-
1
-
-
79958097747
-
Time without Change
-
expanded edition (Oxford: Oxford University Press)
-
Sydney Shoemaker, 'Time without Change', Identity, Cause, and Mind, expanded edition (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003), 49-56.
-
(2003)
Identity, Cause, and Mind
, pp. 49-56
-
-
Shoemaker, S.1
-
2
-
-
70350020748
-
Could time be change?
-
See Denis Corish, 'Could Time be Change?' Philosophy 84 (2009), 219-232. I argue there that Shoemaker's attempt to show the possibility of a time without change begs the question by assuming that time passes in a region without change because it passes in a distant region with change, which distant region has, apart from observation, no effect on the changeless region. In effect, Shoemaker assumes absolute time, which is time without change.
-
(2009)
Philosophy
, vol.84
, pp. 219-232
-
-
Corish, D.1
-
3
-
-
0004042029
-
-
New York: Humanities Press
-
For a general account of the two opposing schools see Richard M. Gale, The Language of Time (New York: Humanities Press, 1968), 3-33.
-
(1968)
The Language of Time
, pp. 3-33
-
-
Gale, R.M.1
-
4
-
-
0043171143
-
-
New Haven and London: Yale University Press
-
There has been some refinement since, particularly as regards the translation of the language of the one school into that of the other, and with some interesting discussion of truth conditions for tensed sentences - see, for example, L. Nathan Oaklander and Quentin Smith (eds.), The New Theory of Time (New Haven and London: Yale University Press, 1994)
-
(1994)
The New Theory of Time
-
-
Oaklander, L.N.1
Smith, Q.2
-
5
-
-
0011763386
-
-
London and New York: Routledge
-
and D. H. Mellor, Real Time II (London and New York: Routledge, 1998)
-
(1998)
Real Time II
-
-
Mellor, D.H.1
-
6
-
-
79958079086
-
-
London and New York: Routledge
-
and there is now also a four-volume collection edited by Oaklander, The Philosophy of Time (London and New York: Routledge, 2008).
-
(2008)
The Philosophy of Time
-
-
Oaklander1
-
7
-
-
8644239962
-
-
London: Hutchinson
-
See, for example, Gale, op. cit. note 1, 88, also P. T. Geach, Truth, Love, and Immortality (London: Hutchinson, 1979), 90.
-
(1979)
Truth, Love, and Immortality
, pp. 90
-
-
Geach, P.T.1
-
8
-
-
0004317042
-
-
Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press
-
Robin Le Poidevin and Murray MacBeath (eds.), The Philosophy of Time (Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press, 1993), 6. It seems to have been expressions such as 'more past than' which made Gale think of circularity in such attempts.
-
(1993)
The Philosophy of Time
, pp. 6
-
-
Le Poidevin, R.1
MacBeath, M.2
-
9
-
-
0006634902
-
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
For an account of such a series see, for example, E. V. Huntington, The Continuum and Other Types of Serial Order (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1917). An example of a simply ordered class in such a relation is, according to Huntington (16), 'The class of all instants of time, arranged in order of priority.'
-
(1917)
The Continuum and Other Types of Serial Order
-
-
Huntington, E.V.1
-
10
-
-
79958099990
-
-
For an account of time as change itself see my 'Could Time be Change?' 223-232.
-
Could Time Be Change?
, pp. 223-232
-
-
-
11
-
-
79958112789
-
-
Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press
-
Even Michael Tooley, who wishes in some sense to bridge the gap between the rival views with 'a third way', based on causation, accepts that there are two rival views and maintains that 'tenseless concepts and facts are more basic than tensed ones' - Michael Tooley, Time, Tense, and Causation (Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press, 1997), 29, 380-381.
-
(1997)
Time, Tense, and Causation
, vol.29
, pp. 380-381
-
-
Tooley, M.1
-
12
-
-
62149111622
-
McTaggart's argument
-
Denis Corish, 'McTaggart's Argument', Philosophy 80 (2005), 79-80. Similarly, as I pointed out in the same paper (90), the two statements from which McTaggart would like to get a contradiction, 'Past, present and future are incompatible determinations' and 'But every event has them all' can in fact be true together. Here we see that as individuals related to each other past, present and future are incompatible, but as individuals that change their classes, present becoming past, future becoming present, they are not.
-
(2005)
Philosophy
, vol.80
, pp. 79-80
-
-
Corish, D.1
-
13
-
-
0004283438
-
-
New York: Macmillan Publishing Company
-
So 'Detroit is between New York and Chicago' is given as an example of a triadic relation in Irving M. Copi, Symbolic Logic Fifth Edition (New York: Macmillan Publishing Company, 1979), 117, even though the directional relation between New York and Detroit is (roughly) the same as that between Detroit and Chicago, so that that relation, a dyadic one, is repeated: as New York is east of Detroit so Detroit is east of Chicago.
-
(1979)
Symbolic Logic Fifth Edition
, pp. 117
-
-
Copi, I.M.1
-
14
-
-
79958084733
-
-
We could, as I pointed out in 'McTaggart's Argument', 84-85 - something which again points to the dyadic nature of past-present-future - contrive an artificial but perfectly logical similar three-term arrangement in the other dyadic series, by introducing something like the impermanence that is natural in time. So, for example, in number, if we envisage that each successive number in turn, running in the same direction, from, say, smaller to greater, has some property like that of time t at time t as a replacement - call it, whatever it is, 'numerus', or by any other arbitrary but constant name - then we have greater-than-numerus (which in turn becomes numerus), numerus, and less-than-numerus (which becomes in order less and less than numerus), a three-term situation in number exactly similar to past, present and future in time. And similarly, mutatis mutandis, for space and the more general precedes-succeeds. The situation is artificial for these other dyadic series, but the mere logical possibility, based on replacement and the repetition of the dyadic relation, of smaller-greater, left-right, say, and precedes-succeeds, is telling.
-
McTaggart's Argument
, pp. 84-85
-
-
-
15
-
-
79954313610
-
-
Aristotle, Physics II. 2. 193b31-35.
-
Physics
, vol.2
, Issue.2
-
-
Aristotle1
-
16
-
-
62149148115
-
Time reconsidered
-
What the ontology may be that permits or requires such a logic I have tried to indicate in Denis Corish, 'Time Reconsidered', Philosophy 81 (2006), 81-106.
-
(2006)
Philosophy
, vol.81
, pp. 81-106
-
-
Corish, D.1
-
17
-
-
79958113915
-
The continuum
-
It involves, I believe, a developed account of time as relative, in the sense disputed in The Leibniz-Clarke Correspondence - and which may be consistent with relativity theory - of which I tried to give an outline in a much earlier paper: Corish, 'The Continuum', The Review of Metaphysics XXII (1969), 523-546.
-
(1969)
The Review of Metaphysics
, vol.22
, pp. 523-546
-
-
Corish1
-
18
-
-
79958101573
-
Time, space and freewill: The leibniz-clarke correspondence
-
edited by J. T. Fraser, N. Lawrence, D. Park (New York, Heidelberg, Berlin: Springer-Verlag)
-
Also in Corish, 'Time, Space and Freewill: The Leibniz-Clarke Correspondence', The Study of Time III, edited by J. T. Fraser, N. Lawrence, D. Park (New York, Heidelberg, Berlin: Springer- Verlag, 1978), 634-657, I give some consideration to why Leibniz himself did not produce such a developed, or even adequate, account.
-
(1978)
The Study of Time
, vol.3
, pp. 634-657
-
-
Corish1
|