메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 99, Issue 4, 2011, Pages 901-959

Uncertainty

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 79956151028     PISSN: 00168092     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (61)

References (392)
  • 2
    • 56849117488 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Stern review and its critics: Implications for the theory and practice of benefit-cost analysis
    • For a discussion of the debate over the Stern Review, see (Winter)
    • For a discussion of the debate over the Stern Review, see Daniel H. Cole, The Stern Review and Its Critics: Implications for the Theory and Practice of Benefit-Cost Analysis, 48 NAT. RESOURCES J. 53 (Winter 2008).
    • (2008) Nat. Resources J. , vol.48 , pp. 53
    • Cole, D.H.1
  • 3
    • 79956106414 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1
    • Cole, supra note 1, at 76.
    • Cole1
  • 6
    • 0004066308 scopus 로고
    • Uncertainty also played a central role in the thought of John Maynard Keynes
    • FRANK KNIGHT, RISK, UNCERTAINTY AND PROFIT (1921). Uncertainty also played a central role in the thought of John Maynard Keynes.
    • (1921) Risk, Uncertainty and Profit
    • Knight, F.1
  • 8
    • 79956136955 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra sections III.A, III.B
    • See infra sections III.A, III.B.
  • 9
    • 79956110495 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra section III.E
    • See infra section III.E.
  • 10
    • 79956118228 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Probabilities, planning failures, and environmental law
    • 269
    • Dave Owen, Probabilities, Planning Failures, and Environmental Law, 84 TUL. L. REV. 265, 269 (2009).
    • (2009) Tul. L. Rev. , vol.84 , pp. 265
    • Owen, D.1
  • 11
    • 79956118228 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Probabilities, planning failures, and environmental law
    • Quantification of risks is required for cost-benefit analysis, which has been mandated for the past twenty-eight years when the government issues important regulations. Shortly after taking office President Reagan signed Executive Order No. 12,291, 46 Fed. Reg. 13,193 (Feb. 17, 1981), aimed at improving the efficiency of informal rulemaking by executive agencies. Section 2 prohibits issuance of "major" regulations unless, "taking into account the condition of the particular industries affected by regulations [and] the condition of the national economy," the potential benefits to society outweigh potential costs, and net benefits are at a maximum. Id
    • Quantification of risks is required for cost-benefit analysis, which has been mandated for the past twenty-eight years when the government issues important regulations. Shortly after taking office President Reagan signed Executive Order No. 12,291, 46 Fed. Reg. 13,193 (Feb. 17, 1981), aimed at improving the efficiency of informal rulemaking by executive agencies. Section 2 prohibits issuance of "major" regulations unless, "taking into account the condition of the particular industries affected by regulations [and] the condition of the national economy," the potential benefits to society outweigh potential costs, and net benefits are at a maximum. Id.
    • (2009) Tul. L. Rev. , vol.84
    • Owen, D.1
  • 12
    • 61349106049 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Saving lives through administrative law and economics
    • For recent defenses of cost-benefit analysis
    • For recent defenses of cost-benefit analysis, see John D. Graham, Saving Lives Through Administrative Law and Economics, 157 U. PA. L. REV. 395 (2008)
    • (2008) U. Pa. L. Rev. , vol.157 , pp. 395
    • Graham, J.D.1
  • 13
    • 79956138851 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Monetizing the benefits of risk and environmental regulation
    • W. Kip Viscusi, Monetizing the Benefits of Risk and Environmental Regulation, 33 FORDHAM URB. L.J. 1003 (2006).
    • (2006) Fordham Urb. L.J. , vol.33 , pp. 1003
    • Viscusi, W.K.1
  • 14
    • 0035998098 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pricing the priceless: Cost-benefit analysis of environmental protection
    • For a vigorous critique of the way cost-benefit analysis treats environmental and health risks
    • For a vigorous critique of the way cost-benefit analysis treats environmental and health risks, see Frank Ackerman & Lisa Heinzerling, Pricing the Priceless: Cost-Benefit Analysis of Environmental Protection, 150 U. PA. L. REV. 1553 (2002).
    • (2002) U. Pa. L. Rev. , vol.150 , pp. 1553
    • Ackerman, F.1    Heinzerling, L.2
  • 15
    • 79956136934 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra text accompanying note 44
    • See infra text accompanying note 44.
  • 16
    • 79956089216 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra text accompanying notes 92-109
    • See infra text accompanying notes 92-109.
  • 17
    • 79956086043 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra text accompanying notes 110-14
    • See infra text accompanying notes 110-14.
  • 18
    • 79956113048 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra text accompanying notes 116-29
    • See infra text accompanying notes 116-29.
  • 19
    • 79956123908 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra text accompanying notes 185-91
    • See infra text accompanying notes 185-91.
  • 20
    • 79956139874 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra text accompanying notes 227-29
    • See infra text accompanying notes 227-29.
  • 21
    • 79956114627 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As with all decision-making tools, these tools have their costs, and we must always consider whether the benefits of the tools outweigh the decision-making costs. But in most cases the incremental costs will not be high; if we have already determined that a single distribution has fat tails, or that two different models produce different results, the remaining steps in the analysis are often fairly straightforward
    • As with all decision-making tools, these tools have their costs, and we must always consider whether the benefits of the tools outweigh the decision-making costs. But in most cases the incremental costs will not be high; if we have already determined that a single distribution has fat tails, or that two different models produce different results, the remaining steps in the analysis are often fairly straightforward.
  • 22
    • 79956118751 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An important caveat is in order. The fundamental research discussed in this Article is rapidly developing, and work on practical applications is at an even earlier stage. Thus, the conclusions discussed in this Article-particularly as they bear on issues such as climate change-must be considered preliminary.
    • An important caveat is in order. The fundamental research discussed in this Article is rapidly developing, and work on practical applications is at an even earlier stage. Thus, the conclusions discussed in this Article-particularly as they bear on issues such as climate change-must be considered preliminary.
  • 23
    • 79956078929 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The models discussed in this Article may also have nonregulatory legal applications. For instance, litigation of major cases may involve uncertainty about results that could affect settlement behavior and litigation strategy in ways relevant to the design of civil procedure rules. Use of ambiguity models in this context might be fruitful
    • The models discussed in this Article may also have nonregulatory legal applications. For instance, litigation of major cases may involve uncertainty about results that could affect settlement behavior and litigation strategy in ways relevant to the design of civil procedure rules. Use of ambiguity models in this context might be fruitful.
  • 24
    • 79956140375 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The term "model uncertainty" is sometimes used in this situation, in which we have one or more models of the world but are unsure which one is right. Dealing with model uncertainty is widely acknowledged to be difficult, supra note 4, ("One of the dimensions of uncertainty that is difficult to capture quantitatively (or even qualitatively) involves model uncertainty."). Even if we know the correct structure for the model, it may be difficult when using complex models to use observations to constrain uncertainties about parameters, although such techniques are now under development
    • The term "model uncertainty" is sometimes used in this situation, in which we have one or more models of the world but are unsure which one is right. Dealing with model uncertainty is widely acknowledged to be difficult. See COMM. ON IMPROVING RISK ANALYSIS APPROACHES USED BY THE U.S. EPA, supra note 4, at 105-06 ("One of the dimensions of uncertainty that is difficult to capture quantitatively (or even qualitatively) involves model uncertainty."). Even if we know the correct structure for the model, it may be difficult when using complex models to use observations to constrain uncertainties about parameters, although such techniques are now under development.
    • Comm. on Improving Risk Analysis Approaches used by the U.S. EPA , pp. 105-106
  • 25
    • 47149090951 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sensitivity analysis of uncertainty in model prediction
    • 2579
    • See Trent Russi, Andrew Packard, Ryan Feeley & Michael Frenklach, Sensitivity Analysis of Uncertainty in Model Prediction, 112 J. PHYSICAL CHEMISTRYA 2579, 2579 (2008).
    • (2008) J. Physical Chemistrya , vol.112 , pp. 2579
    • Russi, T.1    Packard, A.2    Feeley, R.3    Frenklach, M.4
  • 27
    • 84905630355 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some of the complexities are addressed with an eye to practical implementation in, A large literature covers the specific problems of determining the level of risk for toxic chemicals, particularly carcinogens, and considerable controversy continues on this subject
    • Some of the complexities are addressed with an eye to practical implementation in MICHAEL V. FRANK, CHOOSING SAFETY: A GUIDE TO USING PROBABILISTIC RISK ASSESSMENT AND DECISION ANALYSIS IN COMPLEX, HIGH-CONSEQUENCE SYSTEMS (2008). A large literature covers the specific problems of determining the level of risk for toxic chemicals, particularly carcinogens, and considerable controversy continues on this subject.
    • (2008) Choosing Safety: A Guide to Using Probabilistic Risk Assessment and Decision Analysis in Complex, High-Consequence Systems
    • Frank, M.V.1
  • 29
    • 79956113541 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some of the practical difficulties in public health studies are explored in Carole Bass, Solving a Massive Worker Health Puzzle, SCI. AM., Mar. 2008
    • ENVTL. PROT. AGENCY, SUPPLEMENTAL GUIDANCE FOR ASSESSING SUSCEPTIBILITY FROM EARLY-LIFE EXPOSURE TO CARCINOGENS (2005), http://www.epa.gov/ttn/atw/ childrens-supplement-final.pdf. Some of the practical difficulties in public health studies are explored in Carole Bass, Solving a Massive Worker Health Puzzle, SCI. AM., Mar. 2008, at 86.
    • (2005) Envtl. Prot. Agency, Supplemental Guidance for Assessing Susceptibility from Early-Life Exposure to Carcinogens , pp. 86
  • 35
    • 0004160829 scopus 로고
    • For a discussion of the need to keep the uncertainty of parameter estimates and model choice in mind when applying the results of risk analysis
    • For a discussion of the need to keep the uncertainty of parameter estimates and model choice in mind when applying the results of risk analysis, see ADAM M. FINKEL, CONFRONTING UNCERTAINTY IN RISK MANAGEMENT: A GUIDE FOR DECISIONMAKERS (1990).
    • (1990) Confronting Uncertainty in Risk Management: A Guide for Decisionmakers
    • Finkel, A.M.1
  • 36
    • 78651102650 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A recent popular book hammers home the point that serious mistakes can follow from attending only to the average rather than the full probability distribution, One of Savage's examples, climate change, is particularly relevant for our purposes. Savage asks the reader to consider a hypothetical in which, on average, we expect no sea level rise-perhaps because our best estimate is that climate change will not happen. Id. at 291. However, assume further that we are not certain of this outcome, and the range of possible sea levels forms a bell curve. Id. Savage observes that: "If the sea level ends up below expectations, then damage will be a bit lower than expected, but if sea level is above expectations, damage will be much worse than expected."
    • A recent popular book hammers home the point that serious mistakes can follow from attending only to the average rather than the full probability distribution. See SAM L. SAVAGE, THE FLAW OF AVERAGES: WHY WE UNDERESTIMATE RISK IN THE FACE OF UNCERTAINTY (2009). One of Savage's examples, climate change, is particularly relevant for our purposes. Savage asks the reader to consider a hypothetical in which, on average, we expect no sea level rise-perhaps because our best estimate is that climate change will not happen. Id. at 291. However, assume further that we are not certain of this outcome, and the range of possible sea levels forms a bell curve. Id. Savage observes that: "If the sea level ends up below expectations, then damage will be a bit lower than expected, but if sea level is above expectations, damage will be much worse than expected." Id. at 292-93. "Hence," he continues, "the damage associated with the average or expected sea level may be tolerable, but averaged over all the things a scorned and furious Mother Nature might do to us, the damage could be disastrous." Id. at 293. Savage emphasizes, "[F]or this analysis I assumed that the expected temperature would stay the same. Yet the uncertainty alone created great risk."
    • (2009) The Flaw of Averages: Why we Underestimate Risk in the Face of Uncertainty
    • Savage, S.L.1
  • 38
    • 84865132156 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Private Fuel Storage, L.L.C., 350-51
    • See, e.g., Private Fuel Storage, L.L.C., 56 N.R.C. 340, 350-51 (2002).
    • (2002) N.R.C. , vol.56 , pp. 340
  • 39
    • 84865134547 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • San Luis Obispo Mothers for Peace v. Nuclear Regulatory Comm'n, 1032 (9th Cir.)
    • San Luis Obispo Mothers for Peace v. Nuclear Regulatory Comm'n, 449 F.3d 1016, 1032 (9th Cir. 2006).
