메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 27, Issue , 1997, Pages 211-249

Skepticism about meaning: Indeterminacy, normativity, and the rule-following paradox

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 84870707455     PISSN: 00455091     EISSN: 19110820     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1080/00455091.1997.10715967     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (37)

References (31)
  • 1
    • 0003665678 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Ma: Harvard University Press, discussing ‘Kripkes Wittgenstein’ I have mind the philosophical position presented by Saul Kripke chapters 2 and 3 of. Kripke presents this position both as an interpretation of the leading ideas of Wittgensteins Philosophical Investigations and as a philosophical point of view of independent interest. My discussion of the position will be concerned only with its content and merits, not its origin. The question of whether the position outlined by Kripke is an accurate interpretation of Wittgenstein is not directly relevant to my discussion
    • 1982. Wittgenstein On Rules and Private Language Cambridge, Ma: Harvard University Press. In discussing ‘Kripke's Wittgenstein’ I have in mind the philosophical position presented by Saul Kripke in chapters 2 and 3 of. Kripke presents this position both as an interpretation of the leading ideas of Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations and as a philosophical point of view of independent interest. My discussion of the position will be concerned only with its content and merits, not its origin. The question of whether the position outlined by Kripke is an accurate interpretation of Wittgenstein is not directly relevant to my discussion.
    • (1982) Wittgenstein On Rules and Private Language
  • 6
    • 85063699551 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The challenge is to locate non-content-bearing (i.e. nonintentional) facts that determine the content-bearing ones. In attempting to meet this challenge, the nonintentional facts that one is allowed to appeal to are not restricted to behavioural facts, publicly observable facts, or even physical facts. Mental images, representations, feelings, and sensations can all be appealed to, provided that their ‘interpretations,’ or contents, (if any) are not taken for granted, but are themselves given a thoroughly non-intentional explanation. In certain cases, it is quite plausible to suppose that factors such as linguistic rules or representations really do play a role in determining the meanings of some expressions. A case in point is ‘+’ itself
    • However this, as other cases, the role is dependent upon a prior explanation of the contents of the relevant rules, algorithms, images, or representations
    • Kripke's skeptic raises a challenge about content-bearing (i.e. intentional) facts. The challenge is to locate non-content-bearing (i.e. nonintentional) facts that determine the content-bearing ones. In attempting to meet this challenge, the nonintentional facts that one is allowed to appeal to are not restricted to behavioural facts, publicly observable facts, or even physical facts. Mental images, representations, feelings, and sensations can all be appealed to, provided that their ‘interpretations,’ or contents, (if any) are not taken for granted, but are themselves given a thoroughly non-intentional explanation. In certain cases, it is quite plausible to suppose that factors such as linguistic rules or representations really do play a role in determining the meanings of some expressions. A case in point is ‘+’ itself. However in this, as in other cases, the role is dependent upon a prior explanation of the contents of the relevant rules, algorithms, images, or representations.
    • Kripke's skeptic raises a challenge about content-bearing (i.e. intentional) facts
  • 7
    • 85063697828 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kripke, 26
    • Kripke, 26
  • 8
    • 85063700137 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In this connection, it is important to note that the finitude objection to the dispositional analysis of ‘+’ is just one instance of a more general objection. The objection is that a term may apply to certain objects even in cases in which those objects are, for one reason or another, epistemically inaccessible to us, and hence are not objects about which we have any normal dispositions. In the case of ‘+’ the infinity of natural numbers ensures that at some point they will get too big for us to consider
    • In, the case of other words the reasons for epistemic inaccessibility may be quite different
    • Both the error and the finitude objections can be generalized to cover dispositional analyses of other terms. In this connection, it is important to note that the finitude objection to the dispositional analysis of ‘+’ is just one instance of a more general objection. The objection is that a term may apply to certain objects even in cases in which those objects are, for one reason or another, epistemically inaccessible to us, and hence are not objects about which we have any normal dispositions. In the case of ‘+’ the infinity of natural numbers ensures that at some point they will get too big for us to consider. In the case of other words the reasons for epistemic inaccessibility may be quite different.
