메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 35, Issue 3, 2013, Pages 259-278

From intrinsic value to compassion: A place-based ethic

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 84894358604     PISSN: 01634275     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.5840/enviroethics201335325     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (15)

References (73)
  • 1
    • 0003779611 scopus 로고
    • New York: Ballantine Books
    • Aldo Leopold, A Sand County Almanac (New York: Ballantine Books, 1970), p. 262.
    • (1970) A Sand County Almanac , pp. 262
    • Leopold, A.1
  • 2
    • 6244304438 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Leopold, A Sand County Almanac, p. xviii: "We abuse land because we regard it as a commodity belonging to us. When we see land as a community to which we belong, we may begin to use it with love and respect.
    • A Sand County Almanac
    • Leopold1
  • 4
    • 0002118077 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The nature and possibility of an environmental ethic
    • Tom Regan, "The Nature and Possibility of an Environmental Ethic," Environmental Ethics 3 (1981): 19-20.
    • (1981) Environmental Ethics , vol.3 , pp. 19-20
    • Regan, T.1
  • 5
    • 34250003761 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Anthropocentrism and nonanthropocentrism: Why should we care?
    • Throughout this essay, I speak of the intrinsic value of nature as inclusive of both of these approaches. Although seeking the intrinsic value of nature is so prevalent, I must also mention that there is a wide divergence in the interpretations of what, exactly, intrinsic value is. For instructive articles in this regard, see Katie McShane, "Anthropocentrism and Nonanthropocentrism: Why Should We Care?" Environmental Values 16 (2007): 169-85
    • (2007) Environmental Values , vol.16 , pp. 169-185
    • McShane, K.1
  • 6
    • 33947378370 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Why environmental ethics shouldn't give up on intrinsic value
    • "Why Environmental Ethics Shouldn't Give Up on Intrinsic Value," Environmental Ethics 29 (2007): 43-61.
    • (2007) Environmental Ethics , vol.29 , pp. 43-61
  • 7
    • 0001312815 scopus 로고
    • The varieties of intrinsic value
    • John O'Neill's "The Varieties of Intrinsic Value," The Monist 75 (1992): 119-37, also offers a taxonomy of intrinsic value, though it derives different conclusions from it..
    • (1992) The Monist , vol.75 , pp. 119-137
    • O'Neill, J.1
  • 8
    • 0002118077 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Tom Regan, "The Nature and Possibility of an Environmental Ethic," pp. 31-32, although in a later article he seems more pessimistic about such projects, arguing that no theory of intrinsic value can ground the kinds of duties environmental ethicists advocate.
    • The Nature and Possibility of An Environmental Ethic , pp. 31-32
    • Regan, T.1
  • 9
    • 84933493377 scopus 로고
    • Does environmental ethics rest on a mistake?
    • Regan, "Does Environmental Ethics Rest on a Mistake?" The Monist 75 (1992): 161-82.
    • (1992) The Monist , vol.75 , pp. 161-182
    • Regan1
  • 10
    • 0003562160 scopus 로고
    • Albany: SUNY Press, especially part three;
    • The classic examples to cite are philosophers such as J. Baird Callicott, In Defense of the Land Ethic (Albany: SUNY Press, 1989), especially part three;
    • (1989) Defense of the Land Ethic
    • Baird Callicott, J.1
  • 12
    • 0004288674 scopus 로고
    • Princeton: Princeton University Press
    • Paul Taylor, Respect for Nature (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1980).
    • (1980) Respect for Nature
    • Taylor, P.1
  • 13
    • 0001359848 scopus 로고
    • Intrinsic value, environmental obligation and naturalness
    • For a very small sample of more recent defenses, see Robert Elliot, "Intrinsic Value, Environmental Obligation and Naturalness," The Monist 75 (1992): 138-60;
    • (1992) The Monist , vol.75 , pp. 138-160
    • Elliot, R.1
  • 14
    • 70249114693 scopus 로고
    • Awe and humility: Intrinsic value in nature
    • Keekok Lee, "Awe and Humility: Intrinsic Value in Nature" Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 36 (1994): 89-101
    • (1994) Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement , vol.36 , pp. 89-101
    • Lee, K.1
  • 15
    • 0141766782 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Intrinsic value for pragmatists?