    • (2006) F.3d , vol.449 , pp. 1016
  • 40
    • 79956114091 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
    • (2006) F.3d , vol.449
  • 41
    • 79956092272 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Similarly, the Ninth Circuit overturned the Department of Energy's refusal to consider the risk that terrorists might attack a federal biological weapons laboratory. Tri-Valley Cares v. Dep't of Energy, (9th Cir.)
    • Similarly, the Ninth Circuit overturned the Department of Energy's refusal to consider the risk that terrorists might attack a federal biological weapons laboratory. Tri-Valley Cares v. Dep't of Energy, 203 F. App'x 105 (9th Cir. 2006).
    • (2006) F. App'x , vol.203 , pp. 105
  • 42
    • 79956097678 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Amergen Energy Co., No. 50-0219-LR, 2007 WL 595084 (Nuclear Regulatory Comm'n Feb. 26, 2007). Earlier, the agency had said that addressing terrorism was inappropriate because an EIS should only address environmental impacts that will result "with a fair degree of likelihood." Private Fuel Storage, L.L.C., 56 N.R.C. at 347. The agency's position was upheld in New Jersey Department of Environmental Protection v. U.S. Nuclear Regulatory Commission, 561 F.3d 132 (3d Cir. 2009), largely on the ground that relicensing of a plant would not be the "proximate cause" of any harm later resulting from a terrorist attack on the facility. Id. at 140. Legal readers will recall from the first year of law school that proximate cause is a slippery concept
    • Amergen Energy Co., No. 50-0219-LR, 2007 WL 595084 (Nuclear Regulatory Comm'n Feb. 26, 2007). Earlier, the agency had said that addressing terrorism was inappropriate because an EIS should only address environmental impacts that will result "with a fair degree of likelihood." Private Fuel Storage, L.L.C., 56 N.R.C. at 347. The agency's position was upheld in New Jersey Department of Environmental Protection v. U.S. Nuclear Regulatory Commission, 561 F.3d 132 (3d Cir. 2009), largely on the ground that relicensing of a plant would not be the "proximate cause" of any harm later resulting from a terrorist attack on the facility. Id. at 140. Legal readers will recall from the first year of law school that proximate cause is a slippery concept.
  • 43
    • 72549116029 scopus 로고
    • Vt. Yankee Nuclear Power Corp. v. Natural Res. Def. Council, Inc., 528
    • Vt. Yankee Nuclear Power Corp. v. Natural Res. Def. Council, Inc., 435 U.S. 519, 528 (1978).
    • (1978) U.S. , vol.435 , pp. 519
  • 44
    • 33750087361 scopus 로고
    • Balt. Gas & Elec. Co. v. Natural Res. Def. Council, Inc., 93
    • Balt. Gas & Elec. Co. v. Natural Res. Def. Council, Inc., 462 U.S. 87, 93 (1983).
    • (1983) U.S. , vol.462 , pp. 87
  • 45
    • 79956154467 scopus 로고
    • Id., (emphasis added)
    • Id. at 93-94 (emphasis added).
    • (1983) U.S. , vol.462 , pp. 93-94
  • 46
    • 79956072195 scopus 로고
    • Id., (citing Licensing and Regulatory Policy and Procedures for Environmental Protection; Uranium Fuel Cycle Impacts from Spent Fuel Reprocessing and Radioactive Waste Management, 44 Fed. Reg. 45,362, 45,368 (Aug. 2, 1979) (codified at 10 C.F.R. pt. 51)). The Commission ultimately determined that any undue optimism in the assumption of appropriate selection and perfect performance of the repository is offset by the cautious assumption, reflected in other parts of the Table, that all radioactive gases in the spent fuel would escape during the initial 6 to 20 year period that the repository remained open, and thus did not significantly reduce the overall conservatism of the S-3 Table. Id. (citation omitted)
    • Id. at 94 (citing Licensing and Regulatory Policy and Procedures for Environmental Protection; Uranium Fuel Cycle Impacts from Spent Fuel Reprocessing and Radioactive Waste Management, 44 Fed. Reg. 45,362, 45,368 (Aug. 2, 1979) (codified at 10 C.F.R. pt. 51)). The Commission ultimately determined that any undue optimism in the assumption of appropriate selection and perfect performance of the repository is offset by the cautious assumption, reflected in other parts of the Table, that all radioactive gases in the spent fuel would escape during the initial 6 to 20 year period that the repository remained open, and thus did not significantly reduce the overall conservatism of the S-3 Table. Id. (citation omitted).
    • (1983) U.S. , vol.462 , pp. 94
  • 47
    • 79956132939 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra text accompanying notes 258-60
    • See infra text accompanying notes 258-60.
  • 48
    • 79956158154 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Balt. Gas & Elec.
    • Balt. Gas & Elec., 462 U.S. at 102.
    • U.S. , vol.462 , pp. 102
  • 49
    • 79956139873 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. These figures, along with the zero estimate for emissions after permanent disposal, were found in table S-3, published by the Commission.
    • Id. at 102-03. These figures, along with the zero estimate for emissions after permanent disposal, were found in table S-3, published by the Commission.
    • U.S. , vol.462 , pp. 102-103
  • 50
    • 79956081418 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Environmental Effects of the Uranium Fuel Cycle, 39 Fed. Reg. 14,188, 14,191 (Apr. 22, 1974). Essentially, the Court contended that the table was not misleading as a whole even though the zero emissions number was wrong, because it was balanced by other figures that were deliberately set too high. Balt. Gas & Elec.
    • See Environmental Effects of the Uranium Fuel Cycle, 39 Fed. Reg. 14,188, 14,191 (Apr. 22, 1974). Essentially, the Court contended that the table was not misleading as a whole even though the zero emissions number was wrong, because it was balanced by other figures that were deliberately set too high. Balt. Gas & Elec., 462 U.S. at 101-03.
    • U.S. , vol.462 , pp. 101-103
  • 51
    • 33645480391 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Balt. Gas & Elec.
    • Balt. Gas & Elec., 462 U.S. at 103.
    • U.S. , vol.462 , pp. 103
  • 52
    • 77956818291 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • U.S. Nuclear waste law and policy: Fixing a bankrupt system
    • Richard Stewart describes the current nuclear waste disposal scheme as bankrupt, 783
    • Richard Stewart describes the current nuclear waste disposal scheme as bankrupt. Richard B. Stewart, U.S. Nuclear Waste Law and Policy: Fixing a Bankrupt System, 17 N.Y.U. ENVTL. L.J. 783, 783 (2008).
    • (2008) N.Y.U. Envtl. L.J. , vol.17 , pp. 783
    • Stewart, R.B.1
  • 53
    • 0030930654 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Redirecting the U.S. high-level nuclear waste program
    • For another blistering critique of the program from a decade earlier
    • For another blistering critique of the program from a decade earlier, see James Flynn et al., Redirecting the U.S. High-Level Nuclear Waste Program, 39 ENVIRONMENT 6 (1997).
    • (1997) Environment , vol.39 , pp. 6
    • Flynn, J.1
  • 54
    • 79956155024 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Although the probability may have been nearly zero in the agency's preferred model of the world, we cannot dismiss the risk unless we also know that this particular model is almost certainly correct. For instance, suppose that there are two models available for the storage facility. NRC is eighty percent sure that Model A is correct, but thinks there is a twenty percent chance that Model B is correct. Model A predicts a zero probability of a release. Model B predicts a ten percent probability of a release. The NRC's beliefs under this scenario can be summarized as follows: there is an eighty percent chance that the way the world works is described by Model A and that there is consequently no risk of a release, but a twenty percent chance that the way the world works is described by Model B and that there is consequently a ten percent chance of a release
    • Although the probability may have been nearly zero in the agency's preferred model of the world, we cannot dismiss the risk unless we also know that this particular model is almost certainly correct. For instance, suppose that there are two models available for the storage facility. NRC is eighty percent sure that Model A is correct, but thinks there is a twenty percent chance that Model B is correct. Model A predicts a zero probability of a release. Model B predicts a ten percent probability of a release. The NRC's beliefs under this scenario can be summarized as follows: there is an eighty percent chance that the way the world works is described by Model A and that there is consequently no risk of a release, but a twenty percent chance that the way the world works is described by Model B and that there is consequently a ten percent chance of a release. In this hypothetical situation, the NRC could truthfully say that the best estimate of the probability of a release is zero, and that it is highly confident of that estimate. But taking both models into account, there is actually a twenty percent chance that Model B is right, and then a ten percent chance under Model B that a release would take place. Putting these together means that the probability of a release is ten percent of twenty percent (0.1 × 0.2) or two percent (0.02). Two percent could be quite a significant risk if the costs associated with a release are high. No one would step on a commercial airplane with a two percent (one in fifty) chance of crashing. This example involves known probabilities rather than true uncertainty, but it illustrates a more general point: even if we are highly confident that the true probability of harm is zero, we are not justified in completely discounting the hazard, because if there is any possibility of a higher degree of harm, the expected level of harm is greater than zero. We can discount a hazard entirely only if we are certain that it is zero. Because a probability cannot be less than zero, anything short of complete confidence in a zero level of risk means there is some possibility of harm.
  • 55
    • 79956110123 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra text accompanying notes 230-63
    • See infra text accompanying notes 230-63.
  • 56
    • 84865629036 scopus 로고
    • 614-15, (plurality opinion). The only applicable statutory provision dealing expressly with toxic chemicals in the workplace is section 6(b)(5) of the Occupational Health and Safety Act. See 29 U.S.C. § 655(b)(5) (2006). This provision requires the agency to set a standard for any toxic material "which most adequately assures, to the extent feasible, that no employee will suffer material impairment of health or functional capacity." Another section of the Act, section 3(8), 29 U.S.C. § 652(8) (2006), is also relevant. This section simply defines an occupational safety and health standard as a regulation setting any one of a variety of requirements "reasonably necessary or appropriate to provide safe or healthful employment and places of employment."
    • 448 U.S. 607, 614-15 (1980) (plurality opinion). The only applicable statutory provision dealing expressly with toxic chemicals in the workplace is section 6(b)(5) of the Occupational Health and Safety Act. See 29 U.S.C. § 655(b)(5) (2006). This provision requires the agency to set a standard for any toxic material "which most adequately assures, to the extent feasible, that no employee will suffer material impairment of health or functional capacity." Another section of the Act, section 3(8), 29 U.S.C. § 652(8) (2006), is also relevant. This section simply defines an occupational safety and health standard as a regulation setting any one of a variety of requirements "reasonably necessary or appropriate to provide safe or healthful employment and places of employment."
    • (1980) U.S. , vol.448 , pp. 607
  • 57
    • 0002700335 scopus 로고
    • Good science, bad regulation, and toxic risk assessment
    • 91, 144, (arguing that "uncertainties generally preclude reliable assessments of relevant effects, and there is no scientific consensus on how they should be resolved" and that "[i]n view of the many uncertainties in toxic risk assessment, it is unclear whether risk ranges or point estimates create more of 'a false impression that the bounds of the risks are known with certainty'"). Prior to the Benzene Case, courts were more willing to accept evidence of unquantified risks as sufficient
    • See, e.g., Howard A. Latin, Good Science, Bad Regulation, and Toxic Risk Assessment, 5 YALE J. ON REG. 89, 91, 144 (1988) (arguing that "uncertainties generally preclude reliable assessments of relevant effects, and there is no scientific consensus on how they should be resolved" and that "[i]n view of the many uncertainties in toxic risk assessment, it is unclear whether risk ranges or point estimates create more of 'a false impression that the bounds of the risks are known with certainty'"). Prior to the Benzene Case, courts were more willing to accept evidence of unquantified risks as sufficient.
    • (1988) Yale J. On Reg. , vol.5 , pp. 89
    • Latin, H.A.1
  • 58
    • 79956112576 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The story of reserve mining: Managing scientific uncertainty in environmental regulation
    • See John S. Applegate, The Story of Reserve Mining: Managing Scientific Uncertainty in Environmental Regulation, in ENVIRONMENTAL LAW STORIES 43, 70-76
    • Environmental Law Stories , vol.43 , pp. 70-76
    • Applegate, J.S.1
  • 59
    • 79956151166 scopus 로고
    • 2005, (describing the precautionary approach taken in Reserve Mining Co. v. Envtl. Prot. Agency)
    • (Richard J. Lazarus & Oliver A. Houck eds., 2005) (describing the precautionary approach taken in Reserve Mining Co. v. Envtl. Prot. Agency, 514 F.2d 492 (1975)).
