메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn , Issue 9, 2000, Pages 10-18

Narrative as a form of explanation

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 84861865367     PISSN: 0873626X     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.2478/disp-2000-0009     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (13)

References (20)
  • 3
    • 0003053720 scopus 로고
    • Interpretation and the sciences of man
    • Many of the words we would naturally use to describe certain actions, however, presuppose that the actor possesses certain inter-subjective meanings or beliefs. See C. Taylor, "Interpretation and the Sciences of Man,", Review of Metaphysics 25 (1971-72), 3-51.
    • (1971) Review of Metaphysics , vol.25 , pp. 3-51
    • Taylor, C.1
  • 4
    • 0002658699 scopus 로고
    • Mental events
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • Compare D. Davidson, "Mental Events,", in Essays on Actions and Events (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980), pp. 207-27.
    • (1980) Essays on Actions and Events , pp. 207-227
    • Davidson, C.D.1
  • 5
    • 0011639366 scopus 로고
    • The function of general laws in history
    • Thus the well known debate over whether or not narrative explained revolved around the issue of whether or not narrative could be assimilated to a strictly causal or a covering-law form of explanation associated with the natural sciences. See, in particular, the classic argument that narrative is a sketchy or partial version of the nomological-deductive form of explanation, as found in C. Hempel, "The Function of General Laws in History,", Journal of Philosophy 39 (1942), 35-48.
    • (1942) Journal of Philosophy , vol.39 , pp. 35-48
    • Hempel, C.1
  • 6
    • 60950073247 scopus 로고
    • Explanation, causes, and covering laws
    • Beiheft 25: Knowing and Telling History: The Anglo-Saxon Debate
    • For a general account of the debate, see M. Murphy, "Explanation, Causes, and Covering Laws,", History and Theory 25 (1986), Beiheft 25: Knowing and Telling History: The Anglo-Saxon Debate, 43-57.
    • (1986) History and Theory , vol.25 , pp. 43-57
    • Murphy, M.1
  • 7
    • 84863515817 scopus 로고
    • From narrative history to problem-oriented history
    • trans. J. Mandelbaum Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • The annales school are associated with this position. See, in particular, F. Furet, "From Narrative History to Problem-oriented History,", in In the Workshop of History, trans. J. Mandelbaum (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), pp. 54-67.
    • (1984) The Workshop of History , pp. 54-67
    • Furet, F.1
  • 8
    • 84889586832 scopus 로고
    • Colligation and the writing of history
    • On colligation, see L. Cebik, "Colligation and the Writing of History,", Monist 53 (1969), 40-57;
    • (1969) Monist , vol.53 , pp. 40-57
    • Cebik, L.1
  • 10
    • 84925912066 scopus 로고
    • Colligation and classification in history
    • C. McCullagh, "Colligation and Classification in History,", History and Theory 27 (1978), 267-84;
    • (1978) History and Theory , vol.27 , pp. 267-284
    • McCullagh, C.1
  • 11
    • 0009979757 scopus 로고
    • Colligatory concepts in history
    • P. Gardiner, ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • W. Walsh, "Colligatory Concepts in History,", in P. Gardiner, ed., The Philosophy of History (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1974), pp. 127-44.
    • (1974) The Philosophy of History , pp. 127-144
    • Walsh, W.1
  • 12
    • 0007257098 scopus 로고
    • History and fiction as modes of comprehension
    • On configuration, see L. Mink, "History and Fiction as Modes of Comprehension,", New Literary History 1 (1970), 541-58;
    • (1970) New Literary History , vol.1 , pp. 541-558
    • Mink, L.1
  • 13
    • 0004025844 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 3 vols., trans. K. McLaughlin & D. Pellauer Chicago: University of Chicago Press chap. 2
    • P. Ricoeur, Time and Narrative, 3 vols., trans. K. McLaughlin & D. Pellauer (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984-88), Vol. 1, chap. 2.
    • (1984) Time and Narrative , vol.1
    • Ricoeur, P.1
  • 14
    • 0003136586 scopus 로고
    • Narrative form as a cognitive instrument
    • ed. R. Canary & H. Kozicki Madison: University of Wisconsin Press
    • L. Mink, "Narrative Form as a Cognitive Instrument,", in The Writing of History, ed. R. Canary & H. Kozicki (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1978), p. 145.
    • (1978) The Writing of History , pp. 145
    • Mink, L.1
  • 15
    • 2942613955 scopus 로고
    • The question of narrative in contemporary historical theory
    • Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press
    • H. White, "The Question of Narrative in Contemporary Historical Theory,", in The Content of the Form (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1987), p. 47.
    • (1987) The Content of the Form , pp. 47
    • White, H.1
  • 17
    • 0000165269 scopus 로고
    • Objectivity in history
    • For my preferred post-positivist epistemology, see M. Bevir, "Objectivity in History,", History and Theory 33 (1994), 328-44.
    • (1994) History and Theory , vol.33 , pp. 328-344
    • Bevir, M.1
  • 18
    • 84889574660 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Value of narrativity
    • Contrast White's, again implicitly positivist, argument that "it is because real events do not offer themselves as stories that their narrativization is so difficult." H. White, "Value of Narrativity,", in Content of the Form, p. 4.
    • Content of the Form , pp. 4
    • White, H.1
  • 19
    • 0004073483 scopus 로고
    • Bloomington: Indiana University Press
    • Several phenomenologists emphasise we experience history as narrative. See D. Carr, Time, Narrative, and History (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1986);
    • (1986) Time, Narrative, and History
    • Carr, D.1
  • 20
    • 0004025844 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ricoeur, Time and Narrative. Typically, however, their analyses of narrative as part of our experience of the world rely primarily on an analysis of temporality not folk psychology.
    • Time and Narrative
    • Ricoeur1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.