    • Ben Minteer, "Intrinsic Value for Pragmatists?" Environmental Ethics 22 (2001): 57-75;
    • (2001) Environmental Ethics , vol.22 , pp. 57-75
    • Minteer, B.1
  • 16
    • 0034958014 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Intrinsic value and care: Making connections through ecological narratives
    • Christopher Preston, "Intrinsic Value and Care: Making Connections through Ecological Narratives," Environmental Values 10 (2001): 243-63;
    • (2001) Environmental Values , vol.10 , pp. 243-263
    • Preston, C.1
  • 17
    • 0007584669 scopus 로고
    • Has nature a good of its own?
    • ed. Robert Costanza, Bryan G. Norton, and Benjamin D. Haskell
    • Mark Sagoff, "Has Nature a Good of Its Own?" in Ecosystem Health: New Goals for Environmental Management, ed. Robert Costanza, Bryan G. Norton, and Benjamin D. Haskell (1992), pp. 57-71;
    • (1992) Ecosystem Health: New Goals for Environmental Management , pp. 57-71
    • Sagoff, M.1
  • 18
    • 77957925625 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reasons and values in environmental ethics
    • Lars Samuelsson, "Reasons and Values in Environmental Ethics," Environmental Values 19 (2010): 517-35. Even theories that do not rely on theories of intrinsic value for its system of duties at times take care to make a place for the intrinsic value of nature in their theories.
    • (2010) Environmental Values , vol.19 , pp. 517-535
    • Samuelsson, L.1
  • 19
    • 77149165181 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Columbia University Press
    • See, for example, Ronald Sandler, Character and Environment (New York: Columbia University Press, 2007), p. 170;
    • (2007) Character and Environment , pp. 170
    • Sandler, R.1
  • 20
    • 70350605244 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Benevolence as an environmental virtue
    • ed. Ronald Sandler and Philip Cafaro, Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield
    • Geoffrey Frasz, "Benevolence as an Environmental Virtue," in Environmental Virtue Ethics, ed. Ronald Sandler and Philip Cafaro (Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield, 2005), p. 130.
    • (2005) Environmental Virtue Ethics , pp. 130
    • Frasz, G.1
  • 21
    • 6944234464 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • O'Neill, "The Varieties of Intrinsic Value" is a good example of a view that diverges from this account, however, arguing that some further justification is required for the intrinsic value of nature to serve as a basis for duties.
    • The Varieties of Intrinsic Value
    • O'Neill1
  • 24
    • 79960378101 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Toward a progressive naturalism
    • New York: Columbia University Press
    • "Toward a Progressive Naturalism" in Recognizing the Autonomy of Nature: Theory and Practice (New York: Columbia University Press, 2005): 25-53.
    • (2005) Recognizing the Autonomy of Nature: Theory and Practice , pp. 25-53
  • 25
    • 40849100517 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Convergence, noninstrumental value and the semantics of 'love': Comment on mcshane
    • Bryan G. Norton, "Convergence, Noninstrumental Value and the Semantics of 'Love': Comment on McShane," Environmental Values 17 (2008): 7.
    • (2008) Environmental Values , vol.17 , pp. 7
    • Norton, B.G.1
  • 27
    • 0004276410 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Cambridge University Press
    • Martha Nussbaum, Upheavals of Thought (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2001). I do not intend to endorse her moral theory in general by employing and modifying her more specific views regarding compassion, however.
