메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 17, Issue 1, 2005, Pages 62-84

Inegalitarian Biocentric Consequentialism, the Minimax Implication and Multidimensional Value Theory: A Brief Proposal for a New Direction in Environmental Ethics

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 84857675014     PISSN: 09538208     EISSN: 17416183     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S0953820804001402     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (11)

References (65)
  • 6
    • 0003851057 scopus 로고
    • Atlanta and Amsterdam
    • Most notably in Robin Attfield, Value, Obligation and Meta-ethics (Atlanta and Amsterdam, 1995) and in Robin Attfield, The Ethics of the Global Environment (Edinburgh, 1999).
    • (1995) Value, Obligation and Meta-ethics
    • Attfield, R.1
  • 8
    • 84857680164 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Review of Robin Attfield, The Ethics of the Global Environment
    • See Alan Carter, 'Review of Robin Attfield, The Ethics of the Global Environment', Mind 110/437 (2001).
    • (2001) Mind , vol.110 , Issue.437
    • Carter, A.1
  • 10
    • 0006759023 scopus 로고
    • Overpopulation and the Quality of Life
    • ed. Peter Singer (Oxford)
    • For a clear statement of the Repugnant Conclusion, see Derek Parfit, 'Overpopulation and the Quality of Life', Applied Ethics, ed. Peter Singer (Oxford, 1986), p. 150.
    • (1986) Applied Ethics , pp. 150
    • Parfit, D.1
  • 11
    • 0003333322 scopus 로고
    • Obligations to Posterity'
    • ed. R. I. Sikora and Brian Barry (Philadelphia)
    • For seemingly compelling versions of the argument that we cannot harm distant future persons, see Thomas Schwartz, 'Obligations to Posterity', Obligations to Future Generations, ed. R. I. Sikora and Brian Barry (Philadelphia, 1978), and Thomas Schwartz, 'Welfare Judgments and Future Generations', Theory and Decision 11 (1979). For a rebuttal, see Alan Carter, 'Can We Harm Future People?', Environmental Values 10/4 (2001). Also see Alan Carter, 'On Harming Others', Environmental Values 11/1 (2002).
    • (1978) Obligations to Future Generations
    • Schwartz, T.1
  • 12
    • 0003103693 scopus 로고
    • Utilitarianism and New Generations
    • The Person-Affecting Principle was first deployed by Jan Narveson in order to avoid concluding that we are morally obliged to bring future persons into existence. See Jan Narveson, 'Utilitarianism and New Generations', Mind 76 (1967), and Jan Narveson, 'Moral Problems of Population', The Monist 57 (1973).
    • (1967) Mind , vol.76
    • Narveson, J.1
  • 13
    • 85008566369 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Biocentric Consequentialism, Pluralism and "The Minimax Implication": A Reply to Alan Carter
    • March
    • Attfield has acknowledged explicitly that his 'theory does imply that where . . . resources [for which there is competition] could be used either to satisfy hitherto unsatisfied basic needs, or to further develop the capacities of someone whose capacities are already well developed, and cannot be used for both purposes simultaneously, they should be devoted to the first rather than to the second purpose, for greater value is more likely to be delivered in this way' (Robin Attfield, 'Biocentric Consequentialism, Pluralism and "The Minimax Implication": A Reply to Alan Carter', Utilitas 15/1 (March 2003), p. 81).
    • (2003) Utilitas , vol.15 , Issue.1 , pp. 81
    • Attfield, R.1
  • 15
    • 85166630623 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Strictly speaking, it would be preferable to construe "minimax" as "the lowest level for the best off ". However, with regard to any capacity whose development is constrained by a limited resource, bringing about the lowest acceptable level for the greatest number of humans would itself imply minimising the level of the best off
    • 'Strictly speaking, it would be preferable to construe "minimax" as "the lowest level for the best off ". However, with regard to any capacity whose development is constrained by a limited resource, bringing about the lowest acceptable level for the greatest number of humans would itself imply minimising the level of the best off'.
  • 22
    • 85166662384 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Attfield, 'Biocentric Consequentialism', pp. 80-1. Indeed, Attfield even quotes me as referring to his core premisses. See Attfield, 'Biocentric Consequentialism', p. 80.