    • (1975) F.2d , vol.514 , pp. 492
    • Lazarus, R.J.1    Houck, O.A.2
  • 60
    • 33645900738 scopus 로고
    • For example, in Lead Industries Ass'n v. Environmental Protection Agency, 1184 (D.C. Cir.), the D.C. Circuit upheld a primary air quality standard for lead that incorporated an "adequate margin of safety." In setting the margin of safety, the EPA had given no consideration to feasibility or cost. Id. at 1148. Moreover, the evidence of harm was unclear. Id. at 1160. Nevertheless, the court held that feasibility and cost were irrelevant and that the EPA had acted properly in setting the margin of safety. Id. at 1148-49. The court explained Congress's directive to allow a margin of safety "to protect against effects which have not yet been uncovered by research and effects whose medical significance is a matter of disagreement." Id. at 1154
    • For example, in Lead Industries Ass'n v. Environmental Protection Agency, 647 F.2d 1130, 1184 (D.C. Cir. 1980), the D.C. Circuit upheld a primary air quality standard for lead that incorporated an "adequate margin of safety." In setting the margin of safety, the EPA had given no consideration to feasibility or cost. Id. at 1148. Moreover, the evidence of harm was unclear. Id. at 1160. Nevertheless, the court held that feasibility and cost were irrelevant and that the EPA had acted properly in setting the margin of safety. Id. at 1148-49. The court explained Congress's directive to allow a margin of safety "to protect against effects which have not yet been uncovered by research and effects whose medical significance is a matter of disagreement." Id. at 1154.
    • (1980) F.2d , vol.647 , pp. 1130
  • 61
    • 42649116430 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Standing and the precautionary principle
    • 499
    • Jonathan Remy Nash, Standing and the Precautionary Principle, 208 COLUM. L. REV. 494, 499 (2008).
    • (2008) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.208 , pp. 494
    • Nash, J.R.1
  • 62
    • 42649116430 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Standing and the precautionary principle
    • Id.
    • Id. at 498-99.
    • (2008) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.208 , pp. 498-499
    • Nash, J.R.1
  • 63
    • 42649116430 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Standing and the precautionary principle
    • Id.
    • Id. at 502-03.
    • (2008) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.208 , pp. 502-503
    • Nash, J.R.1
  • 65
    • 0000151878 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • More sorry than safe: Assessing the precautionary principle and the proposed international biosafety protocol
    • 195-98
    • See Jonathan H. Adler, More Sorry than Safe: Assessing the Precautionary Principle and the Proposed International Biosafety Protocol, 35 TEX. INT'L L.J. 173, 195-98 (2000).
    • (2000) Tex. Int'l L.J. , vol.35 , pp. 173
    • Adler, J.H.1
  • 66
    • 79956142590 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • United Nations Conference on Environment and Development, Rio de Janeiro, Braz., June 3-14, 1992, Rio Declaration on Environment and Development, U.N. Doc. A/CONF.151/26/Rev.1 (Vol. I), Annex I (Aug. 12, 1992)
    • United Nations Conference on Environment and Development, Rio de Janeiro, Braz., June 3-14, 1992, Rio Declaration on Environment and Development, U.N. Doc. A/CONF.151/26/Rev.1 (Vol. I), Annex I (Aug. 12, 1992).
  • 69
    • 33847359056 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The precautionary principle in Canada: The first decade
    • On the Canadian experience
    • On the Canadian experience, see Juli Abouchar, The Precautionary Principle in Canada: The First Decade, 32 ENVTL. L. REP. 11407 (2002).
    • (2002) Envtl. L. Rep. , vol.32 , pp. 11407
    • Abouchar, J.1
  • 70
    • 79956125914 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 50
    • See HUNTER, SALZMAN & ZELKE, supra note 50, at 407
    • Hunter1    Salzman2    Zelke3
  • 71
    • 79956100106 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bending nature, bending law
    • 575
    • David G. Owen, Bending Nature, Bending Law, 62 FLA. L. REV. 569, 575 (2010).
    • (2010) Fla. L. Rev. , vol.62 , pp. 569
    • Owen, D.G.1
  • 72
    • 79956133430 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Food Quality Protection Act of 1996, Pub. L. No. 104-170, 110 Stat. 1489
    • Food Quality Protection Act of 1996, Pub. L. No. 104-170, 110 Stat. 1489.
  • 73
    • 79956100106 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bending nature, bending law
    • Id. § 405, 110 Stat., at 1518 (codified as amended at 21 U.S.C. § 346a(b)(2)(C))
    • Id. § 405, 110 Stat., at 1518 (codified as amended at 21 U.S.C. § 346a(b)(2)(C))
    • (2010) Fla. L. Rev. , vol.62
    • Owen, D.G.1
  • 74
    • 72549098818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Nw. Coal. for Alts. to Pesticides v. U.S. Envtl. Prot. Agency, , 1051-53 (D.C. Cir.) (reversing the EPA for failing to provide such a justification for downward changes in the magnitude of the safety margin for certain chemicals)
    • See Nw. Coal. for Alts. to Pesticides v. U.S. Envtl. Prot. Agency, 544 F.3d 1043, 1051-53 (D.C. Cir. 2008) (reversing the EPA for failing to provide such a justification for downward changes in the magnitude of the safety margin for certain chemicals).
    • (2008) F.3d , vol.544 , pp. 1043
  • 75
    • 33847148531 scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Robertson v. Methow Valley Citizens Council, 350
    • See, e.g., Robertson v. Methow Valley Citizens Council, 490 U.S. 332, 350 (1989).
    • (1989) U.S. , vol.490 , pp. 332
  • 76
    • 79956070646 scopus 로고
    • The rise and fall of worst case analysis
    • For an overview
    • For an overview, see Edward A. Fitzgerald, The Rise and Fall of Worst Case Analysis, 18 U. DAYTON L. REV. 1 (1992).
    • (1992) U. Dayton L. Rev. , vol.18 , pp. 1
    • Fitzgerald, E.A.1
  • 77
    • 79956151697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 40 C.F.R § 1502.22(b) (1981). If (1) the information relevant to adverse impacts is essential to a reasoned choice among alternatives and is not known and the overall costs of obtaining it are exorbitant or (2) the information relevant to adverse impacts is important to the decision and the means to obtain it are not known ⋯ the agency shall weigh the need for the action against the risk and severity of possible adverse impacts were the action to proceed in the face of uncertainty. If the agency proceeds, it shall include a worst case analysis and an indication of the probability or improbability of its occurrence. Id. (emphasis added)
    • 40 C.F.R § 1502.22(b) (1981). If (1) the information relevant to adverse impacts is essential to a reasoned choice among alternatives and is not known and the overall costs of obtaining it are exorbitant or (2) the information relevant to adverse impacts is important to the decision and the means to obtain it are not known ⋯ the agency shall weigh the need for the action against the risk and severity of possible adverse impacts were the action to proceed in the face of uncertainty. If the agency proceeds, it shall include a worst case analysis and an indication of the probability or improbability of its occurrence. Id. (emphasis added).
  • 78
    • 79956136933 scopus 로고
    • Worst case analysis: The final chapter?
    • 10027
    • See Vicki O'Meara Masterman, Worst Case Analysis: The Final Chapter?, 19 ENVTL. L. REP. 10026, 10027 & n.14 (1989)
    • (1989) Envtl. L. Rep. , vol.19 , Issue.14 , pp. 10026
    • O'Meara Masterman, V.1
  • 79
    • 0001747645 scopus 로고
    • (quoting Forty Most Asked Questions Concerning CEQ's National Environmental Policy Act Regulations, 18,032 (Mar. 23) (to be codified at 40 C.F.R. pt. 1500-08)).
    • (quoting Forty Most Asked Questions Concerning CEQ's National Environmental Policy Act Regulations, 46 Fed. Reg. 18,026, 18,032 (Mar. 23, 1981) (to be codified at 40 C.F.R. pt. 1500-08)).
    • (1981) Fed. Reg. , vol.46 , pp. 18026
  • 80
    • 79956129596 scopus 로고
    • Note, federal agency treatment of uncertainty in environmental impact statements under the CEQ's Amended NEPA regulation § 1502.22: Worst case analysis or risk threshold?
    • 807-809
    • See Charles F. Weiss, Note, Federal Agency Treatment of Uncertainty in Environmental Impact Statements Under the CEQ's Amended NEPA Regulation § 1502.22: Worst Case Analysis or Risk Threshold?, 86 MICH. L. REV. 777, 807-09 (1988)
    • (1988) Mich. L. Rev. , vol.86 , pp. 777
    • Weiss, C.F.1
  • 81
    • 79956127495 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 40 C.F.R. § 1502.22 (2009). The revised regulation applies when an agency completing an EIS has "incomplete information" that is relevant to "reasonably foreseeable significant adverse impacts," including "impacts which have catastrophic consequences, even if their probability of occurrence is low, provided that the analysis of the impacts is supported by credible scientific evidence, is not based on pure conjecture, and is within the rule of reason." Id. If this information is "essential to a reasoned choice among alternatives" and the cost of obtaining it is not "exorbitant," the information must be included
    • 40 C.F.R. § 1502.22 (2009). The revised regulation applies when an agency completing an EIS has "incomplete information" that is relevant to "reasonably foreseeable significant adverse impacts," including "impacts which have catastrophic consequences, even if their probability of occurrence is low, provided that the analysis of the impacts is supported by credible scientific evidence, is not based on pure conjecture, and is within the rule of reason." Id. If this information is "essential to a reasoned choice among alternatives" and the cost of obtaining it is not "exorbitant," the information must be included. Id. If the information is relevant but cannot be obtained because the cost is too high or the "means to obtain it are not known," the impact statement must include four items: a statement of the information's unavailability; a statement of its relevance to reasonably foreseeable impacts; a summary of the existing scientific evidence relevant to assessing the impacts; and the agency's evaluation of these impacts based on generally accepted scientific methods. Id. This regulation seems reasonable, but it may not put enough pressure on agencies to face up to unpalatable adverse consequences from projects that they may well favor on other grounds.
  • 82
    • 33847148531 scopus 로고
    • Robertson v. Methow Valley Citizens Council, 359
    • Robertson v. Methow Valley Citizens Council, 490 U.S. 332, 359 (1989).
    • (1989) U.S. , vol.490 , pp. 332
  • 83
    • 79956138850 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra text accompanying notes 126-31
    • See infra text accompanying notes 126-31.
  • 84
    • 68249115347 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a recent update on the debate, see Fritz Allhoff, Risk, Precaution, and Emerging Technologies, STUD. IN ETHICS L. & TECH., Aug. 2009, http://www.bepress.com/selt/vol3/iss2/art2. Allhoff suggests that "precaution supplements cost-benefit analysis given uncertainty." Id. at 23
    • For a recent update on the debate, see Fritz Allhoff, Risk, Precaution, and Emerging Technologies, STUD. IN ETHICS L. & TECH., Aug. 2009, http://www.bepress.com/selt/vol3/iss2/art2. Allhoff suggests that "precaution supplements cost-benefit analysis given uncertainty." Id. at 23.
  • 85
    • 34249742645 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The big one: A review of richard posner's catastrophe: Risk and response
    • 152, (book review)
    • Edward A. Parson, The Big One: A Review of Richard Posner's Catastrophe: Risk and Response, 45 J. ECON. LITERATURE 147, 152 (2007) (book review)
    • (2007) J. Econ. Literature , vol.45 , pp. 147
    • Parson, E.A.1
  • 87
    • 0000959295 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Is there a precautionary principle?
    • 10791
    • Christopher D. Stone, Is There a Precautionary Principle?, 31 ENVTL. L. REP. 10790, 10791 (2001).
    • (2001) Envtl. L. Rep. , vol.31 , pp. 10790
    • Stone, C.D.1
  • 90
    • 79956100105 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 44, (footnote omitted). Nash calls this "the heartland of the precautionary principle." Id.
    • Nash, supra note 44, at 503 (footnote omitted). Nash calls this "the heartland of the precautionary principle." Id.
    • Nash1
  • 93
    • 79956077816 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 48
    • See Adler, supra note 48, at 195
    • Adler1
  • 94
    • 0001650575 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paradoxical perils of the precautionary principle
    • 863-75, (describing risks created by alternative activities in the face of precautionary government regulation of artificial sweeteners, electric power generation, and pesticides)
    • Frank B. Cross, Paradoxical Perils of the Precautionary Principle, 53 WASH. & LEE L. REV. 851, 863-75 (1996) (describing risks created by alternative activities in the face of precautionary government regulation of artificial sweeteners, electric power generation, and pesticides).
