메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 40, Issue 3, 2009, Pages 412-433

The most stable just regime

(1)  Hussain, Waheed a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 84886653383     PISSN: 00472786     EISSN: 14679833     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1467-9833.2009.01460.x     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (18)

References (60)
  • 1
  • 2
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • revised edition Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Rawls sometimes says that where social justice is silent, practical considerations should guide us. In A Theory of Justice, for example, he says that the principles of justice as fairness are compatible with both public and private ownership of the means of production, so the choice between these alternatives should be made in light of a practical assessment of society's actual "circumstances, institutions, and historical traditions" (John Rawls, A Theory of Justice, revised edition [Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999], 248).
    • (1999) A Theory of Justice , pp. 248
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 3
    • 0003836741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But Rawls also acknowledges that more substantive considerations may figure into our reasoning when justice itself is silent. In Justice as Fairness, Rawls considers the Marxist view that a POD is objectionable because it does not give prominence to democratic forms of government in the firm or the economy more generally. His response is not that practical considerations should decide the issue, but that considerations of stability may be relevant here: Would there be advantages from [subsidizing worker-managed firms] that could be justified in terms of the political values expressed by justice as fairness [...]? For example, would worker-managed firms be more likely to encourage the democratic political virtues needed for a constitutional regime to endure? If so, could greater democracy within capitalist firms achieve much the same result? I shall not pursue these questions. I have no idea of the answers, but certainly these questions call for careful examination. The long-run prospects of a just constitutional regime may depend on them. (Rawls, Justice as Fairness, 178-79).
    • Justice as Fairness , pp. 178-179
    • Rawls1
  • 4
    • 0008423944 scopus 로고
    • Equal liberty and unequal worth of liberty
    • ed. Norman Daniels Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press
    • For more radically egalitarian interpretations of Rawls's theory, see Norman Daniels, "Equal Liberty and Unequal Worth of Liberty," in Reading Rawls, ed. Norman Daniels (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1989)
    • (1989) Reading Rawls
    • Daniels, N.1
  • 5
    • 0039410279 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Against rawlsian equality of opportunity
    • Richard Arneson, "Against Rawlsian Equality of Opportunity," Philosophical Studies 93 (1999), 77-112.
    • (1999) Philosophical Studies , vol.93 , pp. 77-112
    • Arneson, R.1
  • 6
    • 41849140554 scopus 로고
    • Democratic equality
    • July
    • Joshua Cohen offers a somewhat less radical egalitarian reading in Joshua Cohen, "Democratic Equality," Ethics 99 (July 1989): 727-51.
    • (1989) Ethics , vol.99 , pp. 727-751
    • Cohen, J.1
  • 7
    • 50849093627 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • G. A. Cohen criticizes Rawls's theory for allowing incentive considerations to justify potentially large inequalities-see his Rescuing Justice and Equality (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2008).
    • (2008) Rescuing Justice and Equality
  • 8
    • 1442354989 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Difference principles
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • For an overview of various interpretive disagreements, see Philippe Van Parijs, "Difference Principles," in The Cambridge Companion to Rawls (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003).
    • (2003) The Cambridge Companion to Rawls
    • Van Parijs, P.1
  • 9
    • 84888858341 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls's theory of justice
    • For a notable, early exception, see T. M. Scanlon, "Rawls's Theory of Justice," in Reading Rawls, 204.
    • Reading Rawls , pp. 204
    • Scanlon, T.M.1
  • 10
    • 84926359637 scopus 로고
    • Still the century of corporatism?
    • January
    • My account of the democratic corporatist POD follows the main points of Philippe Schmitter's definition of corporatism: Corporatism canbedefinedasasystemofinterest representationinwhich the constituent units are organized into a limited number of singular, compulsory, noncompetitive, hierarchically ordered and functionally differentiated categories, recognized or licensed (if not created) by the state and granted a deliberate representational monopoly within their respective categories in exchange for observing certain controls on their selection of leaders and articulation of demands and supports. (Philippe Schmitter, "Still the Century of Corporatism?" The Review of Politics 36/1 [January 1974], 93-94.)
