-
1
-
-
0003836741
-
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
John Rawls, Justice as Fairness: A Restatement (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2001), 178-79.
-
(2001)
Justice as Fairness: A Restatement
, pp. 178-179
-
-
Rawls, J.1
-
2
-
-
0004048289
-
-
revised edition Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
Rawls sometimes says that where social justice is silent, practical considerations should guide us. In A Theory of Justice, for example, he says that the principles of justice as fairness are compatible with both public and private ownership of the means of production, so the choice between these alternatives should be made in light of a practical assessment of society's actual "circumstances, institutions, and historical traditions" (John Rawls, A Theory of Justice, revised edition [Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999], 248).
-
(1999)
A Theory of Justice
, pp. 248
-
-
Rawls, J.1
-
3
-
-
0003836741
-
-
But Rawls also acknowledges that more substantive considerations may figure into our reasoning when justice itself is silent. In Justice as Fairness, Rawls considers the Marxist view that a POD is objectionable because it does not give prominence to democratic forms of government in the firm or the economy more generally. His response is not that practical considerations should decide the issue, but that considerations of stability may be relevant here: Would there be advantages from [subsidizing worker-managed firms] that could be justified in terms of the political values expressed by justice as fairness [...]? For example, would worker-managed firms be more likely to encourage the democratic political virtues needed for a constitutional regime to endure? If so, could greater democracy within capitalist firms achieve much the same result? I shall not pursue these questions. I have no idea of the answers, but certainly these questions call for careful examination. The long-run prospects of a just constitutional regime may depend on them. (Rawls, Justice as Fairness, 178-79).
-
Justice as Fairness
, pp. 178-179
-
-
Rawls1
-
4
-
-
0008423944
-
Equal liberty and unequal worth of liberty
-
ed. Norman Daniels Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press
-
For more radically egalitarian interpretations of Rawls's theory, see Norman Daniels, "Equal Liberty and Unequal Worth of Liberty," in Reading Rawls, ed. Norman Daniels (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1989)
-
(1989)
Reading Rawls
-
-
Daniels, N.1
-
5
-
-
0039410279
-
Against rawlsian equality of opportunity
-
Richard Arneson, "Against Rawlsian Equality of Opportunity," Philosophical Studies 93 (1999), 77-112.
-
(1999)
Philosophical Studies
, vol.93
, pp. 77-112
-
-
Arneson, R.1
-
6
-
-
41849140554
-
Democratic equality
-
July
-
Joshua Cohen offers a somewhat less radical egalitarian reading in Joshua Cohen, "Democratic Equality," Ethics 99 (July 1989): 727-51.
-
(1989)
Ethics
, vol.99
, pp. 727-751
-
-
Cohen, J.1
-
7
-
-
50849093627
-
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
G. A. Cohen criticizes Rawls's theory for allowing incentive considerations to justify potentially large inequalities-see his Rescuing Justice and Equality (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2008).
-
(2008)
Rescuing Justice and Equality
-
-
-
8
-
-
1442354989
-
Difference principles
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
For an overview of various interpretive disagreements, see Philippe Van Parijs, "Difference Principles," in The Cambridge Companion to Rawls (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003).
-
(2003)
The Cambridge Companion to Rawls
-
-
Van Parijs, P.1
-
9
-
-
84888858341
-
Rawls's theory of justice
-
For a notable, early exception, see T. M. Scanlon, "Rawls's Theory of Justice," in Reading Rawls, 204.
-
Reading Rawls
, pp. 204
-
-
Scanlon, T.M.1
-
10
-
-
84926359637
-
Still the century of corporatism?
-
January
-
My account of the democratic corporatist POD follows the main points of Philippe Schmitter's definition of corporatism: Corporatism canbedefinedasasystemofinterest representationinwhich the constituent units are organized into a limited number of singular, compulsory, noncompetitive, hierarchically ordered and functionally differentiated categories, recognized or licensed (if not created) by the state and granted a deliberate representational monopoly within their respective categories in exchange for observing certain controls on their selection of leaders and articulation of demands and supports. (Philippe Schmitter, "Still the Century of Corporatism?" The Review of Politics 36/1 [January 1974], 93-94.)