    • (1996) Wash. & Lee L. Rev. , vol.53 , pp. 851
    • Cross, F.B.1
  • 95
    • 0347335804 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Probability neglect: Emotions, worst cases, and law
    • 93, The version of precaution discussed in this Article is more forgiving toward technologies with high upside potential and hence seems less vulnerable to this criticism
    • Cass R. Sunstein, Probability Neglect: Emotions, Worst Cases, and Law, 112 YALE L.J. 61, 93 (2002). The version of precaution discussed in this Article is more forgiving toward technologies with high upside potential and hence seems less vulnerable to this criticism.
    • (2002) Yale L.J. , vol.112 , pp. 61
    • Sunstein, C.R.1
  • 98
    • 0347335804 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Probability neglect: Emotions, worst cases, and law
    • Id.
    • Id. at 94.
    • (2002) Yale L.J. , vol.112 , pp. 94
    • Sunstein, C.R.1
  • 99
    • 0347335804 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Probability neglect: Emotions, worst cases, and law
    • Id.
    • Id. at 62-63.
    • (2002) Yale L.J. , vol.112 , pp. 62-63
    • Sunstein, C.R.1
  • 100
    • 0037534321 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Beyond the precautionary principle
    • Sunstein further elaborated his critique in Cass
    • Sunstein further elaborated his critique in Cass R. Sunstein, Beyond the Precautionary Principle, 151 U. PA. L. REV. 1003 (2003).
    • (2003) U. Pa. L. Rev. , vol.151 , pp. 1003
    • Sunstein, R.1
  • 101
    • 0036522974 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bayesian approaches to the precautionary principle
    • 270, (arguing that "[i]n order to retain its credibility as a legitimate principle of environmental policymaking and not degenerate into an instrument of veiled protectionism," the precautionary principle should be implemented through a Bayesian approach)
    • See, e.g., Stephen Charest, Bayesian Approaches to the Precautionary Principle, 12 DUKE ENVTL. L. & POL'Y F. 265, 270 (2002) (arguing that "[i]n order to retain its credibility as a legitimate principle of environmental policymaking and not degenerate into an instrument of veiled protectionism," the precautionary principle should be implemented through a Bayesian approach)
    • (2002) Duke Envtl. L. & Pol'y F. , vol.12 , pp. 265
    • Charest, S.1
  • 102
    • 0000984760 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scientific progress and irreversibility: An economic interpretation of the 'precautionary principle,'
    • (proposing an economic interpretation of the precautionary principle)
    • Christian Gollier, Bruno Jullien & Nicolas Treich, Scientific Progress and Irreversibility: An Economic Interpretation of the 'Precautionary Principle,' 75 J. PUB. ECON. 229 (2000) (proposing an economic interpretation of the precautionary principle)
    • (2000) J. Pub. Econ. , vol.75 , pp. 229
    • Gollier, C.1    Jullien, B.2    Treich, N.3
  • 103
    • 26444621448 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Global climate change and the precautionary principle
    • (arguing for a Bayesian decision analysis approach to the precautionary principle in the context of global climate change)
    • W. David Montgomery & Anne E. Smith, Global Climate Change and the Precautionary Principle, 6 HUM. & ECOLOGICAL RISK ASSESSMENT 399 (2000) (arguing for a Bayesian decision analysis approach to the precautionary principle in the context of global climate change).
    • (2000) Hum. & Ecological Risk Assessment , vol.6 , pp. 399
    • Montgomery, W.D.1    Smith, A.E.2
  • 104
    • 79956106917 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 65, 10799, (arguing that "there appears to be so little content [to the precautionary principle], and so much confusion, that it may be helpful to return to some elementary principles of risk, uncertainty, and law" and "questioning the claim that there is a precautionary principle there")
    • But see Stone, supra note 65, at 10792, 10799, (arguing that "there appears to be so little content [to the precautionary principle], and so much confusion, that it may be helpful to return to some elementary principles of risk, uncertainty, and law" and "questioning the claim that there is a precautionary principle there").
    • Stone1
  • 105
    • 79956161348 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The case for cosmic prudence
    • 35-36
    • See Stephen Toulmin, The Case for Cosmic Prudence, 56 TENN. L. REV. 29, 35-36 (1998).
    • (1998) Tenn. L. Rev. , vol.56 , pp. 29
    • Toulmin, S.1
  • 106
    • 7544242893 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A behavioral economic defense of the precautionary principle
    • 1327-28, (arguing that the principle may "result in the generation of more information" and may "provide advocates of regulation with a discursive tool to increase the amount of information generated and the quality of the analysis of that information")
    • See David A. Dana, A Behavioral Economic Defense of the Precautionary Principle, 97 NW. U. L. REV. 1315, 1327-28 (2003) (arguing that the principle may "result in the generation of more information" and may "provide advocates of regulation with a discursive tool to increase the amount of information generated and the quality of the analysis of that information").
    • (2003) Nw. U. L. Rev. , vol.97 , pp. 1315
    • Dana, D.A.1
  • 107
    • 79956073104 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The contextual rationality of the precautionary principle
    • Dana elaborates his position in, [hereinafter Dana, Contextual Rationality]
    • Dana elaborates his position in David A. Dana, The Contextual Rationality of the Precautionary Principle, 35 QUEEN'S L.J. 67 (2009) [hereinafter Dana, Contextual Rationality].
    • (2009) Queen's L.J. , vol.35 , pp. 67
    • Dana, D.A.1
  • 108
    • 79956131902 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The catastrophic harm precautionary principle
    • See Cass R. Sunstein, The Catastrophic Harm Precautionary Principle, ISSUES LEGAL SCHOLARSHIP, 2007, http://www.bepress.com/ils/iss10/art3.
    • (2007) Issues Legal Scholarship
    • Sunstein, C.R.1
  • 115
    • 34548690996 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Complexity of coupled human and natural systems
    • (discussing feedback loops in coupled human and natural systems)
    • See generally Jainguao Liu et al., Complexity of Coupled Human and Natural Systems, 317 SCIENCE 1513 (2007) (discussing feedback loops in coupled human and natural systems).
    • (2007) Science , vol.317 , pp. 1513
    • Liu, J.1
  • 116
    • 79956106393 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 4 ⋯ = 1/(1 - f ) (by the algebra rule for summing geometric series). Lags in the process would complicate the results. Note that this formula applies only for f < 1; if f = 1 or f > 1, the series diverges (or in simpler terms, the sum is infinite)
    • 4 ⋯ = 1/(1 - f ) (by the algebra rule for summing geometric series). Lags in the process would complicate the results. Note that this formula applies only for f < 1; if f = 1 or f > 1, the series diverges (or in simpler terms, the sum is infinite).
  • 117
    • 33745835372 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Missing feedbacks, asymmetric uncertainties, and the underestimation of future warming
    • This result is explained in
    • This result is explained in Margaret S. Torn & John Harte, Missing Feedbacks, Asymmetric Uncertainties, and the Underestimation of Future Warming, 33 GEOPHYSICAL RES. LETTERS L10703 (2006).
    • (2006) Geophysical Res. Letters , vol.33
    • Torn, M.S.1    Harte, J.2
  • 118
    • 79956112574 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To see why the magnitude of our best estimate of f matters, consider the results of using a best estimate of 3/4 rather than 1/2 for f. Then if the range of uncertainty for f is 5/8 to 7/8, the range of uncertainty in outcomes is 8/3 to 8/1, or 2.66 to 8.0. The uncertainty range in f of 1/4 turns into an uncertainty range in outcomes of 5.33. Note that using the same uncertainty in f but with a best estimate of 1/2, as in the text, leads to an uncertainty in outcome of 0.86. So merely by shifting the best estimate of f while leaving the uncertainty of the estimate of f unchanged, we have amplified the increase in the uncertainty of the outcome by a factor of six
    • To see why the magnitude of our best estimate of f matters, consider the results of using a best estimate of 3/4 rather than 1/2 for f. Then if the range of uncertainty for f is 5/8 to 7/8, the range of uncertainty in outcomes is 8/3 to 8/1, or 2.66 to 8.0. The uncertainty range in f of 1/4 turns into an uncertainty range in outcomes of 5.33. Note that using the same uncertainty in f but with a best estimate of 1/2, as in the text, leads to an uncertainty in outcome of 0.86. So merely by shifting the best estimate of f while leaving the uncertainty of the estimate of f unchanged, we have amplified the increase in the uncertainty of the outcome by a factor of six.
  • 119
    • 35548966746 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Why is climate sensitivity so unpredictable?
    • (discussing the difficulties in assessing climate sensitivity accurately)
    • See Gerard H. Roe & Marcia B. Baker, Why Is Climate Sensitivity So Unpredictable?, 318 SCIENCE 629 (2007) (discussing the difficulties in assessing climate sensitivity accurately).
    • (2007) Science , vol.318 , pp. 629
    • Roe, G.H.1    Baker, M.B.2
  • 120
    • 79956147002 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra text accompanying notes 98-101
    • See infra text accompanying notes 98-101.
  • 121
    • 79956109597 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Normal distribution
    • This can be seen from the graphs in, (last visited Nov. 6), which reviews the mathematics of the normal distribution
    • This can be seen from the graphs in Eric W. Weisstein, Normal Distribution, WOLFRAM MATHWORLD, http://mathworld.wolfram.com/ NormalDistribution.html (last visited Nov. 6, 2010), which reviews the mathematics of the normal distribution.
    • (2010) Wolfram Mathworld
    • Weisstein, E.W.1
  • 122
    • 79956085237 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fat tail
    • The term fat tails has recently come into vogue. According to one language expert: "If you want to make an impression at a board meeting or a Congressional hearing these bearish days, make a harrumphing noise and employ the figure of speech now sweeping the economic world: 'But what about the fat tail?'" Feb. 8
    • The term fat tails has recently come into vogue. According to one language expert: "If you want to make an impression at a board meeting or a Congressional hearing these bearish days, make a harrumphing noise and employ the figure of speech now sweeping the economic world: 'But what about the fat tail?'"William Safire, Fat Tail, N.Y. TIMES MAG., Feb. 8, 2009, at 24.
    • (2009) N.Y. Times Mag. , pp. 24
    • Safire, W.1
  • 124
    • 79960601554 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A brief history of generative models for power law and lognormal distributions
    • For a discussion of processes that generate power laws
    • For a discussion of processes that generate power laws, see Michael Mitzenmacher, A Brief History of Generative Models for Power Law and Lognormal Distributions, 1 INTERNET MATHEMATICS 226 (2004)
    • (2004) Internet Mathematics , vol.1 , pp. 226
    • Mitzenmacher, M.1
  • 125
    • 24744469980 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Power laws, pareto distributions and Zipf's law
    • M.E.J. Newman, Power Laws, Pareto Distributions and Zipf's Law, 46 CONTEMP. PHYSICS 323 (2005).
    • (2005) Contemp. Physics , vol.46 , pp. 323
    • Newman, M.E.J.1
  • 126
    • 79956093312 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cauchy distribution
    • Two other commonly encountered fat-tailed distributions are the Cauchy distribution and the Levy distribution. These distributions behave like power-law distributions in their tails but have different properties for smaller values. The Cauchy distribution, also called the Lorentz distribution, is a continuous distribution describing resonance behavior. (last visited Nov. 6). It is symmetric and bell shaped, just like the normal distribution. It is a classical example of a distribution that has no mean (and consequently no variance)
    • Two other commonly encountered fat-tailed distributions are the Cauchy distribution and the Levy distribution. These distributions behave like power-law distributions in their tails but have different properties for smaller values. The Cauchy distribution, also called the Lorentz distribution, is a continuous distribution describing resonance behavior. See generally Eric W. Weisstein, Cauchy Distribution, WOLFRAM MATHWORLD, http://mathworld.wolfram.com/ CauchyDistribution.html (last visited Nov. 6, 2010). It is symmetric and bell shaped, just like the normal distribution. It is a classical example of a distribution that has no mean (and consequently no variance). As a consequence, the "Law of Large Numbers"-which holds that if a trial is reproduced a large number of times n, then it becomes exceedingly improbable that the average of the outcomes of these n trials will differ significantly from the expected value of one outcome as n grows without limit-does not apply. The Cauchy distribution can be shown to have the distribution of sample means regardless of the sample size. This distribution is just the original Cauchy distribution (sample size one). So the distribution of the sample mean does not "shrink down" as the sample size increases.