    • Both the error and the finitude objections can be generalized to cover dispositional analyses of other terms
  • 9
    • 85063703888 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One possible response to these objections would be to give up the dispositional analysis for ‘+’ while retaining it for simpler notions like ‘successor,’ terms of which ‘+’ could then be defined. Certainly, there is less room for error applying the successor function than applying the addition function. However, some room for error may remain, and, any case, the finitude objection still seems to apply. Another possibility, considered by Kripke, is to reformulate the analysis so as to appeal to idealized dispositions—dispositions to answer questions ‘What is n + m?’, not just any circumstances, but certain idealized circumstances, which one scrupulously ‘checks’ ones work, and which ones mental capacities have somehow been enhanced to allow one to consider arbitrarily large numbers. Kripkes criticism of this response is telling. order for the analysis to be non-circular, one must not characterize the idealized dispositions a way that presupposes advance what we mean by ‘+.’ For example, they cannot be characterized as dispositions to answer the relevant questions when we have been provided with sufficient mental capacities to allow us to correctly, add, any two numbers. However, if our characterization of the ideal dispositions is non-circular, then we will have little reason to be confident that they will fact determine the desired function. It is also worth noting that the finitude and error objections cannot be overcome by appealing to the dispositions of the entire linguistic community of which the speaker is a part. These dispositions are just as subject to the objections as are the dispositions of an individual. These considerations constitute serious obstacles to the dispositional analysis. I do not maintain that they rule out all possible reformulations. Perhaps there are reformulations of the analysis that are capable of avoiding the error and finitude objections. Even if this is so, the normativity arguments will remain, and will, I suspect, require appeal to some factors over and above dispositions. See below
    • One possible response to these objections would be to give up the dispositional analysis for ‘+’ while retaining it for simpler notions like ‘successor,’ in terms of which ‘+’ could then be defined. Certainly, there is less room for error in applying the successor function than in applying the addition function. However, some room for error may remain, and, in any case, the finitude objection still seems to apply. Another possibility, considered by Kripke, is to reformulate the analysis so as to appeal to idealized dispositions—dispositions to answer questions ‘What is n + m?’, not in just any circumstances, but in certain idealized circumstances, in which one scrupulously ‘checks’ one's work, and in which one's mental capacities have somehow been enhanced to allow one to consider arbitrarily large numbers. Kripke's criticism of this response is telling. In order for the analysis to be non-circular, one must not characterize the idealized dispositions in a way that presupposes in advance what we mean by ‘+.’ For example, they cannot be characterized as dispositions to answer the relevant questions when we have been provided with sufficient mental capacities to allow us to correctly add any two numbers. However, if our characterization of the ideal dispositions is non-circular, then we will have little reason to be confident that they will in fact determine the desired function. It is also worth noting that the finitude and error objections cannot be overcome by appealing to the dispositions of the entire linguistic community of which the speaker is a part. These dispositions are just as subject to the objections as are the dispositions of an individual. These considerations constitute serious obstacles to the dispositional analysis. I do not maintain that they rule out all possible reformulations. Perhaps there are reformulations of the analysis that are capable of avoiding the error and finitude objections. Even if this is so, the normativity arguments will remain, and will, I suspect, require appeal to some factors over and above dispositions. See below.