    • (2001) Upheavals of Thought
    • Nussbaum, M.1
  • 28
    • 62649147017 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Emotions are not mere judgments
    • The discussion of Nussbaum's view has been lively. For a sample of how it has been received, see Aaron Ben-Ze'ev, "Emotions Are Not Mere Judgments," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 68 (2004): 450-57;
    • (2004) Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , vol.68 , pp. 450-457
    • Ben-Ze'Ev, A.1
  • 30
    • 46849096904 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pity and compassion as social virtues
    • Brian Carr, "Pity and Compassion as Social Virtues" Philosophy 74 (1999): 411-29;
    • (1999) Philosophy , vol.74 , pp. 411-429
    • Carr, B.1
  • 33
    • 33745475884 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Martha nussbaum on the emotions
    • Lester Hunt, "Martha Nussbaum on the Emotions," Ethics 116 (2006): 552-77;
    • (2006) Ethics , vol.116 , pp. 552-577
    • Hunt, L.1
  • 34
    • 35448970845 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compassion and pity: An evaluation of nussbaum's analysis and defense
    • M. Weber, "Compassion and Pity: An Evaluation of Nussbaum's Analysis and Defense," Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 7 (2004): 487-511;
    • (2004) Ethical Theory and Moral Practice , vol.7 , pp. 487-511
    • Weber, M.1
  • 35
    • 0036702751 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compassion as a political virtue
    • Maureen Whitebrook, "Compassion as a Political Virtue," Political Studies 50 (2002): 529-44.
    • (2002) Political Studies , vol.50 , pp. 529-544
    • Whitebrook, M.1
  • 37
    • 84894359852 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The desert requirement in specific has come under close scrutiny, with commentators questioning whether it is necessary for compassion as we seemingly are capable of experiencing compassion even toward those who are in some way responsible for their own suffering. John Deigh suggests that Nussbaum can address this issue by making a distinction between moral and non-moral forms of compassion: the form of compassion that involves desert is moral since it is guided by the aforementioned concerns of justice, while we can still acknowledge feeling compassion for those who deserve their suffering due to the human capacity for sympathetic concern (Deigh, "Nussbaum's Account of Compassion," p. 471).
    • Nussbaum's Account of Compassion , pp. 471
    • Deigh1
  • 38
    • 34250866641 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Responses
    • Nussbaum accepts this emendation with the stipulation that we also distinguish between "thoughtful" non-moral compassion when one, for example, feels compassion for an unknown homeless person and non-moral compassion as a reflexive response when one, for example, cringes as one watches someone accidentally slice his or her finger while cooking dinner (Nussbaum, "Responses," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 68 [2004]: 482-83
    • (2004) Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , vol.68 , pp. 482-483
    • Nussbaum1
  • 39
    • 0004276410 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • but one can already see her acknowledging this distinction in Upheavals of Thought, p. 301). Ultimately, Nussbaum does not truly want to call this reflexive distress an emotion as it lacks cognitive content, but nevertheless she recognizes it as a common psychological phenomenon. Thus, our "fellow-feeling" might be broken into three categories: moral compassion, non-moral compassion, and reflexive sympathetic reactions.
    • Upheavals of Thought , pp. 301
  • 40
    • 84894365955 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Roger Crisp finds this taxonomy of compassion to be rather unparsimonius: if non-moral compassion is the same emotion as moral compassion only lacking moral direction, then it seems as if compassion itself does not require the judgment of desert or a sense of justice (Crisp, "Beyond Compassion," p. 236).
    • Beyond Compassion , pp. 236
    • Crisp1
  • 42
    • 84894365955 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nussbaum has a variety of ways of defending herself on this point, for example, taking the judgment of non-desert to be proportional rather than absolute (e.g., while the person brought his or her suffering upon him or herself, the suffering is disproportionate to the act that caused it). I agree with Crisp, however, that including the desert requirement and thereby bundling in the need for a theory of justice in order to feel compassion distracts us from the essence of compassion, the felt distress at another being's suffering (Crisp, "Beyond Compassion," p. 237).
    • Beyond Compassion , pp. 237
    • Crisp1
  • 43
    • 8744248697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • A general theory of emotions such Peter Goldie's notion of "feelings toward" can shed light on how this is possible. For Goldie, an emotion is "complex, episodic, dynamic, and structured," meaning that emotions involve a diverse array of cognitive elements (thoughts, feelings, beliefs, desires, etc.), come and go, change over time, and contribute to the larger narrative of our lives (Peter Goldie, The Emotions [New York: Oxford University Press, 2002], pp. 11-12).