    • (2010) Wolfram Mathworld
    • Weisstein, E.W.1
  • 128
    • 43449121690 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It can be difficult to distinguish power laws from other fat-tailed distributions empirically, (Feb. 2) (unpublished manuscript)
    • It can be difficult to distinguish power laws from other fat-tailed distributions empirically. See Aaron Clauset, Cosma Rohilla Shalizi & M.E.J. Newman, Power-Law Distributions in Empirical Data (Feb. 2, 2009) (unpublished manuscript), http://arxiv.org/pdf/0706.1062.
    • (2009) Power-Law Distributions in Empirical Data
    • Clauset, A.1    Shalizi, C.R.2    Newman, M.E.J.3
  • 131
    • 79956078376 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 97
    • See SOLE & GOODWIN, supra note 97, at 200-01.
    • Sole1    Goodwin2
  • 132
    • 34548633128 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Positive feedbacks promote power-law clustering of kalahari vegetation
    • 209
    • Todd M. Scanlon et al., Positive Feedbacks Promote Power-Law Clustering of Kalahari Vegetation, 449 NATURE 209, 209 (2007).
    • (2007) Nature , vol.449 , pp. 209
    • Scanlon, T.M.1
  • 133
    • 79956095062 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 97
    • See SOLE & GOODWIN, supra note 97, at 205.
    • Sole1    Goodwin2
  • 134
    • 79956112053 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For further discussion of possible power laws in ecology, supra note 98, (discussing whether power laws apply to "catastrophes hitting ecological systems, or extinctions striking taxonomic groups," and stating that this question "represents one of the most intriguing and tantalizing open research problems.")
    • For further discussion of possible power laws in ecology, see LEVIN, supra note 98, at 55 (discussing whether power laws apply to "catastrophes hitting ecological systems, or extinctions striking taxonomic groups," and stating that this question "represents one of the most intriguing and tantalizing open research problems.").
    • Levin1
  • 135
    • 79956139331 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a compilation of examples of power laws in many different contexts, supra note 95
    • For a compilation of examples of power laws in many different contexts, see Newman, supra note 95, at 327-30.
    • Newman1
  • 139
    • 79956061830 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This example is given in, supra note 95
    • This example is given in SCHROEDER, supra note 95, at 157.
    • Schroeder1
  • 140
    • 0037677943 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Appendix: A primer on heavy-tailed distributions
    • For a more technical discussion of this phenomenon
    • For a more technical discussion of this phenomenon, see Karl Sigman, Appendix: A Primer on Heavy-Tailed Distributions, 33 QUEUEING SYSS. 261 (1999).
    • (1999) Queueing Syss. , vol.33 , pp. 261
    • Sigman, K.1
  • 143
    • 79961121953 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Are catastrophes insurable?
    • -2. Because of their risk characteristics, fat tails can pose serious problems to insuring risks, Summer, 20
    • -2. Because of their risk characteristics, fat tails can pose serious problems to insuring risks. See Roger M. Cooke & Carolyn Kousky, Are Catastrophes Insurable?, RESOURCES, Summer 2009, at 18, 20.
    • (2009) Resources , pp. 18
    • Cooke, R.M.1    Kousky, C.2
  • 144
    • 35348993238 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A review of the stern review on the economics of climate change
    • 723, (book review)
    • Martin L. Weitzman, A Review of The Stern Review on the Economics of Climate Change, 45 J. ECON. LITERATURE 703, 723 (2007) (book review).
    • (2007) J. Econ. Literature , vol.45 , pp. 703
    • Weitzman, M.L.1
  • 145
    • 69649097412 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On modeling and interpreting the economics of catastrophic climate change
    • 3, Indeed, even determining that data exhibits a fat-tailed distribution such as a power law rather than a thinner tailed distribution such as the lognormal distribution can be difficult. See Newman, supra note 95, at 329-30. The differences can be quite subtle: the same basic model can lead to a power law or a lognormal distribution, depending on whether there is a boundary at an extreme (for example, a requirement that outcomes cannot go below zero)
    • Martin L. Weitzman, On Modeling and Interpreting the Economics of Catastrophic Climate Change, 91 REV. ECON. & STAT. 1, 3 n.4 (2009). Indeed, even determining that data exhibits a fat-tailed distribution such as a power law rather than a thinner tailed distribution such as the lognormal distribution can be difficult. See Newman, supra note 95, at 329-30. The differences can be quite subtle: the same basic model can lead to a power law or a lognormal distribution, depending on whether there is a boundary at an extreme (for example, a requirement that outcomes cannot go below zero).
    • (2009) Rev. Econ. & Stat. , vol.91 , Issue.4 , pp. 1
    • Weitzman, M.L.1
  • 146
    • 79956130131 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 95
    • See Mitzenmacher, supra note 95, at 238.
    • Mitzenmacher1
  • 147
    • 0025125921 scopus 로고
    • A simple formula for calculating the "mass density" of a lognormally distributed characteristic: Applications to risk analysis
    • For a discussion of the use of lognormal distributions
    • For a discussion of the use of lognormal distributions, see Adam M. Finkel, A Simple Formula for Calculating the "Mass Density" of a Lognormally Distributed Characteristic: Applications to Risk Analysis, 10 RISK ANALYSIS 291 (1990).
    • (1990) Risk Analysis , vol.10 , pp. 291
    • Finkel, A.M.1
  • 148
    • 79956095579 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 111, The distribution that he derives is not a power law but another fat-tailed distribution known for historical reasons as the "Student-t." Id. at 8. This distribution looks like a bell curve "except that the probabilities are somewhat more stretched out, making the tails appear relatively fatter at the expense of a slightly flatter center." Id.
    • Weitzman, supra note 111, at 9. The distribution that he derives is not a power law but another fat-tailed distribution known for historical reasons as the "Student-t." Id. at 8. This distribution looks like a bell curve "except that the probabilities are somewhat more stretched out, making the tails appear relatively fatter at the expense of a slightly flatter center." Id.
    • Weitzman1
  • 149
    • 63149096680 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Economics of climate change under uncertainty: Benefits of flexibility
    • One emerging possibility is the use of "real options" analysis, which has only recently been applied to fat-tailed situations such as climate change, 1354, (concluding that benefits of early mitigation are increased by uncertainties that could be resolved later)
    • One emerging possibility is the use of "real options" analysis, which has only recently been applied to fat-tailed situations such as climate change. See Jon Anda, Alexander Golub & Elena Strukova, Economics of Climate Change Under Uncertainty: Benefits of Flexibility, 37 ENERGY POL'Y 1345, 1354 (2009) (concluding that benefits of early mitigation are increased by uncertainties that could be resolved later).
    • (2009) Energy Pol'y , vol.37 , pp. 1345
    • Anda, J.1    Golub, A.2    Strukova, E.3
  • 150
    • 58149361827 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Maximum entropy and the state-variable approach to macroecology
    • Under some circumstances, we have the advantage of having some information about a distribution, and the question then is how to best select the type of distribution. A technique called "maximum entropy" (MaxEnt) can be helpful in making this choice. MaxEnt selects the distribution that, in a sense derived from information theory, avoids the use of any additional assumptions about the shape of the distribution apart from the given information. In other words, MaxEnt selects the distribution that is as "smooth and flat as possible" to be the least biased inference about the distribution. 2701
    • Under some circumstances, we have the advantage of having some information about a distribution, and the question then is how to best select the type of distribution. A technique called "maximum entropy" (MaxEnt) can be helpful in making this choice. MaxEnt selects the distribution
    • (2008) Ecology , vol.89 , pp. 2700
    • Harte, J.1    Zillio, T.2    Conlisk, E.3    Smith, A.B.4
  • 151
    • 79956154466 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 111
    • Weitzman, supra note 111, at 1.
    • Weitzman1
  • 152
    • 33750025899 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ambiguity aversion and the criminal process
    • For other legal applications of ambiguity models, (identifying and analyzing higher ambiguity aversion of defendants as opposed to prosecutors results in unbalanced plea negotiations)
    • For other legal applications of ambiguity models, see Uzi Segal & Alex Stein, Ambiguity Aversion and the Criminal Process, 81 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 1495 (2006) (identifying and analyzing higher ambiguity aversion of defendants as opposed to prosecutors results in unbalanced plea negotiations)
    • (2006) Notre Dame L. Rev. , vol.81 , pp. 1495
    • Segal, U.1    Stein, A.2
  • 153
    • 78149485859 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On uncertainty, ambiguity, and contractual conditions
    • (concluding that ambiguity explains why the possibility of adverse events sometimes results in the use of a conditions clause in a contract rather than a price adjustment)
    • Eric Talley, On Uncertainty, Ambiguity, and Contractual Conditions, 34 DEL. J. CORP. L. 755 (2009) (concluding that ambiguity explains why the possibility of adverse events sometimes results in the use of a conditions clause in a contract rather than a price adjustment)
    • (2009) Del. J. Corp. L. , vol.34 , pp. 755
    • Talley, E.1
  • 154
    • 36749082392 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A unilateral accident model under ambiguity
    • (arguing that negligence rules may be superior to strict liability under conditions of ambiguity)
    • Joshua C. Teitelbaum, A Unilateral Accident Model Under Ambiguity, 36 J. LEGAL STUD. 431 (2007) (arguing that negligence rules may be superior to strict liability under conditions of ambiguity).
    • (2007) J. Legal Stud. , vol.36 , pp. 431
    • Teitelbaum, J.C.1
  • 155
    • 0009883679 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the robustness and possible accounts ofambiguity aversion
    • 149, ("Ambiguity aversion is one of the most robust phenomena documented in the decision making literature . . . .") The researchers found in one experiment that "ambiguity avoidance is so pervasive that it extends even to situations in which the likelihood of winning in the ambiguity condition is higher than in the risky conditions."
    • See Gideon Keren & Leónie E.M. Gerritsen, On the Robustness and Possible Accounts ofAmbiguity Aversion, 103 ACTA PSYCHOLOGICA 149, 149 (1999) ("Ambiguity aversion is one of the most robust phenomena documented in the decision making literature . . . .") The researchers found in one experiment that "ambiguity avoidance is so pervasive that it extends even to situations in which the likelihood of winning in the ambiguity condition is higher than in the risky conditions."
    • (1999) Acta Psychologica , vol.103 , pp. 149
    • Keren, G.1    Gerritsen, L.E.M.2
  • 157
    • 79956147001 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 0 p · 1dp = 1/2 (because one is the probability of a red ball if the urn is red and p is the probability it is red)
    • 0 p · 1dp = 1/2 (because one is the probability of a red ball if the urn is red and p is the probability it is red). This is exactly the same as the probability from the half-red, half-blue urn, so there is no reason to favor one over the other. Another way of seeing this more directly is to assume that we have a choice between the following gambles: (1) Betting that the next ball drawn from a half-red, half-blue urn will be red. (2) Betting on a red ball being produced by the following scenario. First, we flip a coin. Second, if the coin comes out heads, we draw a red ball from an all-red urn; if tails, from an all-blue urn. These are just two different mechanisms for producing a fifty-percent probability of red, so with or without risk aversion, a person should be indifferent between them. Thus, risk aversion cannot account for the common preference for the first gamble over the second gamble.
  • 158
    • 0042350815 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A survey of behavioral finance
    • (George M. Constantinides, Milton Harris & René M. Stulz eds.)
    • Nicholas Barberis & Richard Thaler, A Survey of Behavioral Finance, in HANDBOOK OF THE ECONOMICS OF FINANCE 1053, 1074-75 (George M. Constantinides, Milton Harris & René M. Stulz eds., 2003).
    • (2003) Handbook of the Economics of Finance , vol.1053 , pp. 1074-1075
    • Barberis, N.1    Thaler, R.2
  • 161
    • 0013539607 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hard uncertainty and environmental policy
    • A good summary can be found in, (Graciela Chichilnsky et al. eds.)
    • A good summary can be found in Alessandro Vercelli, Hard Uncertainty and Environmental Policy, in SUSTAINABILITY: DYNAMICS AND UNCERTAINTY 191, 196-205 (Graciela Chichilnsky et al. eds., 1998).