  • 10
    • 85063698377 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A relevant passage is the following: To a good extent this reply [the dispositional analysis] immediately ought to appear to be misdirected, off target. For the skeptic created an air of puzzlement as to my, justification, for responding ‘125’ rather than ‘5’ to the addition problem as queried. He thinks my response is no better than a stab the dark. Does the suggested reply advance matters? How does it, justify, my choice of ‘125’? What it says is: ‘125’ is the response you are disposed to give, and (perhaps the reply adds) it would also have been your response the past. Well and good, I know that ‘125’ is the response I am disposed to give (I am actually giving it!), and maybe it is helpful to be told—as a matter of brute fact—that I would have given the same response the past. How does any of this indicate that—now, or, the past—‘125’ was an answer, justified, terms of instructions I gave myself, rather than a mere jack-in-the-box unjustified and arbitrary response? (23) The emphasis here on justification echoes the way which Kripke initially sets up the skeptical problem. the discussion below, the challenge posed by the skeptic takes two forms. First, he questions whether there is a, fact, that I meant plus, not quus, that will answer his skeptical challenge. Second, he questions whether I have any reason to be so confident that now I should answer ‘125’ rather than ‘5.’ The two forms of the challenge are related. I am confident that I should answer ‘125’ because I am confident that this answer also accords with what I, meant., Neither the accuracy of my computation nor of my memory is under dispute. So it ought to be agreed that, if I, meant plus, then unless I wish to change my usage, I am justified answering (indeed compelled to answer) ‘125’ not ‘5.’ An answer to the skeptic must satisfy two conditions. First, it must give an account of what fact it is (about my mental state) that constitutes my meaning plus, not quus. But further, there is a condition that any putative candidate for such a fact must satisfy. It must, some sense, show how I am justified giving the answer ‘125’ to ‘68 + 57.’ (11
    • A relevant passage is the following: To a good extent this reply [the dispositional analysis] immediately ought to appear to be misdirected, off target. For the skeptic created an air of puzzlement as to my justification for responding ‘125’ rather than ‘5’ to the addition problem as queried. He thinks my response is no better than a stab in the dark. Does the suggested reply advance matters? How does it justify my choice of ‘125’? What it says is: “‘125’ is the response you are disposed to give, and (perhaps the reply adds) it would also have been your response in the past.” Well and good, I know that ‘125’ is the response I am disposed to give (I am actually giving it!), and maybe it is helpful to be told—as a matter of brute fact—that I would have given the same response in the past. How does any of this indicate that—now or in the past—‘125’ was an answer justified in terms of instructions I gave myself, rather than a mere jack-in-the-box unjustified and arbitrary response? (23) The emphasis here on justification echoes the way in which Kripke initially sets up the skeptical problem. In the discussion below, the challenge posed by the skeptic takes two forms. First, he questions whether there is a fact that I meant plus, not quus, that will answer his skeptical challenge. Second, he questions whether I have any reason to be so confident that now I should answer ‘125’ rather than ‘5.’ The two forms of the challenge are related. I am confident that I should answer ‘125’ because I am confident that this answer also accords with what I meant. Neither the accuracy of my computation nor of my memory is under dispute. So it ought to be agreed that if I meant plus, then unless I wish to change my usage, I am justified in answering (indeed compelled to answer) ‘125’ not ‘5.’ An answer to the skeptic must satisfy two conditions. First, it must give an account of what fact it is (about my mental state) that constitutes my meaning plus, not quus. But further, there is a condition that any putative candidate for such a fact must satisfy. It must, in some sense, show how I am justified in giving the answer ‘125’ to ‘68 + 57.’ (11)
  • 11
    • 85063701099 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am here taking the meanings of the other symbols—the numerals and identity sign as given. This simplification does not affect the point at hand
    • I am here taking the meanings of the other symbols—the numerals and identity sign as given. This simplification does not affect the point at hand.
  • 12
    • 85063698566 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On page 11 Kripke insists ‘5. Similarly, on page 13, explaining why he sets up the paradox as a metalinguistic problem about the past use of an expression, Kripke says that when this is not done, some listeners hear it as a skeptical problem about arithmetic: How do I know that 68 + 57 is 125? (Why not answer this question with a mathematical proof?) At least at this stage, skepticism about arithmetic should not be taken to be question: we may assume, if we wish, that 68 + 57 is 125. I take these passages to indicate that Kripkes formulation of the paradox, my present (true) belief that 68 + 57 = 125 can be appealed to (without further justification) attempting to meet the skeptics demand that I show how I am justified thinking that ‘125’ is the answer required by my past understanding of the term
    • Neither the accuracy of my computation nor of my memory is under dispute. So it ought to be agreed that if I meant plus, then unless I wish to change my usage, I am justified in answering. ‘125,’ and not On page 11 Kripke insists ‘5.'” Similarly, on page 13, in explaining why he sets up the paradox as a metalinguistic problem about the past use of an expression, Kripke says that when this is not done, “some listeners hear it as a skeptical problem about arithmetic: “How do I know that 68 + 57 is 125?” (Why not answer this question with a mathematical proof?) At least at this stage, skepticism about arithmetic should not be taken to be in question: we may assume, if we wish, that 68 + 57 is 125.” I take these passages to indicate that in Kripke's formulation of the paradox, my present (true) belief that 68 + 57 = 125 can be appealed to (without further justification) in attempting to meet the skeptic's demand that I show how I am justified in thinking that ‘125’ is the answer required by my past understanding of the term.