    • Biocentric Consequentialism , pp. 80-81
    • Attfield1
  • 27
    • 85166642960 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Attfield is correct in arguing that my first objection would have been better stated if I had referred to resources for which there is competition rather than merely to limited resources. See Attfield, 'Biocentric Consequentialism', p. 81. But the basic objection still stands: There are certain capacities the development of which is constrained by limited resources-some being resources for which there is competition- and Attfield's theory appears to imply that we should bring more people into the world who would have those capacities developed to a slight degree than restrict human numbers so as to have the capacities in question developed further by all existing and future humans. And that seems highly counter-intuitive
    • Attfield is correct in arguing that my first objection would have been better stated if I had referred to resources for which there is competition rather than merely to limited resources. See Attfield, 'Biocentric Consequentialism', p. 81. But the basic objection still stands: There are certain capacities the development of which is constrained by limited resources-some being resources for which there is competition- and Attfield's theory appears to imply that we should bring more people into the world who would have those capacities developed to a slight degree than restrict human numbers so as to have the capacities in question developed further by all existing and future humans. And that seems highly counter-intuitive.
  • 30
    • 85166657179 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I should mention that this strikes me as questionable. In overpopulated areas, some people have insufficient light because the buildings occupied by others are blocking their sunlight, and some have insufficient quiet (i.e. suffer from too much sound) because of the noise made by others. Distributions can often easily be reversed simply by individuals swapping apartments! If a person living next to a noisy highway were to exchange apartments with a person living in a basement four blocks away, then light would be removed from one person and supplied to the other, as would quiet
    • I should mention that this strikes me as questionable. In overpopulated areas, some people have insufficient light because the buildings occupied by others are blocking their sunlight, and some have insufficient quiet (i.e. suffer from too much sound) because of the noise made by others. Distributions can often easily be reversed simply by individuals swapping apartments! If a person living next to a noisy highway were to exchange apartments with a person living in a basement four blocks away, then light would be removed from one person and supplied to the other, as would quiet.
  • 34
    • 0000755331 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moral Theory and Global Population
    • Elsewhere, in an article cited by Attfield, I have mentioned the following objection to certain varieties of consequentialist theories: '[A]dvocates of human rights justifiably criticize [classical utilitarians] for not having safeguards at the very core of their theory which would protect individuals against their possible sacrifice for the pleasures of the majority' (Alan Carter, 'Moral Theory and Global Population', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 99/3 (1999), p. 300). Of course, as I added: 'Classical utilitarians can respond that happiness would not, in fact, be increased by sacrificing individuals, because everyone would feel insecure in a society that was prepared to act in such a way'. But most relevant for our present purposes is the remark that immediately follows, that any such 'reply indicates that any safeguards rely on contingent factors, rather than the theory recognising the inherent value of each individual'.
    • (1999) Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society , vol.99 , Issue.3 , pp. 300
    • Carter, A.1
  • 43
    • 85166673388 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For recall that Attfield explicitly states that 'where greater interests, such as interests in self-consciousness and autonomy, are endangered and conflict with lesser interests, they take priority' (Attfield, Global Environment, p. 159), and that 'interests can only be endangered if they and the creature to which they belong exist already' (Attfield, 'Biocentric Consequentialism', p. 85).
    • Global Environment , pp. 159
    • Attfield1
  • 44
    • 0002479337 scopus 로고
    • Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes'
    • ed. Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave (Cambridge)
    • See Imre Lakatos, 'Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes', Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, ed. Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave (Cambridge, 1970).
    • (1970) Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge
    • Lakatos, I.1
  • 47
    • 84936438611 scopus 로고
    • The Case against Moral Pluralism
    • Summer
    • J. Baird Callicott, 'The Case against Moral Pluralism', Environmental Ethics 12/2 (Summer 1990), p. 104.
    • (1990) Environmental Ethics , vol.12 , Issue.2 , pp. 104
    • Baird Callicott, J.1
  • 48
    • 84936438611 scopus 로고
    • The Case against Moral Pluralism
    • Summer
    • J. Baird Callicott, 'The Case against Moral Pluralism', Environmental Ethics 12/2 (Summer 1990), p. 110.