    • (1998) Sustainability: Dynamics and Uncertainty , vol.191 , pp. 196-205
    • Vercelli, A.1
  • 162
    • 33644553294 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A smooth model of decision making under ambiguity
    • 1849
    • Peter Kilbanoff, Massimo Marinacci & Sujoy Mukerji, A Smooth Model of Decision Making Under Ambiguity, 73 ECONOMETRICA 1849, 1849 (2005).
    • (2005) Econometrica , vol.73 , pp. 1849
    • Kilbanoff, P.1    Marinacci, M.2    Mukerji, S.3
  • 164
    • 64049107866 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Recursive smooth ambiguity preferences
    • The model has been extended to dynamic-choice situations in which the decision maker receives additional information over time
    • The model has been extended to dynamic-choice situations in which the decision maker receives additional information over time. See Peter Klibanoff, Massimo Marinacci & Sujoy Mukerji, Recursive Smooth Ambiguity Preferences, 144 J. ECON. THEORY 930 (2009).
    • (2009) J. Econ. Theory , vol.144 , pp. 930
    • Klibanoff, P.1    Marinacci, M.2    Mukerji, S.3
  • 165
    • 79956124962 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1
    • STERN, supra note 1.
    • Stern1
  • 166
    • 4444277242 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Differentiating ambiguity and ambiguity attitude
    • For discussion of the so-called α-maxmin model in the context of a more general theory, 153-55, (the crucial result is proposition 19(ii)). α-maxmin can be derived from the assumption that decision makers are indifferent between acts which result in the same range of expected utilities over a set of scenarios
    • For discussion of the so-called α-maxmin model in the context of a more general theory, see Paolo Ghirardato, Fabio Maccheroni & Massimo Marinacci, Differentiating Ambiguity and Ambiguity Attitude, 118 J. ECON. THEORY 133, 153-55 (2004) (the crucial result is proposition 19(ii)). α-maxmin can be derived from the assumption that decision makers are indifferent between acts which result in the same range of expected utilities over a set of scenarios.
    • (2004) J. Econ. Theory , vol.118 , pp. 133
    • Ghirardato, P.1    Maccheroni, F.2    Marinacci, M.3
  • 167
    • 5444252095 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Cal. Inst. of Tech., Social Science Working Paper No. 1130), available at, If decision makers care only about the utility associated with outcomes, the assumption seems plausible if we assume that the decision maker has no ability or willingness to evaluate the likelihood of different scenarios, so outcomes across scenarios only reflect the range of possibilities
    • See Paolo Ghirardato, Fabio Maccheroni & Massimo Marinacci, Ambiguity from the Differential Viewpoint 6 (Cal. Inst. of Tech., Social Science Working Paper No. 1130, 2002), available at http://www.hss.caltech.edu/SSPapers/wp1130. pdf. If decision makers care only about the utility associated with outcomes, the assumption seems plausible if we assume that the decision maker has no ability or willingness to evaluate the likelihood of different scenarios, so outcomes across scenarios only reflect the range of possibilities.
    • (2002) Ambiguity from the Differential Viewpoint , pp. 6
    • Ghirardato, P.1    Maccheroni, F.2    Marinacci, M.3
  • 168
    • 79956083098 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1
    • STERN, supra note 1.
    • Stern1
  • 169
    • 79956158152 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A key point in applying these models is identifying the best and worst case scenarios. Use of the models might encourage interest groups to put forward exaggerated scenarios (although this is probably already an incentive for other reasons).
    • A key point in applying these models is identifying the best and worst case scenarios. Use of the models might encourage interest groups to put forward exaggerated scenarios (although this is probably already an incentive for other reasons).
  • 170
    • 79956096072 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some economists and finance theorists postulate that risk measures should focus solely on adverse outcomes, a concept known as downside risk. (Cal. Climate Change Ctr., Draft Report No. CEC-500-2008-XXX) (describing theories of downside risk), available at http://calclimate.berkeley.edu/publication/ agriculture. The magnitude of α can be considered a measure, in the uncertainty context, of the weight placed on downside outcomes. A low α indicates an aversion to downside uncertainty
    • Some economists and finance theorists postulate that risk measures should focus solely on adverse outcomes, a concept known as downside risk. See Michael Hanemann et al., Climate Change Impacts to Urban and Agricultural Sectors in California 36-41 (Cal. Climate Change Ctr., Draft Report No. CEC-500-2008-XXX, 2008) (describing theories of downside risk), available at http://calclimate. berkeley.edu/publication/agriculture. The magnitude of α can be considered a measure, in the uncertainty context, of the weight placed on downside outcomes. A low α indicates an aversion to downside uncertainty.
    • (2008) Climate Change Impacts to Urban and Agricultural Sectors in California , pp. 36-41
    • Hanemann, M.1
  • 171
    • 0001266334 scopus 로고
    • Maxmin expected utility with non-unique prior
    • If α=1, then α-maxmin becomes ordinary maxmin, in which only the worst case matters. For an axiomatic treatment of maxmin, The α parameter could be considered a measure of what Keynes called "animal spirits."
    • If α=1, then α-maxmin becomes ordinary maxmin, in which only the worst case matters. For an axiomatic treatment of maxmin, see Itzhak Gilboa & David Schmeidler, Maxmin Expected Utility With Non-Unique Prior, 18 J. MATHEMATICAL ECON. 141 (1989). The α parameter could be considered a measure of what Keynes called "animal spirits."
    • (1989) J. Mathematical Econ. , vol.18 , pp. 141
    • Gilboa, I.1    Schmeidler, D.2
  • 172
    • 79956074700 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 5, These models are somewhat akin to Dempster-Shafter models of decision making, which use a weighted average of high and low extremes, although the weighting factor (ρ) represents a relative probability rather than ambiguity aversion
    • See CLARKE, supra note 5, at 156. These models are somewhat akin to Dempster-Shafter models of decision making, which use a weighted average of high and low extremes, although the weighting factor (ρ) represents a relative probability rather than ambiguity aversion.
    • Clarke1
  • 173
    • 0043021179 scopus 로고
    • Decision analysis using belief functions
    • 285, 306 (Ronald R. Yager, Janusz Kacprzyk & Mario Fedrizzi eds.)
    • See Thomas M. Strat, Decision Analysis Using Belief Functions, in ADVANCES IN THE DEMPSTER-SHAFER THEORY OF EVIDENCE 275, 285, 306 (Ronald R. Yager, Janusz Kacprzyk & Mario Fedrizzi eds., 1994).
    • (1994) Advances in the Dempster-Shafer Theory of Evidence , pp. 275
    • Strat, T.M.1
  • 174
    • 50849084436 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Precautionary principle as a rule of choice with optimism on windfall gains and pessimism on catastrophic losses
    • 486
    • See Marcello Basili, Alain Chateauneuf & Fulvio Fontini, Precautionary Principle as a Rule of Choice with Optimism on Windfall Gains and Pessimism on Catastrophic Losses, 67 ECOLOGICAL ECON. 485, 486 (2008).
    • (2008) Ecological Econ. , vol.67 , pp. 485
    • Basili, M.1    Chateauneuf, A.2    Fontini, F.3
  • 177
    • 79956145884 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We might be able to narrow the range for α by using empirical evidence showing how individuals approach decision making in situations characterized by ambiguity or through experience over time that might allow officials to develop norms about the appropriate α.
    • We might be able to narrow the range for α by using empirical evidence showing how individuals approach decision making in situations characterized by ambiguity or through experience over time that might allow officials to develop norms about the appropriate α.
  • 180
    • 10044297459 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is a more formalized version of the familiar technique of scenario analysis. For a description of scenario analysis
    • This is a more formalized version of the familiar technique of scenario analysis. For a description of scenario analysis, see JAMES A. DEWAR, ASSUMPTION-BASED PLANNING: A TOOL FOR REDUCING AVOIDABLE SURPRISES 130-42 (2002).
    • (2002) Assumption-Based Planning: A Tool for Reducing Avoidable Surprises , pp. 130-142
    • Dewar, J.A.1
  • 181
    • 79956123907 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 135
    • See GROVES, supra note 135, at 123-48.
    • Groves1
  • 182
    • 79956090764 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id., (describing the RDM robustness criterion)
    • See id. at 132-33 (describing the RDM robustness criterion).
    • Groves1
  • 183
    • 79956093311 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id., (describing how the method achieves "robust" policies that are "relatively insensitive to the key uncertainties and different preferences held by decision makers")
    • Id. at 124-25 (describing how the method achieves "robust" policies that are "relatively insensitive to the key uncertainties and different preferences held by decision makers")
    • Groves1
  • 184
    • 33846838684 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A new analytic method for finding policy-relevant scenarios
    • 75, (stating that "[t]he central idea is to use multiple runs of computer simulation models to identify those scenarios most important to the choices facing decision makers," based on the foundation of RDM)
    • see also David G. Groves & Robert J. Lempert, A New Analytic Method for Finding Policy-Relevant Scenarios, 17 GLOBAL ENVTL. CHANGE 73, 75 (2007) (stating that "[t]he central idea is to use multiple runs of computer simulation models to identify those scenarios most important to the choices facing decision makers," based on the foundation of RDM).
    • (2007) Global Envtl. Change , vol.17 , pp. 73
    • Groves, D.G.1    Lempert, R.J.2
  • 185
    • 79956095061 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 135
    • GROVES, supra note 135, at 125.
    • Groves1
  • 187
    • 56849132654 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Res. for the Future, Discussion Paper No. 04-03), available at, Margolis and Nævdal show that "SMS is optimal policy if managers can put lower bounds on two parameters: the seriousness of the catastrophe and a parameter that determines how the magnitude of risk varies with the state-variable's position in state space."
    • See Michael Margolis & Eric Nævdal, Safe Minimum Standards in Dynamic Resource Problems-Conditions for Living on the Edge of Risk (Res. for the Future, Discussion Paper No. 04-03, 2004), available at www.rff.org/RFF/ Documents/RFF-DP-04-03.pdf. Margolis and Nævdal show that "SMS is optimal policy if managers can put lower bounds on two parameters: the seriousness of the catastrophe and a parameter that determines how the magnitude of risk varies with the state-variable's position in state space."
    • (2004) Safe Minimum Standards in Dynamic Resource Problems-Conditions for Living on the Edge of Risk
    • Margolis, M.1    Nævdal, E.2
  • 189
    • 0032464491 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The rationality of a safe minimum standard
    • For further discussion and critique of SMS, 288, (arguing in favor of a harder version of SMS where a consensus exists that a resource is a human necessity)
    • For further discussion and critique of SMS, see Michael C. Farmer & Alan Randall, The Rationality of a Safe Minimum Standard, 74 LAND ECON. 287, 288 (1998) (arguing in favor of a harder version of SMS where a consensus exists that a resource is a human necessity)
    • (1998) Land Econ. , vol.74 , pp. 287
    • Farmer, M.C.1    Randall, A.2
  • 190
    • 0004038912 scopus 로고
    • Ulysses revisited-A closer look at the safe minimum standard rule
    • 66-68, (arguing for a softer version in which SMS is understood as merely a switching rule triggering more intensive scrutiny of costs and benefits)
    • J.C. Rolfe, Ulysses Revisited-A Closer Look at the Safe Minimum Standard Rule, 39 AUSTL. J. AGRIC. ECON. 55, 66-68 (1995) (arguing for a softer version in which SMS is understood as merely a switching rule triggering more intensive scrutiny of costs and benefits).
    • (1995) Austl. J. Agric. Econ. , vol.39 , pp. 55
    • Rolfe, J.C.1
  • 191
    • 45749117727 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Economically optimal risk reduction strategies in the face of uncertain climate thresholds
    • 30, available at
    • See David McInerney & Klaus Keller, Economically Optimal Risk Reduction Strategies in the Face of Uncertain Climate Thresholds, 91 CLIMATIC CHANGE 29, 30 (2007), available at http:// www.springerlink.com/content/ p238w50423462307/.
    • (2007) Climatic Change , vol.91 , pp. 29
    • McInerney, D.1    Keller, K.2
  • 192
    • 84927110876 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What is the economic value of information about climate thresholds?
    • fig. 28.5 (Michael E. Schlesinger et al. eds.)
    • Klaus Keller et al., What Is the Economic Value of Information About Climate Thresholds?, in HUMAN-INDUCED CLIMATE CHANGE: AN INTERDISCIPLINARY ASSESSMENT 343, 349 fig. 28.5 (Michael E. Schlesinger et al. eds., 2007).
