메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn , Issue 3, 2005, Pages 49-64

Freedom, truth, and possibility in Foucault's Ethics

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 84891805218     PISSN: None     EISSN: 18325203     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.22439/fs.v0i3.872     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (9)

References (46)
  • 1
    • 0141508606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Introduction: The history of systems of thought
    • Michel Foucault, ed. Paul Rabinow, trans. Robert Hurley and others (New York: The New Press,)
    • Paul Rabinow, "Introduction: The History of Systems of Thought," in Michel Foucault, Ethics: Subjectivity and Truth. The Essential Works of Michel Foucault 1954 - 1984, ed. Paul Rabinow, trans. Robert Hurley and others (New York: The New Press, 1997), xxvi.
    • (1997) Ethics: Subjectivity and Truth. The Essential Works of Michel Foucault 1954 - 1984
    • Rabinow, P.1
  • 2
    • 0008205517 scopus 로고
    • The final foucault and his ethics
    • Autumn
    • Paul Veyne, "The Final Foucault and his Ethics." Critical Inquiry 20 (Autumn 1993), 2.
    • (1993) Critical Inquiry , vol.20 , pp. 2
    • Veyne, P.1
  • 3
    • 44849134384 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the genealogy of ethics: An overview of work in progress
    • Foucault
    • Michel Foucault, "On the genealogy of ethics: an overview of work in progress", in Foucault, Ethics, 266, my emphasis.
    • Ethics , pp. 266
    • Foucault, M.1
  • 6
    • 0004213487 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Pantheon
    • As he himself famously put it in the Introduction to The Use of Pleasure, trans. Robert Hurley (New York: Pantheon, 1985), 8: "As for what motivated me, it is quite simple; I would hope that in the eyes of some people it might be sufficient. It was curiosity - the only kind of curiosity, in any case, that is worth acting upon with a degree of obstinacy: not the curiosity that seeks to assimilate what it is proper for one to know, but that which enables one to get free of oneself.
    • (1985) The Use of Pleasure , pp. 8
    • Hurley, R.1
  • 7
    • 84871514432 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Le sujet ancien d'une éthique moderne. À propos des exercices spirituels anciens dans l'Histoire de la sexualité de Michel Foucault
    • Frédéric Gros (coor.) (Paris : Presses universitaires de France)
    • For an excellent discussion of how Foucault's concern with "ethics" is continuous with his more explicitly political considerations, cf. Jean-François Pradeau, "Le sujet ancien d'une éthique moderne. À propos des exercices spirituels anciens dans l'Histoire de la sexualité de Michel Foucault" in Frédéric Gros (coor.) Foucault : le courage de la vérité (Paris : Presses universitaires de France, 2002), 131-154. Pradeau also makes the case that Foucault was perhaps less successful in this exploration than is sometimes assumed by his supporters.
    • (2002) Foucault : Le Courage de la Vérité , pp. 131-154
    • Pradeau, J.-F.1
  • 8
    • 18844374109 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • " Todd May, "philosophy as a spiritual exercise in foucault and deleuze
    • August
    • May quite convincingly argues, it seems to me, that if we return to Foucault's histories - especially Madness and Civilization and Discipline and Punish - it is because they do not only instruct us about past practices and thereby throw light on present practices; they actually serve "as reminders of who we are and how we got to be that way, and, even more important, of the contingency of both. We might return to Foucault's histories for much the same reason Marcus Aurelius returns to the truths of Stoicism in his meditations: to keep calling ourselves back to what we need to remember in order to construct a meaningful life in a world that often pulls us in unhelpful directions." Todd May, "Philosophy as a Spiritual Exercise in Foucault and Deleuze." Angelaki: Journal of the Theoretical Humanities, Vol. 5, No. 2 (August 2000), 227.
    • (2000) Angelaki: Journal of the Theoretical Humanities , vol.5 , Issue.2 , pp. 227
  • 9
    • 29144501554 scopus 로고
    • Beyond good and evil: The ethical sensibility of michel foucault
    • Cf., William E. Connolly, "Beyond Good and Evil: The Ethical Sensibility of Michel Foucault," Political Theory, Vol. 21, No. 3 (1993), 365-389
    • (1993) Political Theory , vol.21 , Issue.3 , pp. 365-389
    • Connolly, W.E.1
  • 10
    • 0004236696 scopus 로고
    • Minneapolis: The University of Minnesota Press
    • as well as The Ethos of Pluralization. (Minneapolis: The University of Minnesota Press, 1995). It should be mentioned that the "sensibility" Connolly articulates is as much inspired by Nietzsche as it is by Foucault, such that it describes less a "Foucauldianism" than, as Connolly himself puts it, a "Fou-connoism." (368) Needless to say, this is no way diminishes its significance and importance.
    • (1995) The Ethos of Pluralization
  • 12
    • 84891788765 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The sense Badiou gives to nihilism has to do with the way contemporary "ethics," in its dismissal of both the precedence of Good over Evil and the affirmation of Truths, merely focuses its efforts on suffering and death. For a good discussion of how Badiou's work can be seen as intersecting with Foucault's, cf., David Pekerow, "The Evental Site of Resistance: Badiou as Supplement to Foucault." www.sspp.us/Protected-Essays/2004-APA- Pekerow.doc
    • The Evental Site of Resistance: Badiou As Supplement to Foucault
    • Pekerow, D.1
  • 13
    • 0011674860 scopus 로고
    • What is enlightenment?