    • (1974) The Review of Politics , vol.36 , Issue.1 , pp. 93-94
    • Schmitter, P.1
  • 11
    • 0003002569 scopus 로고
    • Reflections on where the theory of neo-corporatism has gone and where the praxis of neo-corporatism may be going
    • ed. Gerhard Lehmbruch and Philipppe Schmitter London: Sage Publications
    • My account departs from Schmitter's and other mainstream accounts of corporatism in two important respects. First, corporatism, as I understand it, can operate at levels below that of the state. Schmitter, by contrast, understands corporatism primarily as a modeof interest representation atthe level of the state. (See Philippe Schmitter, "Reflections on Where the Theory of Neo-Corporatism Has Gone and Where the Praxis of Neo-Corporatism May Be Going," in Patterns of Corporatist Policy-Making, ed. Gerhard Lehmbruch and Philipppe Schmitter [London: Sage Publications, 1982], 262-64.)
    • (1982) Patterns of Corporatist Policy-Making , pp. 262-264
    • Schmitter, P.1
  • 12
    • 0002538538 scopus 로고
    • Interest intermediation and regime governability in contemporary western europe and north America
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • He expresses a similar view in "Interest Intermediation and Regime Governability in Contemporary Western Europe and North America," in Organizing Interests in Western Europe: Pluralism, Corporatism and the Transformation of Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981).
    • (1981) Organizing Interests in Western Europe: Pluralism, Corporatism and the Transformation of Politics
  • 13
    • 0011276489 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Introduction: Neo-corporatism in comparative perspective
    • On his view, union representation on corporate boards would not obviously count as a form of corporatism. Gerhard Lehmbruch, another prominent theorist, also understands corporatism as operating primarily at the level of the state. On his view, corporatism involves a distinctive mode of economic decision making only insofar as the state enlists organized interests to help in designing and implementing its policies on wages, regional development and so on. (See Gerhard Lehmbruch, "Introduction: Neo-Corporatism in Comparative Perspective," in Patterns of Corporatist Policy Making, 1-28.)
    • Patterns of Corporatist Policy Making , pp. 1-28
    • Lehmbruch, G.1
  • 14
    • 0004080792 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Basil Blackwell
    • Again, this would seem to exclude union representation on corporate boards as a form of corporatism. My account follows most contemporary theorists, who do not see corporatism as an exclusively state-level phenomenon. (See, for instance, Alan Cawson, Corporatism and Political Theory [Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1986];
    • (1986) Corporatism and Political Theory
    • Cawson, A.1
  • 16
    • 1642551484 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Berkeley: University of California Press
    • Harold Wilensky, Rich Democracies [Berkeley: University of California Press, 2002].) The other major difference is that democratic corporatism, as I understand it, requires that the relevant parties deliberate with each other about appropriate laws and policies, while most theorists understand democratic corporatism as involving some form of bargaining. I take it that this difference reflects the fact that mainstream theorists of corporatism are not looking to describe an ideal arrangement, but rather to describe an arrangement that actually exists in many countries around the world.
    • (2002) Rich Democracies
    • Wilensky, H.1
  • 17
    • 0002658765 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Deliberation and democratic legitimacy
    • ed. James Bohman and William Rehg Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
    • For the distinction between deliberation and bargaining, see Joshua Cohen, "Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy," in Deliberative Democracy, ed. James Bohman and William Rehg (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1997);
    • (1997) Deliberative Democracy
    • Cohen, J.1
  • 19
    • 0004294588 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, Democracyand Disagreement(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996). I takeit that the process that leads to an agreement is a "deliberation" when: (i) each party wants to adopt an arrangement that promotes his own interests but also gives fair consideration to the interests of others; and (ii) each party attempts to convince the others to adopt a certain arrangement by presenting arguments that show that the arrangement advances everyone's interests in a fair way. Sometimes people will find themselves in a situation in which benefits to one party can only come at the cost of greater burdens for another. Wage negotiations, for example, sometimes reach a point where higher wages for workers can only comeatthe costoflower returns for shareholders and vice versa. The reasoning process that leads to a wage agreement in this situation would count as deliberative so long as the parties seek to find an arrangement that advances everyone's interests in a fair way and they try to convince each other through reasoned argument that a certain proposal fits the bill. A deliberation in this context would take the familiar form of a discussion-sometimes a heated argument-about which of several different divisions of benefits and burdens is fair (or most fair).