    • (2007) Human-Induced Climate Change: An Interdisciplinary Assessment , vol.343 , pp. 349
    • Keller, K.1
  • 194
    • 77956120368 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scenario-building for the deepwater horizon oil spill
    • For a recent example of the use of scenario analysis to deal with a situation of high uncertainty
    • For a recent example of the use of scenario analysis to deal with a situation of high uncertainty, see Gary E. Machlis & Marcia K. McNutt, Scenario-Building for the Deepwater Horizon Oil Spill, 329 SCIENCE 1018 (2010).
    • (2010) Science , vol.329 , pp. 1018
    • Machlis, G.E.1    McNutt, M.K.2
  • 195
    • 79956111499 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 146
    • VERCHICK, supra note 146, at 242-43.
    • Verchick1
  • 197
    • 79956112052 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra text accompanying notes 92-109
    • See supra text accompanying notes 92-109.
  • 198
    • 79956078928 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1. Feedback effects, such as methane releases triggered by temperature increases, threaten to accelerate temperature changes
    • Cole, supra note 1, at 75. Feedback effects, such as methane releases triggered by temperature increases, threaten to accelerate temperature changes.
    • Cole1
  • 199
    • 73349100005 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Methane: A menace surfaces
    • Dec.
    • See Katey Walter Anthony, Methane: A Menace Surfaces, SCI. AM., Dec. 2009, at 68.
    • (2009) Sci. Am. , pp. 68
    • Anthony, K.W.1
  • 200
    • 79956077815 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1
    • STERN, supra note 1, at 10-11.
    • Stern1
  • 201
    • 79956100104 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id. at 11.
    • Stern1
  • 202
    • 79956086564 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id. at xvi.
    • Stern1
  • 204
    • 75749085855 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2 is disputed, but the most recent study of the historical record suggests that this feedback loop is not terribly strong. See David C. Frank et al., Ensemble Reconstruction Constraints on the Global Carbon Cycle Sensitivity to Climate, 463 NATURE 527 (2010). The authors caution, however, that this estimate is based on preindustrial conditions that may not apply today
    • 2 is disputed, but the most recent study of the historical record suggests that this feedback loop is not terribly strong. See David C. Frank et al., Ensemble Reconstruction Constraints on the Global Carbon Cycle Sensitivity to Climate, 463 NATURE 527 (2010). The authors caution, however, that this estimate is based on preindustrial conditions that may not apply today.
  • 206
    • 79956159899 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 154
    • Meehl et al., supra note 154, at 799.
    • Meehl1
  • 208
    • 79956120458 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. ("Most studies do not account for structural uncertainty, and thus probably tend to underestimate the uncertainty. On the other hand, since several largely independent lines of evidence indicate similar most likely values and ranges, climate sensitivity values are likely to be better constrained than those found by methods based on single data sets.")
    • See id. ("Most studies do not account for structural uncertainty, and thus probably tend to underestimate the uncertainty. On the other hand, since several largely independent lines of evidence indicate similar most likely values and ranges, climate sensitivity values are likely to be better constrained than those found by methods based on single data sets.").
    • Meehl1
  • 209
    • 79956155021 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As one climate scientist explains, "While ensemble projections carried out to date give a wide range of responses, they do not sample all possible sources of modelling uncertainty . . . . More generally, the set of available models may share fundamental inadequacies, the effects of which cannot be quantified." Id.
    • As one climate scientist explains, "While ensemble projections carried out to date give a wide range of responses, they do not sample all possible sources of modelling uncertainty . . . . More generally, the set of available models may share fundamental inadequacies, the effects of which cannot be quantified." Id. at 805.
    • Meehl1
  • 210
    • 34548100860 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scientific challenges in the attribution of harm to human influence on climate
    • 1361
    • Myles Allen et al., Scientific Challenges in the Attribution of Harm to Human Influence on Climate, 155 U. PA. L. REV. 1353, 1361 (2007).
    • (2007) U. Pa. L. Rev. , vol.155 , pp. 1353
    • Allen, M.1
  • 211
    • 34548100860 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scientific challenges in the attribution of harm to human influence on climate
    • Id. "There is considerable debate over the extent to which currently available models span the range of plausible real-world responses."
    • Id. "There is considerable debate over the extent to which currently available models span the range of plausible real-world responses."
    • (2007) U. Pa. L. Rev. , vol.155
    • Allen, M.1
  • 212
    • 34548100860 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scientific challenges in the attribution of harm to human influence on climate
    • Id.
    • Id.
    • (2007) U. Pa. L. Rev. , vol.155
    • Allen, M.1
  • 213
    • 34548100860 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scientific challenges in the attribution of harm to human influence on climate
    • See id.
    • See id. at 1375.
    • (2007) U. Pa. L. Rev. , vol.155 , pp. 1375
    • Allen, M.1
  • 214
    • 79956115661 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 154, As the IPCC's review of the literature explains: Uncertainty in predictions of anthropogenic climate change arises at all stages of the modelling process . . . . The specification of future emissions of greenhouse gases, aerosols and their precursors is uncertain. It is then necessary to convert these emissions into concentrations of [greenhouse gases], calculate the associated forcing [the direct temperature effect] and predict the response of climate system variables such as surface temperature and precipitation. At each step, uncertainty in the true signal of climate change is introduced both by errors in the representation of Earth system processes in models and by internal climate variability
    • See Meehl et al., supra note 154, at 797. As the IPCC's review of the literature explains: Uncertainty in predictions of anthropogenic climate change arises at all stages of the modelling process . . . . The specification of future emissions of greenhouse gases, aerosols and their precursors is uncertain. It is then necessary to convert these emissions into concentrations of [greenhouse gases], calculate the associated forcing [the direct temperature effect] and predict the response of climate system variables such as surface temperature and precipitation. At each step, uncertainty in the true signal of climate change is introduced both by errors in the representation of Earth system processes in models and by internal climate variability.
    • Meehl1
  • 215
    • 79956113538 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. (citations omitted)
    • Id. (citations omitted).
    • Meehl1
  • 216
    • 79956116677 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id. at 754.
    • Meehl1
  • 218
    • 79956153923 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id.
    • See id.
    • Meehl1
  • 219
    • 29144535307 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Seductive simulations? Uncertainty distribution around climate models
    • 904-08
    • See Myanna Lahsen, Seductive Simulations? Uncertainty Distribution Around Climate Models, 35 SOC. STUD. SCI. 895, 904-08 (2005).
    • (2005) Soc. Stud. Sci. , vol.35 , pp. 895
    • Lahsen, M.1
  • 220
    • 79956070123 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an excellent general treatment of uncertainty in policy analysis, supra note 25. Morgan and Henrion note that in settings "such as nuclear safety analysis"-and one might add climate change here-"where the tails of the distributions are of particular interest," reliance on the mean and variance as a basis for evaluating uncertainty can entail "a serious deficiency."
    • For an excellent general treatment of uncertainty in policy analysis, see MORGAN & HENRION, supra note 25. Morgan and Henrion note that in settings "such as nuclear safety analysis"-and one might add climate change here-"where the tails of the distributions are of particular interest," reliance on the mean and variance as a basis for evaluating uncertainty can entail "a serious deficiency."
    • Morgan1    Henrion2
  • 221
    • 79956125913 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. They prefer Monte Carlo sampling methods
    • Id. at 213. They prefer Monte Carlo sampling methods.
    • Morgan1    Henrion2
  • 224
    • 35448996553 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The economic impacts of climate change: Evidence from agricultural output and random fluctuations in weather
    • 377, 381, (finding that the most likely result of climate change on American agricultural profits is an annual increase in profits of roughly 4%, but with California losing 15%). Note, however, that this study excludes possible impacts of increases in extreme events such as storms and droughts
    • See Olivier Deschênes & Michael Greenstone, The Economic Impacts of Climate Change: Evidence from Agricultural Output and Random Fluctuations in Weather, 97 AM. ECON. REV. 354, 377, 381 (2007) (finding that the most likely result of climate change on American agricultural profits is an annual increase in profits of roughly 4%, but with California losing 15%). Note, however, that this study excludes possible impacts of increases in extreme events such as storms and droughts.
    • (2007) Am. Econ. Rev. , vol.97 , pp. 354
    • Deschênes, O.1    Greenstone, M.2
  • 225
    • 35448996553 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The economic impacts of climate change: Evidence from agricultural output and random fluctuations in weather
    • See id. Extreme local events are a significant factor even in the absence of extreme global temperature changes.
    • See id. at 380. Extreme local events are a significant factor even in the absence of extreme global temperature changes.
    • (2007) Am. Econ. Rev. , vol.97 , pp. 380
    • Deschênes, O.1    Greenstone, M.2
  • 226
    • 75749147020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Models foresee more-intense hurricanes in the greenhouse
    • For instance, the latest models show indications of more intense hurricanes in the remainder of this century.
    • For instance, the latest models show indications of more intense hurricanes in the remainder of this century. See Richard A. Kerr, Models Foresee More-Intense Hurricanes in the Greenhouse, 327 SCIENCE 399 (2010).
    • (2010) Science , vol.327 , pp. 399
    • Kerr, R.A.1
  • 227
    • 32544453816 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The impact of global warming on U.S. agriculture: An econometric analysis of optimal growing conditions
    • 122-24, (estimating the potential impact on farmland values east of the 100th meridian for a range of warming scenarios and concluding that aggregate losses could be quite severe-with an average impact of up to approximately seventy percent at the end of the century-if fossil fuel use increases)
    • See Wolfram Schlenker, W. Michael Hanemann & Anthony C. Fisher, The Impact of Global Warming on U.S. Agriculture: An Econometric Analysis of Optimal Growing Conditions, 88 REV. ECON. & STAT. 113, 122-24 (2006) (estimating the potential impact on farmland values east of the 100th meridian for a range of warming scenarios and concluding that aggregate losses could be quite severe-with an average impact of up to approximately seventy percent at the end of the century-if fossil fuel use increases).
    • (2006) Rev. Econ. & Stat. , vol.88 , pp. 113
    • Schlenker, W.1    Hanemann, W.M.2    Fisher, A.C.3
  • 228
    • 0002644105 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Estimating the Costs of Mitigating Greenhouse Gases
    • For a good overview of modeling issues, (James P. Bruce et al. eds.) (discussing the "critical determinants likely to influence the overall cost of climate policies and of the main methodologies employed to account for them")
    • For a good overview of modeling issues, see J.C. Hourcade et al., Estimating the Costs of Mitigating Greenhouse Gases, in WORKING GROUP III TO THE SECOND ASSESSMENT REPORT OF THE INTERGOVERNMENTAL PANEL ON CLIMATE CHANGE, CLIMATE CHANGE 1995: ECONOMIC AND SOCIAL DIMENSIONS OF CLIMATE CHANGE 263, 268 (James P. Bruce et al. eds., 1996) (discussing the "critical determinants likely to influence the overall cost of climate policies and of the main methodologies employed to account for them").
    • (1996) Working Group III to the Second Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change, Climate Change 1995: Economic and Social Dimensions of Climate Change , vol.263 , pp. 268
    • Hourcade, J.C.1
  • 229
    • 79956131704 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Climate: Uncertain economic models create headaches for senate panel
    • (Oct. 14)
    • Darren Samuelsonn, Climate: Uncertain Economic Models Create Headaches for Senate Panel, GREENWIRE (Oct. 14, 2009), http://www.eenews.net/Greenwire/ 2009/10/14/5.
    • (2009) Greenwire
    • Samuelsonn, D.1
  • 230
    • 79956126984 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (conditioning their model on the need for a "detailed inventory and valuation of climatically sensitive regions for validation")
    • WILLIAM D. NORDHAUS & JOSEPH BOYER, WARMING THE WORLD: ECONOMIC MODELS OF GLOBAL WARMING 86 (2003) (conditioning their model on the need for a "detailed inventory and valuation of climatically sensitive regions for validation").
    • (2003) Warming the World: Economic Models of Global Warming , vol.86
    • Nordhaus, W.D.1    Boyer, J.2
  • 231
    • 85013688697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (reviewing a study of energy price forecasts made in the 1980s by the U.S. Department of Energy and private organizations that found out of nine forecasts, all but one of the median error rates was over 100%, and four were over 200%)
    • STEPHEN J. DECANIO, ECONOMIC MODELS OF CLIMATE CHANGE: A CRITIQUE 138-39 (2003) (reviewing a study of energy price forecasts made in the 1980s by the U.S. Department of Energy and private organizations that found out of nine forecasts, all but one of the median error rates was over 100%, and four were over 200%).