-
(1974)
The Review of Politics
, vol.36
, Issue.1
, pp. 93-94
-
-
Schmitter, P.1
-
11
-
-
0003002569
-
Reflections on where the theory of neo-corporatism has gone and where the praxis of neo-corporatism may be going
-
ed. Gerhard Lehmbruch and Philipppe Schmitter London: Sage Publications
-
My account departs from Schmitter's and other mainstream accounts of corporatism in two important respects. First, corporatism, as I understand it, can operate at levels below that of the state. Schmitter, by contrast, understands corporatism primarily as a modeof interest representation atthe level of the state. (See Philippe Schmitter, "Reflections on Where the Theory of Neo-Corporatism Has Gone and Where the Praxis of Neo-Corporatism May Be Going," in Patterns of Corporatist Policy-Making, ed. Gerhard Lehmbruch and Philipppe Schmitter [London: Sage Publications, 1982], 262-64.)
-
(1982)
Patterns of Corporatist Policy-Making
, pp. 262-264
-
-
Schmitter, P.1
-
12
-
-
0002538538
-
Interest intermediation and regime governability in contemporary western europe and north America
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
He expresses a similar view in "Interest Intermediation and Regime Governability in Contemporary Western Europe and North America," in Organizing Interests in Western Europe: Pluralism, Corporatism and the Transformation of Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981).
-
(1981)
Organizing Interests in Western Europe: Pluralism, Corporatism and the Transformation of Politics
-
-
-
13
-
-
0011276489
-
Introduction: Neo-corporatism in comparative perspective
-
On his view, union representation on corporate boards would not obviously count as a form of corporatism. Gerhard Lehmbruch, another prominent theorist, also understands corporatism as operating primarily at the level of the state. On his view, corporatism involves a distinctive mode of economic decision making only insofar as the state enlists organized interests to help in designing and implementing its policies on wages, regional development and so on. (See Gerhard Lehmbruch, "Introduction: Neo-Corporatism in Comparative Perspective," in Patterns of Corporatist Policy Making, 1-28.)
-
Patterns of Corporatist Policy Making
, pp. 1-28
-
-
Lehmbruch, G.1
-
14
-
-
0004080792
-
-
Oxford: Basil Blackwell
-
Again, this would seem to exclude union representation on corporate boards as a form of corporatism. My account follows most contemporary theorists, who do not see corporatism as an exclusively state-level phenomenon. (See, for instance, Alan Cawson, Corporatism and Political Theory [Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1986];
-
(1986)
Corporatism and Political Theory
-
-
Cawson, A.1
-
16
-
-
1642551484
-
-
Berkeley: University of California Press
-
Harold Wilensky, Rich Democracies [Berkeley: University of California Press, 2002].) The other major difference is that democratic corporatism, as I understand it, requires that the relevant parties deliberate with each other about appropriate laws and policies, while most theorists understand democratic corporatism as involving some form of bargaining. I take it that this difference reflects the fact that mainstream theorists of corporatism are not looking to describe an ideal arrangement, but rather to describe an arrangement that actually exists in many countries around the world.
-
(2002)
Rich Democracies
-
-
Wilensky, H.1
-
17
-
-
0002658765
-
Deliberation and democratic legitimacy
-
ed. James Bohman and William Rehg Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
-
For the distinction between deliberation and bargaining, see Joshua Cohen, "Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy," in Deliberative Democracy, ed. James Bohman and William Rehg (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1997);
-
(1997)
Deliberative Democracy
-
-
Cohen, J.1
-
19
-
-
0004294588
-
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, Democracyand Disagreement(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996). I takeit that the process that leads to an agreement is a "deliberation" when: (i) each party wants to adopt an arrangement that promotes his own interests but also gives fair consideration to the interests of others; and (ii) each party attempts to convince the others to adopt a certain arrangement by presenting arguments that show that the arrangement advances everyone's interests in a fair way. Sometimes people will find themselves in a situation in which benefits to one party can only come at the cost of greater burdens for another. Wage negotiations, for example, sometimes reach a point where higher wages for workers can only comeatthe costoflower returns for shareholders and vice versa. The reasoning process that leads to a wage agreement in this situation would count as deliberative so long as the parties seek to find an arrangement that advances everyone's interests in a fair way and they try to convince each other through reasoned argument that a certain proposal fits the bill. A deliberation in this context would take the familiar form of a discussion-sometimes a heated argument-about which of several different divisions of benefits and burdens is fair (or most fair).