    • (2002) The Emotions , pp. 11-12
    • Goldie, P.1
  • 45
    • 0009388224 scopus 로고
    • Compassion
    • ed. Amelie Rorty, Berkeley: University of California Press
    • It also accommodates Lawrence Blum's characterization of compassion as an emotion with "an irreducible affective dimension" without having to posit the imaginative entering-into the other's situation he regards as central to compassion ("Compassion," in Explaining Emotions, ed. Amelie Rorty [Berkeley: University of California Press, 1980], p. 507).
    • (1980) Explaining Emotions , pp. 507
  • 46
    • 84894316012 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To be fair, Nussbaum expresses surprise that her view of compassion is seen as being independent of feelings, given that she does not hold that there is any distinction between emotion and thought; emotions just are specific kinds of judgments that present the world from a first-person perspective as being a certain, value-laden way that impacts one's eudaimonia (Nussbaum, "Responses," p. 476). The emotional response is a result of recognizing that the objects toward which the emotion is intentionally related are beyond our specific control, a result of our being entwined in the material world. Any feelings that accompany such emotional responses are accidental.
    • Responses , pp. 476
    • Nussbaum1
  • 47
    • 84894316012 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Though she intends perception to be understood in the terms of her broader conception of reason. See Nussbaum, "Responses," p. 473.
    • Responses , pp. 473
    • Nussbaum1
  • 48
    • 84875328162 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Re-envisioning nature: The role of perceptual norms in environmental ethics
    • I discuss the issue of relating perceptual norms and ethical actions in greater detail in "Re-Envisioning Nature: The Role of Perceptual Norms in Environmental Ethics," Environmental Ethics 33 (2011): 414-36.
    • (2011) Environmental Ethics , vol.33 , pp. 414-436
  • 50
    • 84894339264 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ed. George Sher, Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing
    • John Stuart Mill, Utilitarianism, ed. George Sher (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing, 2001), p. 14.
    • (2001) Utilitarianism , pp. 14
    • Stuart Mill, J.1
  • 52
    • 0004276410 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For this reason, Nussbaum believes that compassion must be coupled with "an adequate theory of the worth of basic goods," "an adequate understanding of agency and fault," and "a suitably broad account of the people who should be the object of an agent's concern, distant as well as close" (Nussbaum, Upheavals of Thought, p. 399).
    • Upheavals of Thought , pp. 399
    • Nussbaum1
  • 53
    • 0003442441 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Cambridge University Press
    • While outside the purview of this paper, parties interested in Nussbaum's views on these matters might consult her Women and Human Development (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2001) for further detail.
    • (2001) Women and Human Development
  • 54
    • 61249191106 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Taking care: Care as practice and value
    • ed. Cheshire Calhoun, New York: Oxford University Press
    • For a sense of the differing reasons philosophers have for maintaining this point, see Virginia Held, "Taking Care: Care as Practice and Value," in Setting the Moral Compass: Essays by Women Philosophers, ed. Cheshire Calhoun (New York: Oxford University Press, 2004), p. 69;
    • (2004) Setting the Moral Compass: Essays by Women Philosophers , pp. 69
    • Held, V.1
  • 55
    • 0000345828 scopus 로고
    • Caring as a feminist practice of moral reasoning
    • ed. Virginia Held, Boulder: Westview Press
    • Alison Jaggar, "Caring as a Feminist Practice of Moral Reasoning," in Justice and Care: Essential Readings in Feminist Ethics, ed. Virginia Held (Boulder: Westview Press, 1995), pp. 193-98;
    • (1995) Justice and Care: Essential Readings in Feminist Ethics , pp. 193-198
    • Jaggar, A.1
  • 56
    • 84982031445 scopus 로고
    • Colonialism and its others: Considerations on rights and care discourses
    • Uma Narayan, "Colonialism and Its Others: Considerations on Rights and Care Discourses," Hypatia 10 (1995): 133-40.