    • “Neither the accuracy of my computation nor of my memory is under dispute. So it ought to be agreed that if I meant plus, then unless I wish to change my usage, I am justified in answering. ‘125,’ and not
  • 13
    • 85063706223 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • E ). My reason for preferring the weaker version the text is that it leads to a conclusion of greater generality. I am indebted to George Wilson for a discussion of this point
    • E ). My reason for preferring the weaker version in the text is that it leads to a conclusion of greater generality. I am indebted to George Wilson for a discussion of this point.
  • 14
    • 85063706256 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The point here is a general one, and applies to versions of the rule-following paradox involving all sorts of different words. For example, consider a word like ‘fossil,’ which applies to concrete physical objects. Given some object o, the normative prescription regarding whether one should apply ‘fossil’ to o depends on (i) the meaning of the word ‘fossil,’ (ii) the nonlinguistic facts about the nature of o—i.e. whether or not it is a fossil and (iii) the general presumption that one should apply a term to an object only if doing so would involve speaking the truth. As Michael Thau has emphasized to me, examples like this highlight the need for (ii) over and above (i) particularly clearly. There is, however, another issue involving facts like (ii) that is worth mentioning, even though I dont have sufficient space here to go into detail. Suppose I apply the word ‘fossil’ to a certain object o, and then I am challenged by a skeptic to justify this new application of the word. Suppose further that part of my response involves citing some fact F about my past use of the word. Imagine for the sake of argument that knowledge of F does allow me to demonstrate that the past I used the word to mean fossil. Still, this by itself doesnt justify my application of the word to o, even if I am now using the word with the same meaning as before, and it is granted that I ought this case to speak the truth. To complete my justification I have to show that I am justified thinking that o is a fossil. And how am I to do that? Perhaps the explanation of what it is for me to think that o is a fossil is simply for me to understand the word ‘fossil’ and be disposed lo apply it to o on the basis of some reasonable, empirical examination of, or inquiry about, o. If so, then the justification for my thinking that o is a fossil may amount to little more than my now understanding the word ‘fossil’ and being disposed, after appropriate investigation and reflection, to apply it to o. If this is the situation, then some ultimate sense I may have no justification for applying the term to a new item o, other than my own confident, informed, and reflective inclination to do so, plus my status as a competent user of the term. This does seem to be an important part of what Wittgenstein was trying to show his deployment of the rule-following paradox, and it is also present Kripkes discussion. Moreover, there are, I think, cases which something like this point is correct. However, this observation about justification does not undermine the response given the text to Kripkes version of the skeptical paradox; nor does it lead to any defensible skepticism about meaning. What it may do is point to an alternative route to one of Wittgensteins conclusions about language—a route that does not require any fundamental, skeptical recasting of our ordinary conception of meaning. The conclusion is that, at least some cases, the explanation of a speakers understanding of a term (including his ability to apply it to newly considered objects) does not involve associating T with an independently apprehended property P (and judging those objects to have P). Understanding a term, or using it to mean a certain thing, is not always like deciding to attach a new proper name to an object with which one is already familiar. See my ‘Semantic Competence,’ Philosophical Perspectives3 (1989) 575–96, at 587–91 for a brief discussion of this idea. This idea is discussed more detail my, ‘Facts, Truth Conditions, and the Skeptical Solution to the Rule-Following Paradox,’ Philosophical Perspectives12 (1998), forthcoming. I am indebted to James Pryor and Michael Thau for helpful discussions of the material the footnote
    • T, The point here is a general one, and applies to versions of the rule-following paradox involving all sorts of different words. For example, consider a word like ‘fossil,’ which applies to concrete physical objects. Given some object o, the normative prescription regarding whether one should apply ‘fossil’ to o depends on (i) the meaning of the word ‘fossil,’ (ii) the nonlinguistic facts about the nature of o—i.e. whether or not it is a fossil and (iii) the general presumption that one should apply a term to an object only if doing so would involve speaking the truth. As Michael Thau has emphasized to me, examples like this highlight the need for (ii) over and above (i) particularly clearly. There is, however, another issue involving facts like (ii) that is worth mentioning, even though I don't have sufficient space here to go into detail. Suppose I apply the word ‘fossil’ to a certain object o, and then I am challenged by a skeptic to justify this new application of the word. Suppose further that part of my response