-
1
-
-
84876869977
-
-
If application of a truth norm doesn't explain why belief is subject to a norm of truth, what does? I'd suggest that truth is the norm of belief not because of any mental state we have toward belief, but as a mind-independent normative fact
-
If application of a truth norm doesn't explain why belief is subject to a norm of truth, what does? I'd suggest that truth is the norm of belief not because of any mental state we have toward belief, but as a mind-independent normative fact.
-
-
-
-
2
-
-
84876867898
-
-
This is the standard way to understand moral norms. What it's right to do depends on objective moral facts, not on what we judge to be right
-
This is the standard way to understand moral norms. What it's right to do depends on objective moral facts, not on what we judge to be right.
-
-
-
-
3
-
-
77950274875
-
Memory and imagination
-
Urmson, J. (1967). 'Memory and Imagination,' Mind 76(301), pp. 83-91.
-
(1967)
Mind
, vol.76
, Issue.301
, pp. 83-91
-
-
Urmson, J.1
-
4
-
-
77956980226
-
Direction of fit
-
Humberstone, I. L. (1992). 'Direction of Fit,' Mind 101(401), pp. 59-83.
-
(1992)
Mind
, vol.101
, Issue.401
, pp. 59-83
-
-
Humberstone, I.L.1
-
5
-
-
46349092647
-
Doxastic deliberation
-
Shah, N. and Velleman, D. (2005). 'Doxastic Deliberation,' Philosophical Review 114(4), pp. 497-534.
-
(2005)
Philosophical Review
, vol.114
, Issue.4
, pp. 497-534
-
-
Shah, N.1
Velleman, D.2
-
6
-
-
33644775245
-
How truth governs belief
-
Shah, N. (2003). 'How Truth Governs Belief,' Philosophical Review 112(4), pp. 447-482.
-
(2003)
Philosophical Review
, vol.112
, Issue.4
, pp. 447-482
-
-
Shah, N.1
-
8
-
-
84876826295
-
-
Shah and Velleman suggest that pragmatic considerations are appropriate for determining whether to apply a norm of truth
-
Shah and Velleman suggest that pragmatic considerations are appropriate for determining whether to apply a norm of truth.
-
-
-
-
9
-
-
84876843370
-
-
They write: 'The question whether to apply the concept [of belief] appears to hang on pragmatic considerations of the sort that would determine whether to apply a noncognitive norm' (p. 514)
-
They write: 'The question whether to apply the concept [of belief] appears to hang on pragmatic considerations of the sort that would determine whether to apply a noncognitive norm' (p. 514).
-
-
-
-
10
-
-
84876817634
-
-
How, then, should we make sense of assuming a contradiction in order to see whether everything follows from it? Does one actually have to imagine the contradictory state of affairs that the contradiction describes?
-
How, then, should we make sense of assuming a contradiction in order to see whether everything follows from it? Does one actually have to imagine the contradictory state of affairs that the contradiction describes?
-
-
-
-
11
-
-
84876884624
-
-
I think one usually just imagines the contradictory sentence having the property of truth, without unpacking this to imagine the described state of affairs
-
I think one usually just imagines the contradictory sentence having the property of truth, without unpacking this to imagine the described state of affairs.
-
-
-
-
12
-
-
84876844845
-
-
This sort of imagining permits the syntactic operations involved in logical deduction
-
This sort of imagining permits the syntactic operations involved in logical deduction.
-
-
-
-
13
-
-
84876843673
-
-
For empirically informed work on this issue, see Nichols, S. (2006)
-
For empirically informed work on this issue, see Nichols, S. (2006).
