메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 121, Issue 4, 2011, Pages 693-716

The instability of freedom as noninterference: The case of isaiah berlin

(1)  Pettit, Philip a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 81755171458     PISSN: 00141704     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1086/660694     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (99)

References (95)
  • 2
    • 35148875077 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Immanuel Kant, Notes and Fragments, ed. Paul Guyer (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005), 11.
    • (2005) Notes and Fragments , pp. 11
    • Kant, I.1
  • 5
    • 81755181411 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This contains Berlin's 1958 lecture on "Two Concepts of Liberty" but also, especially in the long introduction, a good deal of later commentary. In the text, I often distinguish between references to the lecture itself and references to the commentary.
  • 6
    • 81755169111 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The thinker in whom Berlin finds the view he rejects is not Hobbes but John Stuart Mill (ibid., 139).
  • 7
    • 81755164608 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This is strange, as Hobbes quite clearly endorses the view, while Mill is guilty, at most, of using a formulation that may seem to give it support: a formulation that refers to being in a position to do what you actually want rather than to do whatever you might come to want.
  • 11
    • 73649092903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Freedom as the absence of arbitrary power
    • note
    • Quentin Skinner, "Freedom as the Absence of Arbitrary Power," in Republicanism and Political Theory, ed. C. Laborde and J. Maynor (Oxford: Blackwell, 2008), 83-102.
    • (2008) Republicanism and Political Theory , pp. 83-102
    • Skinner, Q.1
  • 13
    • 0040936835 scopus 로고
    • note
    • Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, ed. E. Curley (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1994), chap. 21.2.
    • (1994) Leviathan
    • Hobbes, T.1
  • 14
    • 81755176852 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mere incapacity to attain a goal is not lack of political liberty
    • note
    • I ignore questions raised by Hobbes's assumption that freedom presupposes the ability to take the options over which you are free: they must be within your "strength and wit." For the record, Berlin denies that freedom presupposes ability in this way, insisting that you may be free to vote even when you are too ill to go to the polls: "Mere incapacity to attain a goal is not lack of political liberty" (Four Essays on Liberty, 122).
    • Four Essays On Liberty , pp. 122
  • 16
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고
    • note
    • see also lii). He is followed in this view of what is required for the value as distinct from the nature of freedom by Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1971).
    • (1971) A Theory of Justice
  • 18
    • 0009280816 scopus 로고
    • Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility
    • Harry Frankfurt, "Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility," Journal of Philosophy 66 (1969): 829-39.
    • (1969) Journal of Philosophy , vol.66 , pp. 829-839
    • Frankfurt, H.1
  • 20
    • 81755176850 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Given that Hobbes thinks that any form of external hindrance takes from your freedom, he does not belong to the school of thought described in the introduction. Casting him as a foil to Berlin, however, I concentrate only on the hindrance imposed by other human beings; I treat him as if he did belong to that school. Berlin defends his focus on the hindering effects of human action, quoting Rousseau's claim that "the nature of things does not madden us, only ill will does" (ibid., 122).
  • 21
    • 81755182885 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The reference to ill will strongly suggests the need for intention-as other passages also do-but Berlin goes on, confusingly, to say that when other human beings restrict us, this action oppresses us, whether it is performed "with or without the intention of doing so." I take this to be just a slip.
  • 22
    • 81755182877 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Ibid., 123.
  • 23
    • 81755169112 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Ibid., 128.
  • 24
    • 81755169106 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Ibid., xxxviii.
  • 25
    • 81755169101 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Ibid., 139.
  • 26
    • 81755181406 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Strictly, there is a problem in saying that to be free in the choice of A, it must be the case that you could have chosen the alternative, B, had you wanted to -had you preferred that option. This condition might be incapable of fulfillment because you are the sort of person who would only want to do B if it was not available; the possibility will be salient from Groucho Marx's quip that he would only want to join a club that would not accept him as a member. The problem can be overcome if what is required is that you could have chosen B had you tried to do so, where it is not required in that eventuality that you actually prefer B. For expressive convenience, I ignore this complication in the text. I am grateful to Lara Buchak for drawing the problem to my attention.
  • 27
    • 81755182876 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Ibid., xxxix.
  • 28
    • 81755176859 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Ibid., xlviii
  • 29
    • 81755169103 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • see also xxxix.
  • 30
    • 81755176854 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In the original lecture, he comes close to endorsing the open-doors metaphor, despite his endorsement of Hobbes, when he denounces those who would "block every door but one," even one that opens on a "noble prospect" (127).
  • 35
    • 81755169110 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Although I shall speak in what follows of interference without qualification, it might be more appropriate and even more faithful to Berlin's point of view-though not, as it happens, his precise formulations-to take him to have only unlicensed interference in mind. Licensed or nonarbitrary interference, as I think of it, materializes on terms laid down by the interferee, as in the example of how his sailors treat Ulysses.
  • 36
    • 69049108968 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Republican Liberty: Three Axioms, Four Theorems
    • note
    • Philip Pettit, "Republican Liberty: Three Axioms, Four Theorems," in Laborde and Maynor, Republicanism and Political Theory.