involves citing some fact F about my past use of the word. Imagine for the sake of argument that knowledge of F does allow me to demonstrate that in the past I used the word to mean fossil. Still, this by itself doesn't justify my application of the word to o, even if I am now using the word with the same meaning as before, and it is granted that I ought in this case to speak the truth. To complete my justification I have to show that I am justified in thinking that o is a fossil. And how am I to do that? Perhaps the explanation of what it is for me to think that o is a fossil is simply for me to understand the word ‘fossil’ and be disposed lo apply it to o on the basis of some reasonable, empirical examination of, or inquiry about, o. If so, then the justification for my thinking that o is a fossil may amount to little more than my now understanding the word ‘fossil’ and being disposed, after appropriate investigation and reflection, to apply it to o. If this is the situation, then in some ultimate sense I may have no justification for applying the term to a new item o, other than my own confident, informed, and reflective inclination to do so, plus my status as a competent user of the term. This does seem to be an important part of what Wittgenstein was trying to show in his deployment of the rule-following paradox, and it is also present in Kripke's discussion. Moreover, there are, I think, cases in which something like this point is correct. However, this observation about justification does not undermine the response given in the text to Kripke's version of the skeptical paradox; nor does it lead to any defensible skepticism about meaning. What it may do is point to an alternative route to one of Wittgenstein's conclusions about language—a route that does not require any fundamental, skeptical recasting of our ordinary conception of meaning. The conclusion is that, at least in some cases, the explanation of a speaker's understanding of a term (including his ability to apply it to newly considered objects) does not involve associating T with an independently apprehended property P (and judging those objects to have P). Understanding a term, or using it to mean a certain thing, is not always like deciding to attach a new proper name to an object with which one is already familiar. See my ‘Semantic Competence,’ Philosophical Perspectives3 (1989) 575–96, at 587–91 for a brief discussion of this idea. This idea is discussed in more detail in my, ‘Facts, Truth Conditions, and the Skeptical Solution to the Rule-Following Paradox,’ Philosophical Perspectives12 (1998), forthcoming. I am indebted to James Pryor and Michael Thau for helpful discussions of the material in the footnote.
  • 16
    • 52549104926 scopus 로고
    • One important reason why it is difficult to be certain on this point is that it is not completely clear what apriori definitions of intentional notions are possible. For a good discussion of this issue, and an argument for the conclusion that facts about meaning (and belief) are not apriori consequences of nonintentional facts, see Alex Byrne, unpublished dissertation, Princeton University
    • 1993. The Emergent Mind One important reason why it is difficult to be certain on this point is that it is not completely clear what apriori definitions of intentional notions are possible. For a good discussion of this issue, and an argument for the conclusion that facts about meaning (and belief) are not apriori consequences of nonintentional facts, see Alex Byrne, unpublished dissertation, Princeton University
    • (1993) The Emergent Mind
  • 18
    • 85063699317 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1
    • 1
  • 19
    • 85063697716 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The strength of this thesis, as well as the more general thesis of the underdetermination of empirical theories by observational data, depends on ones conception of what it is for a class of data statements to support a theory. For present purposes I will follow what appears to be Quines latitudinarianism on this subject. Theories, together with auxiliary observational statements, make (entail) observational predictions. (Which statements count as observational for this purpose will not be an issue here.) A set of such observational predictions supports a theory to the extent that the theory, supplemented by true auxiliary observation statements, entails the members of the set. Two theories (appropriately supplemented with auxiliary observational statements) that entail the same members of the set, are equally well supported by the set
    • The strength of this thesis, as well as the more general thesis of the underdetermination of empirical theories by observational data, depends on one's conception of what it is for a class of data statements to support a theory. For present purposes I will follow what appears to be Quine's latitudinarianism on this subject. Theories, together with auxiliary observational statements, make (entail) observational predictions. (Which statements count as observational for this purpose will not be an issue here.) A set of such observational predictions supports a theory to the extent that the theory, supplemented by true auxiliary observation statements, entails the members of the set. Two theories (appropriately supplemented with auxiliary observational statements) that entail the same members of the set, are equally well supported by the set.