-
(1996)
Democracyand Disagreement
-
-
Gutmann, A.1
Thompson, D.2
-
20
-
-
0042721739
-
Codetermination by workers in german enterprise
-
For the basic features of the codetermination system, see Herbert Wiedemann, "Codetermination by Workers in German Enterprise," The American Journal of Comparative Law 28 (1980): 79-82;
-
(1980)
The American Journal of Comparative Law
, vol.28
, pp. 79-82
-
-
Wiedemann, H.1
-
21
-
-
0001928383
-
Varieties of corporate governance: Comparing Germany and the U.K.
-
ed. Peter A. Hall and David Soskice Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
Sigurt Vitols, "Varieties of Corporate Governance: Comparing Germany and the U.K.," in Varieties of Capitalism, ed. Peter A. Hall and David Soskice (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001), 337-60;
-
(2001)
Varieties of Capitalism
, pp. 337-360
-
-
Vitols, S.1
-
23
-
-
33646672386
-
-
Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley and Son
-
For some examples of the dispersion of ownership approach, see Gar Alperovitz, America Beyond Capitalism: Reclaiming Our Wealth, Our Liberty, and Our Democracy (Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley and Son, 2005);
-
(2005)
America Beyond Capitalism: Reclaiming our Wealth, our Liberty, and our Democracy
-
-
Alperovitz, G.1
-
25
-
-
0004221970
-
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
John Roemer, A Future for Socialism (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1994).
-
(1994)
A Future for Socialism
-
-
Roemer, J.1
-
26
-
-
45949096333
-
-
New York: Routledge
-
I would argue that Rawls's sketch of a POD also represents a version of the dispersion of ownership approach. Some interpreters read Rawls as being committed to more than dispersion: see Samuel Freeman, Rawls (New York: Routledge, 2007), 219-35.
-
(2007)
Rawls
, pp. 219-235
-
-
Freeman, S.1
-
27
-
-
85164856522
-
-
Berkeley: University of California Press
-
For some examples of the worker management approach, see Robert Dahl, A Preface to Economic Democracy (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1985);
-
(1985)
A Preface to Economic Democracy
-
-
Dahl, R.1
-
31
-
-
0040981156
-
-
Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press
-
Jaroslav Vanek, The Participatory Economy (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1971).
-
(1971)
The Participatory Economy
-
-
Vanek, J.1
-
32
-
-
0003846902
-
-
Edison, NJ: Transaction Publishers
-
Shareholders in our society are typically passive and lack the tools effectively to shape the decisions of managers, so it is not clear that expanding the class of owners would substantially change how decisions are made in the economy. The classic discussion of the conflict between shareholders and managers is Adolph Berle and Gardiner Means, The Modern Corporation and Private Property (Edison, NJ: Transaction Publishers, 1991).
-
(1991)
The Modern Corporation and Private Property
-
-
Berle, A.1
Means, G.2
-
33
-
-
84972219071
-
Associations and democracy
-
Summer
-
Joshua Cohen and Joel Rogers, "Associations and Democracy," Social Philosophy and Policy 10/2 (Summer 1993): 282-312;
-
(1993)
Social Philosophy and Policy
, vol.10
, Issue.2
, pp. 282-312
-
-
Cohen, J.1
Rogers, J.2
-
35
-
-
0004233737
-
-
Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press
-
Paul Hirst Associative Democracy (Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1994).
-
(1994)
Associative Democracy
-
-
Hirst, P.1
-
36
-
-
84871275903
-
-
Associationalism is, in this regard, closer in spirit to Habermas's theory, which stresses the need for an active, dynamic, and engaged civil society. (See Habermas, Between Facts and Norms.)
-
Between Facts and Norms
-
-
Habermas1
-
37
-
-
33748805993
-
Civil society meets the state: Towards associational democracy?
-
May
-
For a helpful discussion of the relationship between associationalism and mainstream corporatism, see Lucio Baccaro, "Civil Society Meets the State: Towards Associational Democracy?" Socio-Economic Review 4/2 (May 2006), 185-208.
-
(2006)
Socio-Economic Review
, vol.4
, Issue.2
, pp. 185-208
-
-
Baccaro, L.1
-
38
-
-
84871647310
-
-
Here I adapt Rawls's description of a stable equilibrium state. See Rawls, A Theory of Justice, 399-401.
-
A Theory of Justice
, pp. 399-401
-
-
Rawls1
-
39
-
-
0003624191
-
-
New York: Columbia University Press
-
See Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993), 143-44
-
(1993)
Political Liberalism
, pp. 143-144
-
-
Rawls1
-
40
-
-
26444488766
-
Congruence and the good of justice
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
For an excellent discussion of the role that Political Liberalism plays in Rawls's overall account of stability, see Samuel Freeman, "Congruence and the Good of Justice," in The Cambridge Companion to Rawls (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003), 277-315.