    • Republicanism and Political Theory
    • Pettit, P.1
  • 39
    • 81755176853 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., xxxviii.
  • 40
    • 81755176841 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Carter, Measure of Freedom, and Kramer, Quality of Freedom. They will argue that where adaptation is required for being able to take a particular option-and also, to anticipate, where ingratiation is required for that result-the agent loses out in overall freedom, not being in a position to choose the option-without-adaptation or the option-without-ingratiation.
    • Measure of Freedom, and Kramer, Quality of Freedom
    • Carter1
  • 41
    • 81755181410 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The observation may soften the difficulty of living with the conclusion of Berlin's argument-that one can make oneself free in a given choice by adaptation or ingratiation-but it does not remove it; the intuition remains that one cannot achieve freedom in that given choice just by adapting preferences or just by ingratiating yourself with an obstructive agent. For a general comment on the limitations of this overall-freedom line,
  • 43
    • 85012431467 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Capability and Freedom: A Defence of Sen
    • Philip Pettit, "Capability and Freedom: A Defence of Sen," Economics and Philosophy 17 (2001): 1-20.
    • (2001) Economics and Philosophy , vol.17 , pp. 1-20
    • Pettit, P.1
  • 45
    • 81755181408 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • It may be enough, according to Berlin, that you enjoy noninterference in the nearest possible world or worlds in which you choose the other option, B. Or it may be required that there is a larger range of possible Y-worlds where noninterference is absent. These might be defined in a context-sensitive way but certainly cannot include all possible worlds in which you choose B. The fact that you would attract interference in the remote possible world where B would bring about the end of all sentient life, e.g., hardly shows that you are actually unfree in choosing between A and B. I abstract from this issue here, as I abstract from the related issue of whether it is necessary, not just that you are actually not interfered with in choosing A, but that you would not be interfered with in a range of other possible A-worlds: worlds that differ in intuitively irrelevant ways from the actual world. On issues about the relation between noninterference and freedom and about how contemporobust noninterference must be in order to constitute freedom
  • 47
    • 2542591016 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Impossibility of a Paretian Republican? Some Comments on Pettit and Sen
    • Christian List, "The Impossibility of a Paretian Republican? Some Comments on Pettit and Sen," Economics and Philosophy 20 (2004): 1-23
    • (2004) Economics and Philosophy , vol.20 , pp. 1-23
    • List, C.1
  • 48
    • 34248032160 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Republican Freedom and the Rule of Law
    • "Republican Freedom and the Rule of Law," Politics, Philosophy and Economics 5 (2006): 201-20.
    • (2006) Politics, Philosophy and Economics , vol.5 , pp. 201-220
  • 49
    • 81755181402 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • These issues are parallel to issues in epistemology about the relation between true belief and knowledge.
  • 50
    • 0004317645 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See, e.g., Timothy Williamson, Knowledge and Its Limits (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000).
    • (2000) Knowledge and Its Limits
  • 51
    • 81755176848 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • That the ideals are distinct does not rule out the possibility, however, that interference- with-frustration is worse, worse even in freedom terms, that interference-withoutfrustration.
  • 52
    • 69049083702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pettit's Molecule
    • note
    • Jeremy Waldron, "Pettit's Molecule," in Common Minds: Themes from the Philosophy of Philip Pettit, ed. G. Brennan, R. E. Goodin, F. Jackson, and M. Smith (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), 143-60. But see also the previous footnote.
    • (2007) Common Minds: Themes From the Philosophy of Philip Pettit , pp. 143-160
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 54
    • 49549086667 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Freedom and Probability: A Comment on Goodin and Jackson
    • Philip Pettit, "Freedom and Probability: A Comment on Goodin and Jackson," Philosophy and Public Affairs 36 (2008): 206-20.
    • (2008) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.36 , pp. 206-220
    • Pettit, P.1
  • 55
    • 81755169093 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The hypothetical probability P(Int if x) should be understood, not as a conditional probability, but in one of the alternative modes consistent with causal decision theory: e.g., as the probability of the truth of the appropriate subjunctive conditional.
  • 56
    • 0012084326 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See James M. Joyce, The Foundations of Causal Decision Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999). The conditional probability P(Int/x)-the probability of interference, given x- may be low for evidential rather than objective or causal reasons: say, because your taking x would be good evidence that I am friendly and unlikely to interfere.
    • The Foundations of Causal Decision Theory
    • Joyce, J.M.1
  • 57
    • 81755182878 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • What if you were close to certain that I would not be put off by any line you took in the choice between A and B, or in any other choice of that kind? What if you were so sure of my favorable attitude toward you that you had no fear of alienating me and triggering interference? Would there still be a sense in which your choice was subject to my will? The right response to this query is that you could not think of me as such a mechanically predetermined entity-and certainly could not manifest that view-while ontinuing to see and treat me as an agent. Suppose that you are disposed to hold me esponsible as an agent for whatever I turn out to do in a given choice that affects your nterests, so that you will feel gratitude or resentment at the decision I take. You must then think of me, before the decision is made, as being in a position to take one or another course, depending on my will. And that attitude rules out the sort of certainty envisaged here. For such a viewpoint
  • 60
    • 81755182872 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Inevitably, this presentation of freedom as nondomination is not as cautious as it might be. Two points of caution, in particular, should be registered. One is that you do not depend on the will of another in the relevant sense just in virtue of your options being dependent on what they, perhaps in ignorance of your existence, choose to do
  • 61
    • 81755176842 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • in that case, you do not depend on their will as to what you should do: they may have no wishes about what you should do. And another is that you do not depend on the will of others just in virtue of the fact that a majority in your society might coalesce and take against you
  • 62
    • 81755181397 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • short of coalescing or incorporating, they do not constitute an existent agency that dominates you, and the possibility of such a development testifies only to possible, not actual, domination.
