-
1
-
-
84882271381
-
Introduction
-
ed. Gibbons (New York: Basil Blackwell)
-
For more on the "hermeneutics of suspicion" versus those of "recovery" (which derive from Paul Ricoeur's philosophy), see: Michael Gibbons, "Introduction" in Interpreting Politics, ed. Gibbons (New York: Basil Blackwell, 1987).
-
(1987)
Interpreting Politics
-
-
Gibbons, M.1
-
2
-
-
77952992271
-
Hermeneutics
-
Summer Edition, ed. Edward N. Zalta (accessed 13 May 2012)
-
This split is also often cast in terms of the disagreement between Gadamer (advocating recovery) and Habermas (advocating suspicion): Bjørn Ramberg and Kristin Gjesdal, "Hermeneutics," The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2009 Edition), ed. Edward N. Zalta, http://plato. stanford.edu/archives/sum2009/entries/hermeneutics/ (accessed 13 May 2012).
-
(2009)
The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
-
-
Ramberg, B.1
Gjesdal, K.2
-
3
-
-
70449388473
-
-
Cambridge: Polity Press
-
Here my argument dovetails with recent scholars who have advanced important explorations of MacIntyres continuing relevance to an Aristotelian conception of politics. See, for example: Kelvin Knight, Aristotelian Philosophy: Ethics and Politics from Aristotle to MacIntyre (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2007).
-
(2007)
Aristotelian Philosophy: Ethics and Politics from Aristotle to MacIntyre
-
-
Knight, K.1
-
4
-
-
84860749420
-
-
4 Vols. (London: Sage)
-
MacIntyre is largely excluded from collections on the interpretive turn. For example: Mark Bevir, ed., Interpretive Political Science, 4 vols. (London: Sage, 2010)
-
(2010)
Interpretive Political Science
-
-
Bevir, M.1
-
5
-
-
0012464143
-
-
Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press
-
Gibbons, Interpreting Politics; David R. Hiley, James F. Bohman, and Richard Shusterman, eds., The Interpretive Turn (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1991)
-
(1991)
The Interpretive Turn
-
-
Hiley, D.R.1
Bohman, J.F.2
Shusterman, R.3
-
14
-
-
0010107827
-
Understanding a primitive society
-
Winch, The Idea of a Social Science, 117. Tellingly, Winch later criticized his own work on similar grounds. See "Preface to the Second Edition," of The Idea of a Social Science, xii. Likewise, Winch later amended his position, citing MacIntyre and arguing that the "concept of causal influence is by no means monolithic" and so might have application in both the natural and social sciences. Peter Winch, "Understanding a Primitive Society," American Philosophical Quarterly 1 (1964): 320.
-
(1964)
American Philosophical Quarterly
, vol.1
, pp. 320
-
-
Winch, P.1
-
16
-
-
0039793749
-
Causality and history
-
ed. Juha Manninen and Raimo Tuomela (Boston: D. Reidel Publishing Company)
-
Alasdair MacIntyre, "Causality and History," in his Essays on Explanation and Understanding, ed. Juha Manninen and Raimo Tuomela (Boston: D. Reidel Publishing Company, 1976), 149-50.
-
(1976)
Essays on Explanation and Understanding
, pp. 149-150
-
-
Macintyre, A.1
-
19
-
-
0004123406
-
-
3rd ed. (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press)
-
See also, Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue, 3rd ed. (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2007), 207-208.
-
(2007)
After Virtue
, pp. 207-208
-
-
Macintyre, A.1
-
23
-
-
0004058460
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, at 299
-
MacIntyres own analysis of rational versus irrational beliefs, although successfully moving past Winch's descriptivism is not without flaws. MacIntyre often ichotomizes rational explanations and "impersonal," naturalist causes in such a way that neglects a more nuanced analysis of repressed and distorted beliefs. Critics like Mark Bevir have rightly noted that the causal links in distorted beliefs might still be volitional (as opposed to naturalistic) without being either conscious or rational. See: Mark Bevir, The Logic of the History of Ideas (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), 265-308, at 299.
-
(1999)
The Logic of the History of Ideas
, pp. 265-308
-
-
Bevir, M.1
-
24
-
-
84882256524
-
Positivism, sociology and practical reasoning: Notes on durkheim's suicide
-
ed. Alan Donagan, Anthony Perovich, and Michael Wedin (Boston: D. Reidel Publishing)
-
Compare: Alasdair MacIntyre, "Positivism, Sociology and Practical Reasoning: Notes on Durkheim's Suicide," in Human Nature and Natural Knowledge, ed. Alan Donagan, Anthony Perovich, and Michael Wedin (Boston: D. Reidel Publishing, 1986), 99, 100-103.