-
(2003)
The Cambridge Companion to Rawls
, pp. 277-315
-
-
Freeman, S.1
-
41
-
-
0038080436
-
-
ed. J. P. Mayer New York: Harper & Rowe
-
Immersion in associational life has important features in common with the condition that Alexis de Tocqueville calls "individualism." See Alexis de Tocqueville, Democracy in America, ed. J. P. Mayer (New York: Harper & Rowe, 1969), 506.
-
(1969)
Democracy in America
, pp. 506
-
-
De Tocqueville, A.1
-
43
-
-
84888873674
-
The federalist no. 10
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
James Madison famously discusses the problem of faction in Federalist 10. He argues that a large and diverse democracy is less susceptible to the dangers posed by unjust factions because it is harder for any kind of majority coalition to emerge and make changes to the laws in a society where there are many different groups with very different goals and values. (See James Madison, "The Federalist No. 10," in The Federalist [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003], 40-46). Madison does not pay much attention to the danger posed by unjust minority factions because he believes that majoritarian institutions will limit the impact of minority groups. But, as I have argued, there are many examples in the twentieth century of minority factions that were able to advance unjust legislative agendas because society was in a relatively disaggregated condition. Democratic corporatism addresses the danger posed by minority factions by empowering more groups in society to assert themselves in the political forum, thereby making it harder for any minority group to advance its agenda when the rest of society disapproves.
-
(2003)
The Federalist
, pp. 40-46
-
-
Madison, J.1
-
45
-
-
0002440930
-
Secondary associations and democratic governance
-
Cohen and Rogers also emphasize the importance of taking measures to foster the right kind of secondary associations in civil society. See Cohen and Rogers, "Secondary Associations and Democratic Governance," in Associations and Democracy, 7-98.
-
Associations and Democracy
, pp. 7-98
-
-
Cohen1
Rogers2
-
48
-
-
0003710981
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
For an overview of recent findings (with an emphasis on Europe), see: Continuity and Change in Contemporary Capitalism, ed. Herbert Kitschelt et al. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999);
-
(1999)
Continuity and Change in Contemporary Capitalism
-
-
Kitschelt, H.1
-
51
-
-
0002769727
-
Divergent production regimes: Coordinated and uncoordinated market economies in the 1980s and 1990s
-
One important conclusion that emerges from several studies is that globalization does not seem to be producing a convergence in economic systems toward some form of liberal market capitalism. Corporatist mechanisms of coordination have evolved in the face of globalization, but they have not collapsed. So if globalization strengthens the bargaining power of capital, it does not do so in a way that leads to the destruction of corporatist coordination. There are many explanations for why these mechanisms have persisted. One prominent explanation is that corporatist institutions create an economic opportunity for firms because these institutions lead to an environment that is more conducive to a competitive strategy based on producing diverse, high-quality goods. See David Soskice, "Divergent Production Regimes: Coordinated and Uncoordinated Market Economies in the 1980s and 1990s," in Continuity and Change in Contemporary Capitalism;
-
Continuity and Change in Contemporary Capitalism
-
-
Soskice, D.1
-
53
-
-
84888882386
-
-
Berkeley: University of California Press chap. 17
-
Harold Wilensky, Rich Societies (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2002), chap. 17.
-
(2002)
Rich Societies
-
-
Wilensky, H.1
-
55
-
-
0004100179
-
-
New Haven, CT: Yale University Press chap. 16
-
See Arend Lijphart, Patterns of Democracy (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1999), chap. 16.
-
(1999)
Patterns of Democracy
-
-
Lijphart, A.1
-
56
-
-
1642551484
-
-
Another comprehensive assessment of the social consequences of corporatism is Wilensky, Rich Democracies.
-
Rich Democracies
-
-
Wilensky1
-
57
-
-
0003453395
-
-
Chicago: University of Chicago Press
-
The classic study of democracy in town councils is Jane Mansbridge, Beyond Adversary Democracy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983).
-
(1983)
Beyond Adversary Democracy
-
-
Mansbridge, J.1
-
58
-
-
84883923065
-
-
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
-
For a discussion of local school councils and community-based policing, see Archon Fung, Empowered Participation: Reinventing Urban Democracy (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2004).
-
(2004)
Empowered Participation: Reinventing Urban Democracy
-
-
Fung, A.1
|