    • (1996) Democracyand Disagreement
    • Gutmann, A.1    Thompson, D.2
  • 20
    • 0042721739 scopus 로고
    • Codetermination by workers in german enterprise
    • For the basic features of the codetermination system, see Herbert Wiedemann, "Codetermination by Workers in German Enterprise," The American Journal of Comparative Law 28 (1980): 79-82;
    • (1980) The American Journal of Comparative Law , vol.28 , pp. 79-82
    • Wiedemann, H.1
  • 21
    • 0001928383 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Varieties of corporate governance: Comparing Germany and the U.K.
    • ed. Peter A. Hall and David Soskice Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Sigurt Vitols, "Varieties of Corporate Governance: Comparing Germany and the U.K.," in Varieties of Capitalism, ed. Peter A. Hall and David Soskice (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001), 337-60;
    • (2001) Varieties of Capitalism , pp. 337-360
    • Vitols, S.1
  • 25
    • 0004221970 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • John Roemer, A Future for Socialism (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1994).
    • (1994) A Future for Socialism
    • Roemer, J.1
  • 26
    • 45949096333 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Routledge
    • I would argue that Rawls's sketch of a POD also represents a version of the dispersion of ownership approach. Some interpreters read Rawls as being committed to more than dispersion: see Samuel Freeman, Rawls (New York: Routledge, 2007), 219-35.
    • (2007) Rawls , pp. 219-235
    • Freeman, S.1
  • 27
    • 85164856522 scopus 로고
    • Berkeley: University of California Press
    • For some examples of the worker management approach, see Robert Dahl, A Preface to Economic Democracy (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1985);
    • (1985) A Preface to Economic Democracy
    • Dahl, R.1
  • 31
    • 0040981156 scopus 로고
    • Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press
    • Jaroslav Vanek, The Participatory Economy (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1971).
    • (1971) The Participatory Economy
    • Vanek, J.1
  • 32
    • 0003846902 scopus 로고
    • Edison, NJ: Transaction Publishers
    • Shareholders in our society are typically passive and lack the tools effectively to shape the decisions of managers, so it is not clear that expanding the class of owners would substantially change how decisions are made in the economy. The classic discussion of the conflict between shareholders and managers is Adolph Berle and Gardiner Means, The Modern Corporation and Private Property (Edison, NJ: Transaction Publishers, 1991).
    • (1991) The Modern Corporation and Private Property
    • Berle, A.1    Means, G.2
  • 33
    • 84972219071 scopus 로고
    • Associations and democracy
    • Summer
    • Joshua Cohen and Joel Rogers, "Associations and Democracy," Social Philosophy and Policy 10/2 (Summer 1993): 282-312;
    • (1993) Social Philosophy and Policy , vol.10 , Issue.2 , pp. 282-312
    • Cohen, J.1    Rogers, J.2
  • 35
    • 0004233737 scopus 로고
    • Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press
    • Paul Hirst Associative Democracy (Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1994).
    • (1994) Associative Democracy
    • Hirst, P.1
  • 36
    • 84871275903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Associationalism is, in this regard, closer in spirit to Habermas's theory, which stresses the need for an active, dynamic, and engaged civil society. (See Habermas, Between Facts and Norms.)
    • Between Facts and Norms
    • Habermas1
  • 37
    • 33748805993 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Civil society meets the state: Towards associational democracy?
    • May
    • For a helpful discussion of the relationship between associationalism and mainstream corporatism, see Lucio Baccaro, "Civil Society Meets the State: Towards Associational Democracy?" Socio-Economic Review 4/2 (May 2006), 185-208.
    • (2006) Socio-Economic Review , vol.4 , Issue.2 , pp. 185-208
    • Baccaro, L.1
  • 38
    • 84871647310 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Here I adapt Rawls's description of a stable equilibrium state. See Rawls, A Theory of Justice, 399-401.
    • A Theory of Justice , pp. 399-401
    • Rawls1
  • 39
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고
    • New York: Columbia University Press
    • See Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993), 143-44
    • (1993) Political Liberalism , pp. 143-144
    • Rawls1
  • 40
    • 26444488766 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Congruence and the good of justice
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • For an excellent discussion of the role that Political Liberalism plays in Rawls's overall account of stability, see Samuel Freeman, "Congruence and the Good of Justice," in The Cambridge Companion to Rawls (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003), 277-315.