    • (1995) Hypatia , vol.10 , pp. 133-140
    • Narayan, U.1
  • 57
    • 80455150459 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Flesh and nature: Understanding merleau-ponty's relational ontology
    • For those interested in Merleau-Ponty's philosophy more specifically, I develop this theory of flesh in much greater detail in "Flesh and Nature: Understanding Merleau-Ponty's Relational Ontology," Research in Phenomenology 41 (2011): 327-57.
    • (2011) Research in Phenomenology , vol.41 , pp. 327-357
  • 58
    • 0003612575 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bloomington: Indiana University Press
    • Although Casey develops the concept in different directions in his more recent works, Getting Back into Place (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1993) remains his most thorough explication of his views on place and their philosophical implications.
    • (1993) Getting Back into Place
  • 60
    • 0000935836 scopus 로고
    • The big lie: Human restoration of nature
    • I have in mind here the sometimes fractious debates regarding ecological restoration. Perhaps the strongest exponent of the rejection of restoration based on naturalness is Eric Katz, "The Big Lie: Human Restoration of Nature," Research in Philosophy and Technology 12 (1992): 231-41.
    • (1992) Research in Philosophy and Technology , vol.12 , pp. 231-241
    • Katz, E.1
  • 61
    • 0004096751 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Routledge
    • At times, such arguments are bound up with views about the intrinsic value of nature as with Robert Elliot's Faking Nature (New York: Routledge, 1997).
    • (1997) Faking Nature
    • Elliot, R.1
  • 62
    • 84894316479 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Environmental atrocities
    • Claudia Card, "Environmental Atrocities," Ethics and the Environment 9 (2004): 27-28.
    • (2004) Ethics and the Environment , vol.9 , pp. 27-28
    • Card, C.1
  • 63
    • 77954121617 scopus 로고
    • New York: Cambridge University Press, esp. parts four and five
    • For a history of this dispute, see Donald Worster, The Economy of Nature (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1977), esp. parts four and five
    • (1977) The Economy of Nature
    • Worster, D.1
  • 64
    • 0025660564 scopus 로고
    • The ecology of order and chaos
    • "The Ecology of Order and Chaos," Environmental History Review 14 (1990): 1-18.
    • (1990) Environmental History Review , vol.14 , pp. 1-18
  • 65
    • 0004175139 scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • Popular texts that take a position on the matter include Daniel Botkin, Discordant Harmonies (New York: Oxford University Press, 1991);
    • (1991) Discordant Harmonies
    • Botkin, D.1
  • 68
    • 34248995919 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Local ecological communities
    • Kim Sterelny, "Local Ecological Communities," Philosophy of Science 73 (2006): 218-26.
    • (2006) Philosophy of Science , vol.73 , pp. 218-226
    • Sterelny, K.1
  • 71
    • 0002397909 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Refocusing ecocentrism: De-emphasizing stability and defending wildness
    • Ned Hettinger and Bill Throop, "Refocusing Ecocentrism: De-emphasizing Stability and Defending Wildness," Environmental Ethics 21 (1999): 12. I am in essential agreement with them that "emphasizing wildness provides the most promising general strategy for defending ecocentric ethics" even as I resist their using wildness as a means of finding intrinsic value in natural systems (p. 12).
    • (1999) Environmental Ethics , vol.21 , pp. 12
    • Hettinger, N.1    Throop, B.2
  • 72
    • 84872850036 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Prescriptions for health, the environmental kind
    • 11 August
    • Amanda Schaffer, "Prescriptions for Health, the Environmental Kind," The New York Times, 11 August 2008, at http://www.nytimes.com/2008/ 08/12/health/12clin.html?-r=1&emc=etal.
    • (2008) The New York Times
    • Schaffer, A.1
  • 73
    • 0008423947 scopus 로고
    • Moral considerability and universal consideration
    • Tom Birch, "Moral Considerability and Universal Consideration," Environmental Ethics 15 (1993): 313-32.
    • (1993) Environmental Ethics , vol.15 , pp. 313-332
    • Birch, T.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.