    • ed. Lewis White Beck, (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill Educational Publishing)
    • Immanuel Kant, "What is Enlightenment?" in Kant On History, ed. Lewis White Beck, (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill Educational Publishing, 1963), 3-10.
    • (1963) Kant on History , pp. 3-10
    • Kant, I.1
  • 16
    • 0039903845 scopus 로고
    • (New York: Routledge), especially
    • Foucault, of course, is hardly alone in this; for a good discussion of how Foucault's concern with ethics relates to Lacan's similar critique of Kant, cf., John Rajchman, Truth and Eros: Foucault, Lacan, and the Question of Ethics. (New York: Routledge, 1991), especially, 55-61.
    • (1991) Truth and Eros: Foucault, Lacan, and the Question of Ethics , pp. 55-61
    • Rajchman, J.1
  • 17
    • 0004213487 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. Robert Hurley. (New York: Pantheon)
    • Michel Foucault, The Use of Pleasure, trans. Robert Hurley. (New York: Pantheon, 1985).
    • (1985) The Use of Pleasure
    • Foucault, M.1
  • 18
    • 84856479386 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Foucault on history and the self
    • For a more extensive discussion of the arguments in the last two volumes of The History of Sexuality in connection with the themes of this paper, cf., my "Foucault on History and the Self." Laval Théologique et Philosophique, Vol. 54, No. 1 (1998), 143-162.
    • (1998) Laval Théologique et Philosophique , vol.54 , Issue.1 , pp. 143-162
  • 23
    • 0004195469 scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge: Harvard University Press), especially chapter 10
    • Cf.,Bernard Williams, Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1985), especially chapter 10.
    • (1985) Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy
    • Williams, B.1
  • 24
    • 84970771148 scopus 로고
    • Foucault on freedom and truth
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Charles Taylor, "Foucault on Freedom and Truth," in Philosophy and the Human Sciences: Philosophical Papers 2 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985), 152-184;
    • (1985) Philosophy and the Human Sciences: Philosophical Papers , vol.2 , pp. 152-184
    • Taylor, C.1
  • 27
    • 84891770188 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Affirming the political: Tragic affirmations versus gothic displacements
    • edited by Jane Bennett and Michael J. Shapiro, (New York: Routledge)
    • Michael J. Shapiro, "Affirming the Political: Tragic Affirmations versus Gothic Displacements," in The Politics of Moralizing, edited by Jane Bennett and Michael J. Shapiro, (New York: Routledge, 2002), 237.
    • (2002) The Politics of Moralizing , pp. 237
    • Shapiro, M.J.1
  • 28
    • 60950523360 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Foucault after hyppolite: Toward an a-theistic theodicy
    • Placing Foucault within a Hegelian orbit will no doubt be hotly contested by many Foucauldians (including Connolly), but I think needlessly so. Foucault is not Deleuze; his unflagging commitment to a thinking informed by history cannot help maintaining some common ground with Hegel. I develop some of this common ground in my "Foucault after Hyppolite: Toward an A-theistic Theodicy." The Southern Journal of Philosophy, Vol XLIII, no. 1 (2005), 79-93.
    • (2005) The Southern Journal of Philosophy , vol.43 , Issue.1 , pp. 79-93
  • 29
    • 0004250031 scopus 로고
    • trans. A. Sheridan. (New York: Random House)
    • Michel Foucault, The Order of Things, trans. A. Sheridan. (New York: Random House, 1970).
    • (1970) The Order of Things
    • Foucault, M.1
  • 31
    • 0004226456 scopus 로고
    • trans. A.V. Miller (Atlantic Highlands: Humanities Press International, Inc.)
    • in Hegel's Science of Logic, trans. A.V. Miller (Atlantic Highlands: Humanities Press International, Inc., 1989), 541-550.