    • (2003) The Cambridge Companion to Rawls , pp. 277-315
    • Freeman, S.1
  • 41
    • 0038080436 scopus 로고
    • ed. J. P. Mayer New York: Harper & Rowe
    • Immersion in associational life has important features in common with the condition that Alexis de Tocqueville calls "individualism." See Alexis de Tocqueville, Democracy in America, ed. J. P. Mayer (New York: Harper & Rowe, 1969), 506.
    • (1969) Democracy in America , pp. 506
    • De Tocqueville, A.1
  • 43
    • 84888873674 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The federalist no. 10
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • James Madison famously discusses the problem of faction in Federalist 10. He argues that a large and diverse democracy is less susceptible to the dangers posed by unjust factions because it is harder for any kind of majority coalition to emerge and make changes to the laws in a society where there are many different groups with very different goals and values. (See James Madison, "The Federalist No. 10," in The Federalist [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003], 40-46). Madison does not pay much attention to the danger posed by unjust minority factions because he believes that majoritarian institutions will limit the impact of minority groups. But, as I have argued, there are many examples in the twentieth century of minority factions that were able to advance unjust legislative agendas because society was in a relatively disaggregated condition. Democratic corporatism addresses the danger posed by minority factions by empowering more groups in society to assert themselves in the political forum, thereby making it harder for any minority group to advance its agenda when the rest of society disapproves.
    • (2003) The Federalist , pp. 40-46
    • Madison, J.1
  • 45
    • 0002440930 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Secondary associations and democratic governance
    • Cohen and Rogers also emphasize the importance of taking measures to foster the right kind of secondary associations in civil society. See Cohen and Rogers, "Secondary Associations and Democratic Governance," in Associations and Democracy, 7-98.
    • Associations and Democracy , pp. 7-98
    • Cohen1    Rogers2
  • 48
    • 0003710981 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • For an overview of recent findings (with an emphasis on Europe), see: Continuity and Change in Contemporary Capitalism, ed. Herbert Kitschelt et al. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999);
    • (1999) Continuity and Change in Contemporary Capitalism
    • Kitschelt, H.1
  • 51
    • 0002769727 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Divergent production regimes: Coordinated and uncoordinated market economies in the 1980s and 1990s
    • One important conclusion that emerges from several studies is that globalization does not seem to be producing a convergence in economic systems toward some form of liberal market capitalism. Corporatist mechanisms of coordination have evolved in the face of globalization, but they have not collapsed. So if globalization strengthens the bargaining power of capital, it does not do so in a way that leads to the destruction of corporatist coordination. There are many explanations for why these mechanisms have persisted. One prominent explanation is that corporatist institutions create an economic opportunity for firms because these institutions lead to an environment that is more conducive to a competitive strategy based on producing diverse, high-quality goods. See David Soskice, "Divergent Production Regimes: Coordinated and Uncoordinated Market Economies in the 1980s and 1990s," in Continuity and Change in Contemporary Capitalism;
    • Continuity and Change in Contemporary Capitalism
    • Soskice, D.1
  • 53
    • 84888882386 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Berkeley: University of California Press chap. 17
    • Harold Wilensky, Rich Societies (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2002), chap. 17.
    • (2002) Rich Societies
    • Wilensky, H.1
  • 55
    • 0004100179 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New Haven, CT: Yale University Press chap. 16
    • See Arend Lijphart, Patterns of Democracy (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1999), chap. 16.
    • (1999) Patterns of Democracy
    • Lijphart, A.1
  • 56
    • 1642551484 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Another comprehensive assessment of the social consequences of corporatism is Wilensky, Rich Democracies.
    • Rich Democracies
    • Wilensky1
  • 57
    • 0003453395 scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • The classic study of democracy in town councils is Jane Mansbridge, Beyond Adversary Democracy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983).
    • (1983) Beyond Adversary Democracy
    • Mansbridge, J.1
  • 58
    • 84883923065 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • For a discussion of local school councils and community-based policing, see Archon Fung, Empowered Participation: Reinventing Urban Democracy (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2004).
    • (2004) Empowered Participation: Reinventing Urban Democracy
    • Fung, A.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.