-
Dummett1
-
90
-
-
84921963419
-
-
See Fraenkel, Bar-Hillel, and Levy (1973), p. 332 ff.
-
(1973)
, pp. 332 ff
-
-
Fraenkel, B.-H.1
Levy2
-
91
-
-
84921990995
-
-
One can also give a generic account of how this kind of truth condition arises. See, sects
-
One can also give a generic account of how this kind of truth condition arises. See Quine (1973), sects. 22-8
-
(1973)
, pp. 22-28
-
-
Quine1
-
92
-
-
84921945676
-
-
See Quine (1973), pp. 118-20;
-
(1973)
, pp. 118-120
-
-
Quine1
-
93
-
-
84921955541
-
-
Kripke (1976), p. 385.
-
(1976)
, pp. 385
-
-
Kripke1
-
94
-
-
84921973589
-
-
italics original
-
Kripke (1976), p. 341; italics original.
-
(1976)
, pp. 341
-
-
Kripke1
-
95
-
-
84921939595
-
-
In terms of Quine's fortunate distinction, expressed in unfortunate language, set theory may provide the ontology of mathematics without providing its ideology
-
In terms of Quine's fortunate distinction, expressed in unfortunate language (1953, pp. 130-2), set theory may provide the ontology of mathematics without providing its ideology.
-
(1953)
, pp. 130-132
-
-
-
96
-
-
84921946358
-
-
See e.g.
-
See e.g. Steiner (1975), pp. 102-8.
-
(1975)
, pp. 102-108
-
-
Steiner1
-
97
-
-
84921961942
-
-
See e.g.
-
See e.g. Williams (1951)
-
(1951)
-
-
Williams1
-
98
-
-
84921971720
-
-
Smart (1949).
-
(1949)
-
-
Smart1
-
99
-
-
84921961081
-
-
e.g.
-
e.g. J. W. Dunn (1927).
-
(1927)
-
-
Dunn, J.W.1
-
100
-
-
84921978683
-
-
See e.g.
-
See e.g. Grünbaum (1967a )
-
(1967)
-
-
Grünbaum1
-
101
-
-
84921950396
-
-
Mellor (1984).
-
(1984)
-
-
Mellor1
-
102
-
-
84921988129
-
-
See e.g.
-
See e.g. Gold (1966).
-
(1966)
-
-
Gold1
-
103
-
-
84921942963
-
-
of translation
-
Hegel (1812), p. 440 of translation.
-
(1812)
, pp. 440
-
-
Hegel1
-
104
-
-
84921963136
-
-
273-4 of the translation
-
Hegel (1840), vol. I, pp. 273, 273-4 of the translation.
-
(1840)
, vol.1
, pp. 273
-
-
Hegel1
-
105
-
-
84921961271
-
-
of the translation. The italics are original
-
Hegel (1830), p. 43 of the translation. The italics are original.
-
(1830)
, pp. 43
-
-
Hegel1
-
106
-
-
84921950248
-
-
See, ch. 2
-
See Priest and Routley (1983), ch. 2.
-
(1983)
-
-
Priest1
Routley2
-
107
-
-
84921982174
-
-
Much of the following comes from
-
Much of the following comes from Priest (1982).
-
(1982)
-
-
Priest1
-
108
-
-
84921943748
-
-
See e.g.
-
See e.g. Hamblin (1969).
-
(1969)
-
-
Hamblin1
-
109
-
-
84921965005
-
-
The idea can be made the basis of systems of tense logic; see
-
The idea can be made the basis of systems of tense logic; see Humberstone (1979).
-
(1979)
-
-
Humberstone1
-
110
-
-
84921955762
-
-
Leibniz (1687), p. 351 of translation.
-
(1687)
, pp. 351
-
-
Leibniz1
-
111
-
-
84921970237
-
-
See
-
See Boyer (1949), p. 256.
-
(1949)
, pp. 256
-
-
Boyer1
-
112
-
-
84921963842
-
-
Leibniz (1687), p. 352 of translation.
-
(1687)
, pp. 352
-
-
Leibniz1
-
113
-
-
84921976822
-
-
Leibniz (1687), pp. 352-3 of translation.
