-
4
-
-
0039123032
-
-
in DOING AND DESERVING: ESSAYS IN THE THEORY OF RESPONSIBILITY, 95-118. See also FEINBERG, THE MORAL LIMITS OF THE CRIMINAL LAW note 1, at
-
JOEL FEINBERG, The Expressive Function of Punishment, in DOING AND DESERVING: ESSAYS IN THE THEORY OF RESPONSIBILITY, 95-118 (1970). See also FEINBERG, THE MORAL LIMITS OF THE CRIMINAL LAW note 1, at 24.
-
(1970)
The Expressive Function of Punishment
, pp. 24
-
-
FEINBERG, J.1
-
5
-
-
85022352420
-
-
The Expressive Function of Punishment note 1, at
-
FEINBERG, The Expressive Function of Punishment note 1, at 4.
-
FEINBERG
, pp. 4
-
-
-
8
-
-
85022352420
-
-
THE MORAL LIMITS OF THE CRIMINAL LAW note 1, at
-
FEINBERG, THE MORAL LIMITS OF THE CRIMINAL LAW note 1, at 116.
-
FEINBERG
, pp. 116
-
-
-
9
-
-
85022416673
-
-
FEINBERG note 7, at
-
FEINBERG, FEINBERG note 7, at 10-11.
-
FEINBERG
, pp. 10-11
-
-
-
10
-
-
85022399693
-
-
Paternalistic reasons are said to be “weightless,” “trumped,” “illegitimate,” “not good” or “invalid”; cf. JOEL FEINBERG, THE MORAL LIMITS OF THE CRIMINAL LAW, HARMLESS WRONGDOING, 320-323. Feinberg never availed himself-so far as I know-of the Razian idiom of the “excluded” reason.
-
Feinberg variously expresses this idea. Paternalistic reasons are said to be “weightless,” “trumped,” “illegitimate,” “not good” or “invalid”; cf. JOEL FEINBERG, THE MORAL LIMITS OF THE CRIMINAL LAW, vol. 4 HARMLESS WRONGDOING, 320-323 (1988). Feinberg never availed himself-so far as I know-of the Razian idiom of the “excluded” reason.
-
(1988)
Feinberg variously expresses this idea
, vol.4
-
-
-
11
-
-
85022416673
-
-
Feinberg variously expresses this idea. note 1, at
-
FEINBERG, Feinberg variously expresses this idea. note 1, at 115-116.
-
FEINBERG
, pp. 115-116
-
-
-
12
-
-
85022401173
-
-
by fully voluntary, self-regarding actions of his own” (id. at 115); and in the same passage he goes on to say that, given volenti, such harm is never a wrong (id. at 116). But in further discussion Feinberg reiterates that an agent can change what is a harm to him by changing his interests (see, e.g., FEINBERG, FEINBERG note 10, at 22-23); and his discussion of personal sovereignty (FEINBERG, FEINBERG note 7, at 60-62, 94) makes clear that what is in one's interests is ultimately one's own call-once all relevant facts have been disclosed, all risks discounted, and all pertinent adjustments of one's personal “network of interests” have been made (cf. FEINBERG, FEINBERG note 1, at 41-42, 55-61).
-
True, at one point Feinberg says that “There is no doubt that a person can be harmed… by fully voluntary, self-regarding actions of his own” (id. at 115); and in the same passage he goes on to say that, given volenti, such harm is never a wrong (id. at 116). But in further discussion Feinberg reiterates that an agent can change what is a harm to him by changing his interests (see, e.g., FEINBERG, FEINBERG note 10, at 22-23); and his discussion of personal sovereignty (FEINBERG, FEINBERG note 7, at 60-62, 94) makes clear that what is in one's interests is ultimately one's own call-once all relevant facts have been disclosed, all risks discounted, and all pertinent adjustments of one's personal “network of interests” have been made (cf. FEINBERG, FEINBERG note 1, at 41-42, 55-61).
-
True, at one point Feinberg says that “There is no doubt that a person can be harmed
-
-
-
14
-
-
85022416673
-
-
Joel Feinberg and the Justification of Hard Paternalism note 7, at 143 ff.
-
FEINBERG, Joel Feinberg and the Justification of Hard Paternalism note 7, at 143 ff.
-
FEINBERG
-
-
-
16
-
-
85022350748
-
-
FEINBERG note 19 note 7, at
-
Cf. FEINBERG, FEINBERG note 19 note 7, at 94.
-
FEINBERG
, pp. 94
-
-
-
19
-
-
85022433045
-
-
Subject to soft antipaternalism's “substantial voluntariness” proviso. note 19 note 10, at
-
FEINBERG, Subject to soft antipaternalism's “substantial voluntariness” proviso. note 19 note 10, at 17, 22.
-
FEINBERG
, vol.17
, pp. 22
-
-
|