-
(1986)
Human Nature and Natural Knowledge
, vol.99
, pp. 100-103
-
-
Macintyre, A.1
-
25
-
-
84882236667
-
-
Revised Edition (London: Routledge)
-
For a more defensible (though still incomplete) analysis of how volitional desires might distort beliefs, see MacIntyres reassessment of his early work on Freud in The Unconscious: A Conceptual Analysis, Revised Edition (London: Routledge, 2004), 2-5.
-
(2004)
The Unconscious: A Conceptual Analysis
, pp. 2-5
-
-
Freud1
-
26
-
-
0003527763
-
-
Chicago: Open Court
-
Where Winch tended to overly dichotomize natural and social science, MacIntyre made clearer the role of natural scientific explanation in establishing the physiological conditions for healthy human reasoning (e.g., in cases like injury, disease, diet, age, and so on). These conditions for the flourishing of rational human agency became a central theme of MacIntyres later moral philosophy: Alasdair MacIntyre, Dependent Rational Animals (Chicago: Open Court, 1999).
-
(1999)
Dependent Rational Animals
-
-
Macintyre, A.1
-
30
-
-
40949130317
-
Epistemological crises, dramatic narrative and the philosophy of science
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
The key essay here casts Thomas Kuhn as caught in a Winchean form of relativism and so can be read as part of an ongoing response to Winch. See: Alasdair MacIntyre, "Epistemological Crises, Dramatic Narrative and the Philosophy of Science," in his The Tasks of Philosophy: Selected Essays, Volume I (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006).
-
(2006)
The Tasks of Philosophy: Selected Essays
, vol.1
-
-
Macintyre, A.1
-
33
-
-
84867101633
-
-
Winch accepted the open-ended nature of systems of thought, arguing that the rules governing a way of life were "limited by what we have hitherto accepted" without being "uniquely determined" by them. He also considered the possibility of bridging incompatible languages by what he called a "realignment of our categories" into a third, shared language. Nevertheless, because he didn't resolve this problem theoretically, he was still forced to defend the thesis of radical incommensurability and relativism. Winch, "Understanding a Primitive Society," 317-18.
-
Understanding A Primitive Society
, pp. 317-318
-
-
Winch1
-
35
-
-
0003392316
-
-
Notre Dame IN: University of Notre Dame Press
-
Alasdair MacIntyre, Whose Justice? Which Rationality? (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1988), 359.
-
(1988)
Whose Justice? Which Rationality?
, vol.359
-
-
Macintyre, A.1
-
36
-
-
0040446232
-
Ideology, social science, and revolution
-
April
-
Alasdair MacIntyre, "Ideology, Social Science, and Revolution," Comparative Politics 5 (April, 1973): 325.
-
(1973)
Comparative Politics
, vol.5
, pp. 325
-
-
Macintyre, A.1
-
38
-
-
0010083144
-
Explanation and practical reason
-
Cambridge: Harvard University Press
-
MacIntyres line of argument here has been a major influence on Charles Taylor's hermeneutics; see: Taylor, "Explanation and Practical Reason," in Philosophical Arguments (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1995), 34-60, 54.
-
(1995)
Philosophical Arguments
, vol.34-60
, pp. 54
-
-
Taylor1
-
42
-
-
84882281931
-
-
MacIntyre has advanced an anti-technocratic critique of modern politics precisely on the basis of an interpretive philosophy of social science. Cf., After Virtue, chs. 7-8.
-
After Virtue, Chs.
, pp. 7-8
-
-
-
43
-
-
0005802077
-
The hermeneutics of conflict
-
ed. James Tully (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press)
-
Cf., Charles Taylor, "The Hermeneutics of Conflict," in Meaning and Context: Quentin Skinner and his Critics, ed. James Tully (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1988), 226.
-
(1988)
Meaning and Context: Quentin Skinner and His Critics
, vol.226
-
-
Taylor, C.1
-
44
-
-
0009157660
-
Remembering the revolution: Behavioralism in american political science
-
ed. James Farr, John Dryzek, and Stephen Leonard (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
-
For a succinct account of the behavioral revolution's relationship to the doctrine of value neutrality, see James Farr, "Remembering the Revolution: Behavioralism in American Political Science," in Political Science in History: Research Programs and Political Traditions, ed. James Farr, John Dryzek, and Stephen Leonard (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), 203, 205.
-
(1995)
Political Science in History: Research Programs and Political Traditions
, vol.203
, pp. 205
-
-
Farr, J.1
-
45
-
-
48249096230
-
Concept formation in political science: An anti-naturalist critique of qualitative methodology
-
September
-
On Sartoris commitment to descriptive neutrality, see Mark Bevir and Asaf Kedar, "Concept Formation in Political Science: An Anti-Naturalist Critique of Qualitative Methodology," Perspectives on Politics 6 (September 2008): 503-17.