-
(1687)
, pp. 352-353
-
-
Leibniz1
-
114
-
-
84921958088
-
-
Hegel (1812), p. 439 of translation.
-
(1812)
, pp. 439
-
-
Hegel1
-
115
-
-
84921981743
-
-
notes a similar distinction (and confusion) in grammar
-
Chomsky (1980), p. 220, notes a similar distinction (and confusion) in grammar.
-
(1980)
, pp. 220
-
-
Chomsky1
-
116
-
-
84921958994
-
-
For a fuller discussion of the development of modern logical theory, see
-
For a fuller discussion of the development of modern logical theory, see Priest (1989a).
-
(1989)
-
-
Priest1
-
117
-
-
84921991031
-
-
Tarski (1936), p. 188 of reprint.
-
(1936)
, pp. 188
-
-
Tarski1
-
118
-
-
84921948104
-
-
See
-
See Quine (1970), pp. 10-13.
-
(1970)
, pp. 10-13
-
-
Quine1
-
119
-
-
84921957260
-
-
As usual, I am supposing the language in question not to contain indexicals
-
Davidson (1967). As usual, I am supposing the language in question not to contain indexicals.
-
-
-
Davidson1
-
120
-
-
84921955814
-
-
especially ch. 6
-
Montague (1974), especially ch. 6;
-
(1974)
-
-
Montague1
-
121
-
-
84921997272
-
-
Lewis (1972);
-
(1972)
-
-
Lewis1
-
122
-
-
84921993582
-
-
Routley et al. (1982).
-
(1982)
-
-
Routley1
-
123
-
-
84921955583
-
-
See, especially ch. 14. N.B. also, xxii
-
See Dummett (1978), especially ch. 14. N.B. also p. xxii.
-
(1978)
-
-
Dummett1
-
124
-
-
84921977306
-
-
xxi
-
Dummett (1978), p. xxi.
-
(1978)
-
-
Dummett1
-
125
-
-
84921960740
-
-
Dummett (1973), p. 320.
-
(1973)
, pp. 320
-
-
Dummett1
-
126
-
-
84921965049
-
-
Grice (1957, 1968).
-
(1957)
-
-
Grice1
-
127
-
-
84921944933
-
-
As, e.g. in, ch. 1
-
As, e.g. in Davies (1981), ch. 1.
-
(1981)
-
-
Davies1
-
128
-
-
84921986611
-
-
of reprint. Italics original
-
Dummett (1959a), p. 8 of reprint. Italics original.
-
(1959)
, pp. 8
-
-
Dummett1
-
129
-
-
84921966345
-
-
See, ch. 4
-
See Haack (1974), ch. 4.
-
(1974)
-
-
Haack1
-
130
-
-
84921969544
-
-
This case is examined in more detail in
-
This case is examined in more detail in Priest (1979).
-
(1979)
-
-
Priest1
-
131
-
-
84921940731
-
-
See e.g
-
See e.g. Haack (1974), pp. 101-2.
-
(1974)
, pp. 101-102
-
-
Haack1
-
132
-
-
84921995565
-
-
In fact, the supposition that the sentence is neither true nor false leads to problems of its own. See
-
In fact, the supposition that the sentence is neither true nor false leads to problems of its own. See Mortensen and Priest (1981).
-
(1981)
-
-
Mortensen1
Priest2
-
133
-
-
84921950190
-
-
The propensity of verificationism to produce dialetheism as well as intuitionism is noted in
-
The propensity of verificationism to produce dialetheism as well as intuitionism is noted in Papineau (1979), pp. 91-2.
-
(1979)
, pp. 91-92
-
-
Papineau1
-
134
-
-
84921951270
-
-
sect. 26
-
Rescher and Brandom (1980), sect. 26.
-
(1980)
-
-
Rescher1
Brandom2
-
135
-
-
84921993153
-
-
The matter is discussed a little further in, sect. 3
-
The matter is discussed a little further in Priest (1984), sect. 3.
-
(1984)
-
-
Priest1
|