  • 20
    • 85063701066 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am assuming, in order to simplify the argument, that words are the minimal meaning bearing units, that languages contain finitely many such words, and that the translation of the infinitely many phrases and sentences of the two languages is the result of (i) the translation of the words that make them up plus (ii) combinatorial principles specifying the translations of syntactically complex expressions in terms of the translations of their parts.
    • I am assuming, in order to simplify the argument, that words are the minimal meaning bearing units, that languages contain finitely many such words, and that the translation of the infinitely many phrases and sentences of the two languages is the result of (i) the translation of the words that make them up plus (ii) combinatorial principles specifying the translations of syntactically complex expressions in terms of the translations of their parts.
  • 21
    • 0003799915 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Ma: MIT Press, See chapter 2 of
    • 1960. Word and Object Cambridge, Ma: MIT Press. See chapter 2 of.
    • (1960) Word and Object
  • 22
    • 85063706263 scopus 로고
    • 2 , and a set containing (a)-(d) is logically inconsistent; as are corresponding unions involving the other relevant combinations. The justification for appealing to these auxiliary claims is that (a) states an obvious fact and (b)-(d) are axiomatic to any overall theory that makes significant use of the concepts of meaning and reference
    • 2 , and a set containing (a)-(d) is logically inconsistent; as are corresponding unions involving the other relevant combinations. The justification for appealing to these auxiliary claims is that (a) states an obvious fact and (b)-(d) are axiomatic to any overall theory that makes significant use of the concepts of meaning and reference.
    • (1970) Journal of Philosophy , vol.67
  • 23
    • 0040575924 scopus 로고
    • Reidel: Dordrecht, See Quine, ‘Reply to Chomsky,’ 303., and, eds
    • Davidson, D., and Hintikka, J., eds. 1969. Words and Objections Reidel: Dordrecht. See Quine, ‘Reply to Chomsky,’ 303.
    • (1969) Words and Objections
    • Davidson, D.1    Hintikka, J.2
  • 24
    • 85063701126 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • this paper I will assume, without argument, that Quines behaviourism about language is false. It is noteworthy, however, that the appeal of the indeterminacy thesis, and the challenge posed by it, have been strongly felt by many philosophers who have not been prepared to accept behaviourism independently. My task here is to diage the source of that appeal, and defuse the challenge felt by those philosophers
    • In this paper I will assume, without argument, that Quine's behaviourism about language is false. It is noteworthy, however, that the appeal of the indeterminacy thesis, and the challenge posed by it, have been strongly felt by many philosophers who have not been prepared to accept behaviourism independently. My task here is to diagnose the source of that appeal, and defuse the challenge felt by those philosophers.
  • 26
    • 85063705737 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Quines doctrines of Physicalism, the Indeterminacy of Translation and the Inscrutability of Reference entail that claims of the sort, are not determined by the totality of physical facts and so do not express genuine truths; ditto for any open formula Ps word w refers to x relative to an assignment of an object as value of the variable ‘x.’ Given Quines usual understanding of the existential quantifier, one can conclude from this that Ex Ps word w refers to x never expresses a genuine truth. Supposing that it is nevertheless meaningful, we may conclude that ∼Ex Ps word w refers to x will always be true; effect, no ones words ever refer to anything. This is eliminativism about reference (as ordinarily understood). Pretty paradoxical, especially for someone who clearly is attempting to use words to refer to, and make claims about, things. Quine nowhere explicitly acknowledges such starkly paradoxical consequences of his views. The closest he comes is the essay Ontological Relativity,’ Quine, Ontological Relativity (New York and London: Columbia University Press 1969), 26–68, at 47–51. There he notes the paradoxical consequences of applying the Indeterminacy and Inscrutability doctrines to our (present) selves, and attempts (unsuccessfully) to avoid these consequences by invoking his mysterious doctrine of reference relative to a coordinate system (48) and acquiescing our mother tongue (49). Unfortunately, space limitations prevent me from providing a thorough discussion of these passages here
    • Person P's word w refers to rabbits (as opposed to sets of undetached rabbit parts, etc.) Quine's doctrines of Physicalism, the Indeterminacy of Translation and the Inscrutability of Reference entail that claims of the sort, are not determined by the totality of physical facts and so do not express genuine truths; ditto for any open formula P's word w refers to x relative to an assignment of an object as value of the variable ‘x.’ Given Quine's usual understanding of the existential quantifier, one can conclude from this that Ex P's word w refers to x never expresses a genuine truth. Supposing that it is nevertheless meaningful, we may conclude that ∼Ex P's word w refers to x will always be true; in effect, no one's words ever refer to anything. This is eliminativism about reference (as ordinarily understood). Pretty paradoxical, especially for someone who clearly is attempting to use words to refer to, and make claims about, things. Quine nowhere explicitly acknowledges such starkly paradoxical consequences of his views. The closest he comes is in the essay Ontological Relativity,’ in Quine, Ontological Relativity (New York and London: Columbia University Press 1969), 26–68, at 47–51. There he notes the paradoxical consequences of applying the Indeterminacy and Inscrutability doctrines to our (present) selves, and attempts (unsuccessfully) to avoid these consequences by invoking his mysterious doctrine of reference relative to a coordinate system (48) and “acquiescing in our mother tongue” (49). Unfortunately, space limitations prevent me from providing a thorough discussion of these passages here.