  • 63
    • 81755181400 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Indeed, the varieties of domination are even richer than this suggests. I may interfere with you, as explained earlier, by removing or replacing an option, by denying you information about the options, or by undermining your capacity to reason properly about them. But this means that I may have the power to interfere with you in a given choice, should my will incline that way-i.e., I may dominate you-not just in virtue of superior resources, intuitively understood, but even in virtue of your believing that I have such resources. If you do believe that I have those resources, then I will have the power to deceive you in the choice: say, by making a bluff threat to stop you doing one or another option. All of this illustrates Hobbes's remark that "reputation of power is power."
  • 65
    • 0004215391 scopus 로고
    • note
    • Richard Price, Political Writings (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 26.
    • (1991) Political Writings , pp. 26
    • Price, R.1
  • 69
    • 81755169963 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Imagine, then, that you face a choice between options A and B. By Berlin's lights it must be the case that you avoid interference both in the A-scenario-the world where you choose A-and in the B-scenario. By republican lights, you should avoid interference in the corresponding four scenarios, described as A-F, A-H, B-F, and B-H. But this description of the positions raises a natural question parallel to one raised in an earlier footnote on Berlin. How encompassing should the A-F scenario be-and the A-H, B-F, and B-H scenarios? At a minimum, it might reduce to a singleton-the nearest possible world, as we say, in which A-F holds; and I have written, implicitly, as if this is the way to think: it fits with the standard reading of the counterfactual conditional. At a maximum, it might encompass all those possible worlds where A-F holds true, including outlandishly unlikely worlds where, say, a more powerful, extragalactic species invades earth. On the most plausible understanding, however, it should probably be taken to refer us to a range of possible worlds, salient on the basis of a background, contextually sensitive understanding, where you choose A and others are friendly. I cannot discuss the question further in this context.
  • 72
    • 81755182868 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I abstract from the question of whether, according to Berlin, establishing this minimal area, and thereby enabling each person to be free, also requires providing for the value of that freedom in the sense discussed in an earlier footnote: i.e., also requires giving people the wherewithal to enjoy the exercise of choice in that area. I assume that at least an updated version of the republican ideal of the free person, mentioned later in this section, would require such support.
  • 77
    • 84920075134 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Basic Liberties
    • note
    • Philip Pettit, "The Basic Liberties," in Essays on H. L. A. Hart, ed. M. Kramer (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008), 201-224.
    • (2008) Essays On H. L. A. Hart , pp. 201-224
    • Pettit, P.1
  • 85
    • 81755176834 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Perhaps this is what Berlin himself registered in saying that the "connection between democracy and individual liberty is a good deal more tenuous than it seemed to many advocates of both" (ibid., 130-31).
  • 86
    • 81755176835 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Ibid., lvi.
  • 87
    • 0009386564 scopus 로고
    • note
    • Douglas C. Long, Bentham on Liberty (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1977), 54.
    • (1977) Bentham On Liberty , pp. 54
    • Long, D.C.1
  • 88
    • 81755176832 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Law and Liberty
    • note
    • Philip Pettit, "Law and Liberty," in Law and Republicanism, ed. S. Besson and J. L. Marti (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), 39-59.
    • (2009) Law and Republicanism , pp. 39-59
    • Pettit, P.1
  • 91
    • 84923485817 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Two Republican Traditions
    • note
    • See also Philip Pettit, "Two Republican Traditions," in Republican Democracy: Liberty, Law and Politics, ed. A. Niederbeger and P. Schink (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, forthcoming).
    • Republican Democracy: Liberty, Law and Politics
    • Pettit, P.1
  • 93
    • 69049114285 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Neo-Republicanism: A Normative and Institutional Research Program
    • Frank Lovett and Philip Pettit, "Neo-Republicanism: A Normative and Institutional Research Program," Annual Review of Political Science 12 (2009): 11-29
    • (2009) Annual Review of Political Science , vol.12 , pp. 11-29
    • Lovett, F.1    Pettit, P.2
  • 94
    • 75949115674 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Republican Law of Peoples," in "Republicanism and International Relations
    • note
    • Philip Pettit, "A Republican Law of Peoples," in "Republicanism and International Relations," ed. Duncan Bell, special issue, European Journal of Political Theory 9 (2010): 70-94. For a recent articulation of the republican theory of democracy
    • (2010) European Journal of Political Theory , vol.9 , pp. 70-94
    • Pettit, P.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.