    • (1989) Science of Logic , pp. 541-550
    • Hegel1
  • 34
    • 79951873080 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I should note immediately that the appeal to Hegel here is not the appeal that Žižek calls the "pseudo-Hegelian" critique, which in fact is not an advance on Kant as far as thinking through "ethics" is concerned. He writes: "According to the standard pseudo-Hegelian critique, the Kantian universalist ethic of the categorical imperative fails to take into account the concrete historical situation in which the subject is embedded, and which provides the determinate content of the Good: what eludes Kantian formalism is the historically specified particular Substance of ethical life. However, this reproach can be countered by claiming that the unique strength of Kant's ethics resides in this very formal indeterminacy: moral Law does not tell me what my duty is, it merely tells me that I should accomplish my duty, i.e., it is not possible to derive the concrete norms I have to follow in my specific situation from the moral Law itself-which means that the subject himself has to assume the responsibility of "translating" the abstract injunction of the moral Law into a series of concrete obligations." Slavoj Žižek, "Kant and Sade: The Ideal Couple." http://www.egs.edu/faculty/zizek/zizek-kant-and-sade-the-ideal-couple.html
    • Kant and Sade: The Ideal Couple
    • Žižek, S.1
  • 35
    • 61149387105 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Naturalness and mindedness: Hegel's compatibilism
    • For good discussions of this reading, see Robert B. Pippin, "Naturalness and Mindedness: Hegel's Compatibilism." European Journal of Philosophy 7:2 (1999), 194-212;
    • (1999) European Journal of Philosophy , vol.7 , Issue.2 , pp. 194-212
    • Pippin, R.B.1
  • 36
    • 61149330810 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Virtues, morality, and sittlichkeit: From maxims to practices
    • Terry Pinkard, "Virtues, Morality, and Sittlichkeit: From Maxims to Practices." European Journal of Philosophy 7:2 (1999), 217-238;
    • (1999) European Journal of Philosophy , vol.7 , Issue.2 , pp. 217-238
    • Pinkard, T.1
  • 37
    • 33748929596 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some pragmatist themes in Hegel's idealism
    • and Robert Brandom, "Some Pragmatist Themes in Hegel's Idealism." European Journal of Philosophy 7:2 (1999), 164-189.
    • (1999) European Journal of Philosophy , vol.7 , Issue.2 , pp. 164-189
    • Brandom, R.1
  • 39
    • 84998146017 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Freedom and recognition in Hegel and Habermas
    • The "paradox" is nicely captured by Kenneth Baynes in the following questions: "Doesn't a rule have to have a certain independence from my own will in order to bind my will? And if rules are thus independent doesn't that constitute a form of heteronomy?" Kenneth Baynes, "Freedom and Recognition in Hegel and Habermas." Philosophy & Social Criticism 28:1 (2002), 4.
    • (2002) Philosophy & Social Criticism , vol.28 , Issue.1 , pp. 4
    • Baynes, K.1
  • 41
    • 33845624020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Agency and institutional rationality: Foucault's critique of normativity
    • For a good discussion of Foucault's analytics of power as they relate to questions of normativity, cf., Kory P. Schaff, "Agency and Institutional Rationality: Foucault's Critique of Normativity." Philosophy & Social Criticism, Vol. 30, No. 1 (2004), 51-71.
    • (2004) Philosophy & Social Criticism , vol.30 , Issue.1 , pp. 51-71
    • Schaff, K.P.1
  • 42
    • 0000087006 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The subject and power
    • ed. James D. Faubion (New York: The New Press)
    • Foucault is explicit about the connection between power and freedom: "Power is exercised only over free subjects, and only insofar as they are "free." By this we mean individual or collective subjects who are faced with a field of possibilities in which several kinds of conduct, several ways of reacting and modes of behavior are available. Where the determining factors are exhaustive, there is no relationship of power: slavery is not a power relationship when a man is in chains, only when he has some possible mobility, even a chance of escape. (In this case it is a question of a physical relationship of constraint.) Consequently, there is not a face-to-face confrontation of power and freedom as mutually exclusive facts (freedom disappearing everywhere power is exercised), but a much more complicated interplay. In this game, freedom may well appear as the condition for the exercise of power (at the same time its precondition, since freedom must exist for power to be exerted, and also its permanent support, since without the possibility of recalcitrance power would be equivalent to a physical determination)." Michel Foucault, "The Subject and Power," Power: Essential Works of Foucault, 1954-1984, Vol. 3, ed. James D. Faubion (New York: The New Press, 2000), 342.
    • (2000) Power: Essential Works of Foucault, 1954-1984 , vol.3 , pp. 342
    • Foucault, M.1
  • 43
    • 0347378348 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "What is the question for which Hegel's "the theory of recognition is the answer?
    • Compare Foucault's use of the notion of freedom here with Pippin's reading of Hegel: "freedom is understood by Hegel to involve a certain sort of self-relation and a certain sort of relation to others; it is constituted by being in a certain self-regarding and a certain mutually related state. Such states are active, involve deeds and practices, but are understood to be free by being undertaken in certain ways, not by having some special causal conditions." Robert B. Pippin, "What is the Question for which Hegel's "The Theory of Recognition is the Answer?" European Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 8, No. 2 (2000), 156. I don't think it is much of a stretch to see in Foucault's "ethics" a movement of thought that resembles that of this "non-metaphysical" Hegel. If Foucault resists the notion of a state of "recognition," it is no doubt because it still rings too much of "reconciliation" with what is, something his commitment to "possibility" leads him to challenge. The emphasis on the constitutive role of events within this ontological/historical approach can also lead to a more sustained discussion of Badiou. However, I must leave that for another time.
    • (2000) European Journal of Philosophy , vol.8 , Issue.2 , pp. 156
    • Pippin, R.B.1
  • 44
    • 84891769540 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Here is a sample of discussions showing Foucault's relevance to various institutional and practical dynamics: for health care and bioethics, cf., the special issue of the Journal of Medical Humanities, Vol. 24, Nos. 3-4 (2003);
    • (2003) Journal of Medical Humanities , vol.24 , Issue.3-4


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.