    • Person P's word w refers to rabbits (as opposed to sets of undetached rabbit parts, etc.)
  • 27
    • 85063705868 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This result could be avoided if it could be shown that there are genuinely apriori semantic definitions of ‘gene’ and ‘DNA’ from which, together with the set of purely physical truths, the theoretical identification of genes with DNA can be derived. Since I am not certain whether this is possible principle, I am not certain that the case of genetics provides a genuine counterexample to the strong epistemological version of physicalism. By the same token, I am not certain that no genuinely apriori semantic definitions of notions like meaning and reference exist from which, together with all physical truths, claims about meaning and reference can be derived
    • This result could be avoided if it could be shown that there are genuinely apriori semantic definitions of ‘gene’ and ‘DNA’ from which, together with the set of purely physical truths, the theoretical identification of genes with DNA can be derived. Since I am not certain whether this is possible in principle, I am not certain that the case of genetics provides a genuine counterexample to the strong epistemological version of physicalism. By the same token, I am not certain that no genuinely apriori semantic definitions of notions like meaning and reference exist from which, together with all physical truths, claims about meaning and reference can be derived.
  • 28
    • 85063702912 scopus 로고
    • 2 with formulas, or sets of formulas, that are intensionally equivalent to them any sense. particular D is not required to produce pairs that are extensionally equivalent arbitrary counterfactual, or apriori imaginable, circumstances. Because of this the different merely possible, or merely imaginable, ways which a mental type might be physically realized are, strictly speaking, irrelevant to the existence of ‘definitional’ mappings D satisfying Friedmans stated conditions for reduction. Since, as far as I know, physicalist functionalists never maintain that there actually exist infinitely many physically different kinds of realizations of a given mental type, they presumably ought to be reasonably confident asserting the strong reducibility (in Friedmans official sense) of their theories to physics. Why then is there a need for the notion of weak reducibility? Does Friedmans use of the notion reflect an implicit desire to require the ‘definitional’ mappings genuine reductions to provide more than actual coextensiveness? Do they also have to provide coextensiveness all counterfactual (or all apriori imaginable) situations as well? If so, then couldnt we define the determination relations needed to evaluate Quines theses directly terms of necessary, or a priori, consequence, as above? Putting these and other subsidiary issues aside, I would like to acknowledge the essential correctness of some of Friedmans central points. particular, he makes a plausible case for interpreting Quines thesis of the Indeterminacy of Translation as the doctrine that theories of translation are not reducible (in either his strong or his weak sense) to the set of physical truths. He then argues for the correct (but understated) conclusion that Quine has given no compelling argument for the Indeterminacy Thesis, understood this way
    • 2 with formulas, or sets of formulas, that are intensionally equivalent to them in any sense. In particular D is not required to produce pairs that are extensionally equivalent in arbitrary counterfactual, or apriori imaginable, circumstances. Because of this the different merely possible, or merely imaginable, ways in which a mental type might be physically realized are, strictly speaking, irrelevant to the existence of ‘definitional’ mappings D satisfying Friedman's stated conditions for reduction. Since, as far as I know, physicalist functionalists never maintain that there actually exist infinitely many physically different kinds of realizations of a given mental type, they presumably ought to be reasonably confident in asserting the strong reducibility (in Friedman's official sense) of their theories to physics. Why then is there a need for the notion of weak reducibility? Does Friedman's use of the notion reflect an implicit desire to require the ‘definitional’ mappings in genuine reductions to provide more than actual coextensiveness? Do they also have to provide coextensiveness in all counterfactual (or in all apriori imaginable) situations as well? If so, then couldn't we define the determination relations needed to evaluate Quine's theses directly in terms of necessary, or a priori, consequence, as above? Putting these and other subsidiary issues aside, I would like to acknowledge the essential correctness of some of Friedman's central points. In particular, he makes a plausible case for interpreting Quine's thesis of the Indeterminacy of Translation as the doctrine that theories of translation are not reducible (in either his strong or his weak sense) to the set of physical truths. He then argues for the correct (but understated) conclusion that Quine has given no compelling argument for the Indeterminacy Thesis, understood in this way.