    • (1990) Environmental Ethics , vol.12 , Issue.2 , pp. 110
    • Baird Callicott, J.1
  • 50
    • 85166644055 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a critique of Callicott's own attempt to deal with a plurality of considerations, see the Appendix, below
    • For a critique of Callicott's own attempt to deal with a plurality of considerations, see the Appendix, below.
  • 51
    • 5044234947 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Value-Pluralist Egalitarianism'
    • See Alan Carter, 'Value-Pluralist Egalitarianism', Journal of Philosophy 99/11 (2002); and Carter, 'Moral Theory and Global Population'.
    • (2002) Journal of Philosophy , vol.99 , Issue.11
    • Carter, A.1
  • 54
    • 5644275450 scopus 로고
    • Duties to Endangered Species
    • ed. R. Elliot (Oxford)
    • See, for example, Holmes Rolston, III, 'Duties to Endangered Species', Environmental Ethics, ed. R. Elliot (Oxford, 1995).
    • (1995) Environmental Ethics
    • Rolston, H.1
  • 55
    • 0000916983 scopus 로고
    • Animal Liberation: A Triangular Affair
    • See, as the most famous (or infamous) instance, J. Baird Callicott, 'Animal Liberation: A Triangular Affair', Environmental Ethics 2 (1980). Also see Mark Sagoff, 'Animal Liberation and Environmental Ethics: Bad Marriage, Quick Divorce', Earth Ethics: Environmental Ethics, Animal Rights, and Practical Applications, ed. J. P. Sterba (Englewood Cliffs, NJ, 1995).
    • (1980) Environmental Ethics , vol.2
    • Baird Callicott, J.1
  • 56
  • 57
    • 85166669289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The asymptotic feature of certain indifference curves can provide a solution to the Repugnant Conclusion, while simultaneously avoiding the pitfalls of average utilitarianism. See Carter, 'Moral Theory and Global Population
    • The asymptotic feature of certain indifference curves can provide a solution to the Repugnant Conclusion, while simultaneously avoiding the pitfalls of average utilitarianism. See Carter, 'Moral Theory and Global Population'.
  • 58
    • 0034107184 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Humean Nature
    • It would be a mistake to assume that I hold all values as simply given. See Alan Carter, 'Humean Nature', Environmental Values 9/1 (2000), and Alan Carter, 'Projectivism and the Last Person Argument', The American Philosophical Quarterly 41/1 (2004).
    • (2000) Environmental Values , vol.9 , Issue.1
    • Carter, A.1
  • 62
    • 0348017933 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Conceptual Foundations of the Land Ethic
    • ed. M. E. Zimmerman, J. B. Callicott, G. Sessions, K. J. Warren and J. Clark, 2nd edn. (Upper Saddle River, NJ)
    • See J. Baird Callicott, 'The Conceptual Foundations of the Land Ethic', Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology, ed. M. E. Zimmerman, J. B. Callicott, G. Sessions, K. J. Warren and J. Clark, 2nd edn. (Upper Saddle River, NJ, 1998).
    • (1998) Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology
    • Baird Callicott, J.1
  • 64
    • 85166646113 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Holistic Environmental Ethics and the Problem of Ecofascism
    • ed. M. E. Zimmerman, J. B. Callicott, G. Sessions, K. J. Warren and J. Clark, 3rd edn. (Upper Saddle River, NJ)
    • J. Baird Callicott, 'Holistic Environmental Ethics and the Problem of Ecofascism', Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology, ed. M. E. Zimmerman, J. B. Callicott, G. Sessions, K. J. Warren and J. Clark, 3rd edn. (Upper Saddle River, NJ, 2001), p. 122.
    • (2001) Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology , pp. 122
    • Baird Callicott, J.1
  • 65
    • 85166646113 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Holistic Environmental Ethics and the Problem of Ecofascism
    • ed. M. E. Zimmerman, J. B. Callicott, G. Sessions, K. J. Warren and J. Clark, 3rd edn. (Upper Saddle River, NJ)
    • J. Baird Callicott, 'Holistic Environmental Ethics and the Problem of Ecofascism', Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology, ed. M. E. Zimmerman, J. B. Callicott, G. Sessions, K. J. Warren and J. Clark, 3rd edn. (Upper Saddle River, NJ, 2001), pp. 123-4.
    • (2001) Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology , pp. 123-124
    • Baird Callicott, J.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.