-
-
-
-
14
-
-
33747735524
-
Just the imagination: Why imagining doesn't behave like believing
-
'Just the Imagination: Why Imagining Doesn't Behave Like Believing,' Mind & Language 21, pp. 459-474
-
Mind & Language
, vol.21
, pp. 459-474
-
-
-
15
-
-
84909318067
-
On the relation between pretense and belief
-
M. Kieran and D. M. Lopes (eds) New York: Routledge
-
Gendler, T. (2006). 'On the Relation Between Pretense and Belief,' in M. Kieran and D. M. Lopes (eds) Imagination, Philosophy, and the Arts. New York: Routledge, pp. 125-141.
-
(2006)
Imagination, Philosophy, and the Arts
, pp. 125-141
-
-
Gendler, T.1
-
16
-
-
84876836486
-
-
These authors don't address the norm-application theory, but the differences between believing and imagining which they describe suggest functional differences that would allow the distinction to be drawn without help from the norm-application theory
-
These authors don't address the norm-application theory, but the differences between believing and imagining which they describe suggest functional differences that would allow the distinction to be drawn without help from the norm-application theory.
-
-
-
-
17
-
-
84865394706
-
Belief
-
E. Zalta (ed.) available at
-
These are drawn from Schwitzgebel, E. (2006). 'Belief,' in E. Zalta (ed.) Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, available at http://plato.stanford.edu/ entries/belief.
-
(2006)
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
-
-
Schwitzgebel, E.1
-
18
-
-
84876848853
-
-
The fourth condition seems to be reducible to the third, since assertions are actions, but I won't address this here
-
The fourth condition seems to be reducible to the third, since assertions are actions, but I won't address this here.
-
-
-
-
20
-
-
61049393613
-
Imagination and the motivational view of belief
-
O'Brien, L. (2005). 'Imagination and the Motivational View of Belief,' Analysis 65(1), pp. 55-62
-
(2005)
Analysis
, vol.65
, Issue.1
, pp. 55-62
-
-
O'Brien, L.1
-
21
-
-
35948977589
-
Believe what you want
-
Similar comments along these lines appear in Noordhof, P. (2001). 'Believe What You Want,' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 101, pp. 247-265.
-
(2001)
Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society
, vol.101
, pp. 247-265
-
-
Noordhof, P.1
-
22
-
-
85009597137
-
The motivational role of belief
-
The view in Van Leeuwen, D. S. (2009). 'The Motivational Role of Belief,' Philosophical Papers 38(2), pp. 219-246
-
(2009)
Philosophical Papers
, vol.38
, Issue.2
, pp. 219-246
-
-
Van Leeuwen, D.S.1
-
23
-
-
84876824745
-
-
Early functionalists who analogized the mind to a Turing machine may have had a non-normative sense of 'function' in mind
-
Early functionalists who analogized the mind to a Turing machine may have had a non-normative sense of 'function' in mind.
-
-
-
-
24
-
-
84876832089
-
-
They understood mental states like mathematical functions, producing particular outputs in response to particular inputs
-
They understood mental states like mathematical functions, producing particular outputs in response to particular inputs.
-
-
-
-
25
-
-
84876830740
-
-
Unlike behaviorists, they allowed the outputs to be effects on other mental states rather than outward behavior
-
Unlike behaviorists, they allowed the outputs to be effects on other mental states rather than outward behavior.
-
-
-
-
26
-
-
0642332690
-
Putting the function back into functionalism
-
W. Lycan (ed.) Oxford: Blackwell
-
Sober, E. (1990). 'Putting the Function Back Into Functionalism,' in W. Lycan (ed.) Mind and Cognition. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 63-70.
-
(1990)
Mind and Cognition
, pp. 63-70
-
-
Sober, E.1
-
27
-
-
84876826651
-
-
While I (unlike Sober) am inclined towards a non-normative form of functionalism, I argue here that even those attracted to normative functionalism shouldn't require a further normative attitude to be applied to a representation for it to be a belief
-
While I (unlike Sober) am inclined towards a non-normative form of functionalism, I argue here that even those attracted to normative functionalism shouldn't require a further normative attitude to be applied to a representation for it to be a belief.
-
-
-
|