-
(2008)
Perspectives on Politics
, vol.6
, pp. 503-517
-
-
Bevir, M.1
Kedar, A.2
-
46
-
-
84882280002
-
Widely used methods book
-
New York: Wadsworth
-
See also Earl Babbies widely used methods book, The Practice of Social Research (New York: Wadsworth, 1983).
-
(1983)
The Practice of Social Research
-
-
Babbies, E.1
-
47
-
-
31144479422
-
A normative turn in political science?
-
January
-
John Gerring and Joshua Yesnowitz, "A Normative Turn in Political Science?" Polity 38 (January 2006): 101-33.
-
(2006)
Polity
, vol.38
, pp. 101-133
-
-
Gerring, J.1
Yesnowitz, J.2
-
50
-
-
84882277900
-
This line of argument is echoed in Gerring's most recent book
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
This line of argument is echoed in Gerring's most recent book, Social Science: A Unified Framework (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012), 69-73.
-
(2012)
Social Science: A Unified Framework
, pp. 69-73
-
-
-
51
-
-
0003591736
-
-
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
-
Gary King, Robert Keohane, Sidney Verba, Designing Social Inquiry: Scientific Inference in Qualitative Research (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1994), 14-19.
-
(1994)
Designing Social Inquiry: Scientific Inference in Qualitative Research
, pp. 14-19
-
-
King, G.1
Keohane, R.2
Verba, S.3
-
52
-
-
84882269542
-
-
Gerring goes so far as to warn his fellow political scientists that "nothing could be more damaging to [their] discipline than an inability, or unwillingness, to distinguish between normative and empirical arguments." Gerring and Yesnowitz, "A Normative Turn in Political Science?" 121.
-
A Normative Turn in Political Science?
, vol.121
-
-
Gerring1
Yesnowitz2
-
54
-
-
33749352907
-
Quentin skinner on encountering the past
-
at 54
-
Skinner has echoed this sentiment in other recent interviews, confessing that: "moral and political motivations have always affected my choice of subjects for research [but] I very much hope that they have not affected the way in which I then approach and treat those subjects." "Quentin Skinner on Encountering the Past," by Petri Koikkalainen and Sami Syrjämäki, Finnish Yearbook of Political Thought 6: 34-63 at 54.
-
Finnish Yearbook of Political Thought
, vol.6
, pp. 34-63
-
-
Koikkalainen, P.1
Syrjämäki, S.2
-
55
-
-
85140134919
-
-
Skinner has spoken at length about this as the dilemma of "either becoming too purely instrumental or too purely antiquarian." Faced with this dilemma, he argues that the historian's "choice of what to study should be motivated by our sense of what matters here and now. We should select the subjects we study in light of their having some kind of general social significance. But having selected them, we should be as rigorous in our scholarship as we can possibly manage to be." "Intellectual History, Liberty and Republicanism: An Interview with Quentin Skinner," by Javier Fernández Sebastián, Contributions to the History of Concepts 3 (2007): 118-19.
-
(2007)
Contributions to the History of Concepts
, vol.3
, pp. 118-119
-
-
Sebastián, J.F.1
-
57
-
-
84871342191
-
Foucault on modern power: Empirical insights and normative confusions
-
Nancy Fraser, "Foucault on Modern Power: Empirical Insights and Normative Confusions," Praxis International 1 (1981): 272-87
-
(1981)
Praxis International
, vol.1
, pp. 272-287
-
-
Fraser, N.1
-
58
-
-
0001753541
-
Foucault on freedom and truth
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
Charles Taylor, "Foucault on Freedom and Truth," in Philosophy and the Human Sciences (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985), 182.
-
(1985)
Philosophy and the Human Sciences
, vol.182
-
-
Taylor, C.1
-
59
-
-
0004328310
-
-
trans. A. M. Sheridan Smith (New York: Vintage Books)
-
Michel Foucault, The Archaeology of Knowledge, trans. A. M. Sheridan Smith (New York: Vintage Books, 2010), 140
-
(2010)
The Archaeology of Knowledge
, pp. 140
-
-
Foucault, M.1
-
61
-
-
0004125178
-
-
trans. Alan Sheridan (New York: Pantheon)
-
Michel Foucault, Discipline and Punish, trans. Alan Sheridan (New York: Pantheon, 1977), 215.
-
(1977)
Discipline and Punish
, vol.215
-
-
Foucault, M.1
-
63
-
-
34248566116
-
Social science methodology as the ideology of bureaucratic authority
-
Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press
-
"Social Science Methodology as the Ideology of Bureaucratic Authority," in The MacIntyre Reader, ed. Kelvin Knight (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1998), 53-68.
-
(1998)
The MacIntyre Reader
, pp. 53-68
-
-
Knight, K.1
-
64
-
-
0004123406
-
-
This politics is precisely what MacIntyre has attempted to develop within his revival of the Aristotelian tradition. See: MacIntyre, After Virtue.
-
After Virtue
-
-
Macintyre1
|