    • (1975) Noûs , vol.9
  • 29
    • 85063698380 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • this discussion I ignore certain practical complications such as the fact that some speakers speak more than one language, the fact that words of the language may be ambiguous, and the possibility that sometimes there may be no translation of a word one language onto a word or phrase of the other language. Although these are real factors translation, they are peripheral to Quines philosophical claims about translation
    • In this discussion I ignore certain practical complications such as the fact that some speakers speak more than one language, the fact that words of the language may be ambiguous, and the possibility that sometimes there may be no translation of a word in one language onto a word or phrase of the other language. Although these are real factors in translation, they are peripheral to Quine's philosophical claims about translation.
  • 31
    • 85063700145 scopus 로고
    • The ideas this paper date back to seminars I gave the summer of 1988 at the University of Washington, and the fall of at Princeton University. These ideas were refined and elaborated my fall semester seminar of 1993 at Princeton. An early version of the first section of this paper, on Kripkes account of the rule-following paradox, was presented June of 1995 at the Later versions of the paper were presented at the Department of Philosophy, Wayne State University on October 13, 1995, the Chapel Hill Philosophy Colloquium on October 29, 1995, the Division of Humanities at the California Institute of Technology on November 3,1995, the Instituto de Investigaciones Filosoficas de la Universidad Nacional Autonoma de Mexico on January 26 and 29, 1996, the Department of Philosophy at Rutgers University on March 7, 1996, the Department of Philosophy at Reed College on March 20, 1996, and the Department of Philosophy at the University of California at Berkeley on April 25, 1996. It was also presented at my fall semester seminar 1996 at Princeton. I would like to thank the participants at all those presentations, and seminars, for their comments. addition, I would like to thank James Pryor, Michael Thau and George Wilson for reading and commenting on earlier drafts of the paper
    • 1988. Instituto de Investigaciones Filosóficas de la Universidad Nacional Autonoma de Mexico. The ideas in this paper date back to seminars I gave in the summer of 1988 at the University of Washington, and in the fall of at Princeton University. These ideas were refined and elaborated in my fall semester seminar of 1993 at Princeton. An early version of the first section of this paper, on Kripke's account of the rule-following paradox, was presented in June of 1995 at the Later versions of the paper were presented at the Department of Philosophy, Wayne State University on October 13, 1995, the Chapel Hill Philosophy Colloquium on October 29, 1995, the Division of Humanities at the California Institute of Technology on November 3,1995, the Instituto de Investigaciones Filosoficas de la Universidad Nacional Autonoma de Mexico on January 26 and 29, 1996, the Department of Philosophy at Rutgers University on March 7, 1996, the Department of Philosophy at Reed College on March 20, 1996, and the Department of Philosophy at the University of California at Berkeley on April 25, 1996. It was also presented at my fall semester seminar in 1996 at Princeton. I would like to thank the participants at all those presentations, and seminars, for their comments. In addition, I would like to thank James Pryor, Michael Thau and George Wilson for reading and commenting on earlier drafts of the paper.
    • (1988) Instituto de Investigaciones Filosóficas de la Universidad Nacional Autonoma de Mexico.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.