    • (2003) Economic Models of Climate Change: A Critique , pp. 138-139
    • Decanio, S.J.1
  • 232
    • 0027973239 scopus 로고
    • Quantifying the credibility of energy projections from trends in past data: The U.S. energy sector
    • 119, (finding that often normal distribution fails to model the frequency of extreme outcomes accurately in energy forecasts).
    • See Alexander I. Shlyakhter et al., Quantifying the Credibility of Energy Projections from Trends in Past Data: The U.S. Energy Sector, 22 ENERGY POL'Y 119, 119 (1994) (finding that often normal distribution fails to model the frequency of extreme outcomes accurately in energy forecasts).
    • (1994) Energy Pol'y , vol.22 , pp. 119
    • Shlyakhter, A.I.1
  • 233
    • 34250208744 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Adapting to climate change: Environmental law in a warmer world
    • 81-84, (arguing that adaptation presents great institutional and political difficulties, which may prevent it from being successfully managed to minimize ecological or other impacts)
    • See Matthew D. Zinn, Adapting to Climate Change: Environmental Law in a Warmer World, 34 ECOLOGY L.Q. 61, 81-84 (2007) (arguing that adaptation presents great institutional and political difficulties, which may prevent it from being successfully managed to minimize ecological or other impacts).
    • (2007) Ecology L.Q. , vol.34 , pp. 61
    • Zinn, M.D.1
  • 235
    • 79956117175 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 111
    • Weitzman, supra note 111, at 1.
    • Weitzman1
  • 236
    • 79956104812 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. A leading critic ofWeitzman concurs that "[m]any people would agree that a 5% chance of a 10° change, or a 1% chance of a 20° change, would be a catastrophic prospect for human societies."
    • Id. A leading critic ofWeitzman concurs that "[m]any people would agree that a 5% chance of a 10° change, or a 1% chance of a 20° change, would be a catastrophic prospect for human societies."
    • Weitzman1
  • 237
    • 70349535692 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Cowles Found., Discussion Paper No. 1686), available at
    • William D. Nordhaus, An Analysis of the Dismal Theorem 10 (Cowles Found., Discussion Paper No. 1686, 2009), available at http//ssrn.com/abstracts= 1330454.
    • (2009) An Analysis of the Dismal Theorem , pp. 10
    • Nordhaus, W.D.1
  • 238
    • 79956074175 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 111
    • Weitzman, supra note 111, at 1.
    • Weitzman1
  • 239
    • 79956098490 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. The fat-tail aspect of Weitzman's analysis seems to be crucial. Using a thin-tail analysis while still taking into account possible extreme outcomes, Pindyck finds a case for moderate climate mitigation but nothing more.
    • Id. at 18. The fat-tail aspect of Weitzman's analysis seems to be crucial. Using a thin-tail analysis while still taking into account possible extreme outcomes, Pindyck finds a case for moderate climate mitigation but nothing more.
    • Weitzman1
  • 240
    • 76149122258 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (MIT Sloan Sch., Working Paper No. 4742-09) available at, Pindyck provides an important caveat: We have no historical or experimental data from which to assess the likelihood of a ΔT [change in temperature] above 5° C, never mind its economic impact, and one could argue á la Weitzman (2009) that we will never have sufficient data because the distributions are fat-tailed, implying a WTP [willingness to pay] of 100% [of consumption] (or at least something much larger than 2%)
    • See Robert S. Pindyck, Uncertain Outcomes and Climate Change Policy 22 (MIT Sloan Sch., Working Paper No. 4742-09, 2009) available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=1448683. Pindyck provides an important caveat: We have no historical or experimental data from which to assess the likelihood of a ΔT [change in temperature] above 5° C, never mind its economic impact, and one could argue á la Weitzman (2009) that we will never have sufficient data because the distributions are fat-tailed, implying a WTP [willingness to pay] of 100% [of consumption] (or at least something much larger than 2%).
    • (2009) Uncertain Outcomes and Climate Change Policy , pp. 22
    • Pindyck, R.S.1
  • 242
    • 79956095578 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is hard to quarrel, however, with Weitzman's statement that "[e]ven just acknowledging more openly the incredible magnitude of the deep structural uncertainties that are involved in climate-change analysis . . . might go a long way toward elevating the level of public discourse concerning what to do about global warming." supra note 111
    • It is hard to quarrel, however, with Weitzman's statement that "[e]ven just acknowledging more openly the incredible magnitude of the deep structural uncertainties that are involved in climate-change analysis . . . might go a long way toward elevating the level of public discourse concerning what to do about global warming." Weitzman, supra note 111, at 18.
    • Weitzman1
  • 243
    • 79956106392 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra text accompanying notes 116-33
    • See supra text accompanying notes 116-33.
  • 244
    • 79956097118 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 80.
    • See Sunstein, supra note 80.
    • Sunstein1
  • 245
    • 79956136408 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Another attempt to provide a rigorous basis for the precautionary principle can be found in, supra note 77, (recommending precaution when "prudence is larger . . . than twice the absolute aversion to risk")
    • Another attempt to provide a rigorous basis for the precautionary principle can be found in Gollier, Jullien & Treich, supra note 77, at 239 (recommending precaution when "prudence is larger . . . than twice the absolute aversion to risk")
    • Gollier1    Jullien2    Treich3
  • 246
    • 0035054567 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Complex ecologic-economic dynamics and environmental policy
    • 32, (applying, among other theories, the precautionary principle to fishery management and commenting that "the Precautionary Principle is crucial in situations with critical threshold levels or effects")
    • see also J. Barkley Rosser, Jr., Complex Ecologic-Economic Dynamics and Environmental Policy, 37 ECOLOGICAL ECON. 23, 32 (2001) (applying, among other theories, the precautionary principle to fishery management and commenting that "the Precautionary Principle is crucial in situations with critical threshold levels or effects").
    • (2001) Ecological Econ. , vol.37 , pp. 23
    • Rosser Jr., J.B.1
  • 247
    • 79956075240 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 180, (stating that "the discounted value of world consumption is in the order of $1016)
    • Nordhaus, supra note 180, at 14 (stating that "the discounted value of world consumption is in the order of $1016).
    • Nordhaus1
  • 248
    • 79956068480 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1
    • STERN, supra note 1, at 187.
    • Stern1
  • 249
    • 79956088128 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1, explains, these numbers are controversial but they are at least illustrative
    • As Cole, supra note 1, at 62, explains, these numbers are controversial but they are at least illustrative.
    • Cole1
  • 250
    • 79956062855 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Key development data and statistics
    • (last visited Dec. 20)
    • See Key Development Data and Statistics, THEWORLD BANK, http://econ.worldbank.org/WBSITE/EXTERNAL/DATASTATISTICS/0,,contentMDK: 20535285%A0menuPK:1192694%A0pagePK:64133150%A0piPK:64133175%A0theSitePK:239419, 00.html (last visited Dec. 20, 2010).
    • (2010) Theworld Bank
  • 251
    • 79956099547 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A caveat is that we could downplay the potential catastrophic possibilities if, as Nordhaus argues, we could learn that catastrophe is impending fast enough to make a sufficiently quick and vigorous global response to head off the possibility. supra note 180, In my view, Nordhaus is excessively optimistic about this last-minute policy response, in part because of the potential for "climate surprises" involving abrupt climate change that might not leave a great deal of time for a response
    • A caveat is that we could downplay the potential catastrophic possibilities if, as Nordhaus argues, we could learn that catastrophe is impending fast enough to make a sufficiently quick and vigorous global response to head off the possibility. See Nordhaus, supra note 180, at 20. In my view, Nordhaus is excessively optimistic about this last-minute policy response, in part because of the potential for "climate surprises" involving abrupt climate change that might not leave a great deal of time for a response.
    • Nordhaus1
  • 252
    • 27644495587 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ("The more likely circumstance . . . is that we are not going to predict the future with any degree of confidence-that climate surprises are inevitable."). Nevertheless, the potential for detecting and heading off catastrophic climate change does need to be considered as part of the analysis
    • See JOHN D. COX, CLIMATE CRASH: ABRUPT CLIMATE CHANGE AND WHAT IT MEANS FOR OUR FUTURE 189 (2005) ("The more likely circumstance . . . is that we are not going to predict the future with any degree of confidence-that climate surprises are inevitable."). Nevertheless, the potential for detecting and heading off catastrophic climate change does need to be considered as part of the analysis.
    • (2005) Climate Crash: Abrupt Climate Change and what it Means for our Future , pp. 189
    • Cox, J.D.1
  • 253
    • 69649104340 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Climate policy: Separating fact from fantasy
    • As Robert Hahn explains: [I]f one believes that the probability of a catastrophe is high, and the costs of a catastrophe are enormous, there may be a rationale for throwing the "kitchen sink" at the problem. For now, though, we have barely thrown anything at the problem, and the critical question facing politicians is what reasonable next steps in the real world might look like. 577, (footnote omitted). I believe that a high level of uncertainty, even without knowledge of a high probability, is sufficient to justify strenuous climate mitigation efforts, but Hahn's point about the gap between the required response and the current situation is well taken
    • As Robert Hahn explains: [I]f one believes that the probability of a catastrophe is high, and the costs of a catastrophe are enormous, there may be a rationale for throwing the "kitchen sink" at the problem. For now, though, we have barely thrown anything at the problem, and the critical question facing politicians is what reasonable next steps in the real world might look like. Robert W. Hahn, Climate Policy: Separating Fact from Fantasy, 33 HARV. ENVTL. L. REV. 557, 577 (2009) (footnote omitted). I believe that a high level of uncertainty, even without knowledge of a high probability, is sufficient to justify strenuous climate mitigation efforts, but Hahn's point about the gap between the required response and the current situation is well taken.
    • (2009) Harv. Envtl. L. Rev. , vol.33 , pp. 557
    • Hahn, R.W.1
  • 254
    • 84860256761 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For this reason, despite its risks, geoengineering needs to be considered as a fallback measure if mitigation efforts are unsuccessful in limiting climate change to noncatastrophic levels. (World Bank, Policy Research Working Paper No. 5127), available at
    • For this reason, despite its risks, geoengineering needs to be considered as a fallback measure if mitigation efforts are unsuccessful in limiting climate change to noncatastrophic levels. See Carolyn Kousky, Olga Rostapshova, Michael Toman & Richard Zeckhauser, Responding to Threats of Climate Change Mega-Catastrophes 11-12 (World Bank, Policy Research Working Paper No. 5127, 2009), available at http://go.worldbank.org/OIXDV8KSN0.
    • (2009) Responding to Threats of Climate Change Mega-Catastrophes , pp. 11-12
    • Kousky, C.1    Rostapshova, O.2    Toman, M.3    Zeckhauser, R.4
  • 255
    • 79956086040 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1
    • STERN, supra note 1, at 466.
    • Stern1
  • 256
    • 79956132938 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id. at 483.
    • Stern1
  • 257
    • 17044390236 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To get a sense of the potential economic impact, consider the following estimates regarding sea-level rise: a half-meter sea-level rise would place $185 billion of property in jeopardy by 2100, and the cost of protecting all developed areas from a half-meter rise would be $50 to $66 billion.
    • To get a sense of the potential economic impact, consider the following estimates regarding sea-level rise: a half-meter sea-level rise would place $185 billion of property in jeopardy by 2100, and the cost of protecting all developed areas from a half-meter rise would be $50 to $66 billion. WILLIAM E. EASTERLING III, BRIAN H. HURD & JOEL B. SMITH, COPING WITH GLOBAL CLIMATE CHANGE: THE ROLE OFADAPTATION IN THE UNITED STATES 14 (2004), http://www.pewclimate.org/global-warming-in-depth/all-reports/ adaptation.
    • (2004) Coping with Global Climate Change: The Role Ofadaptation in the United States , pp. 14
    • Easterling III, W.E.1    Hurd, B.H.2    Smith, J.B.3
  • 258
    • 79956126983 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1
    • See STERN, supra note 1, at 466
    • Stern1
  • 259
    • 77957357989 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Adapting governance to climate change: Managing uncertainty through a learning infrastructure
    • 12-15
    • Alejandro E. Comacho, Adapting Governance to Climate Change: Managing Uncertainty Through a Learning Infrastructure, 59 EMORY L.J. 1, 12-15 (2009).
    • (2009) Emory L.J. , vol.59 , pp. 1
    • Comacho, A.E.1
  • 261
    • 50049112706 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Modeling climate change and its impacts: Law, policy, and science
    • For an extensive discussion of these uncertainties, 1656-57, (discussing the difficulties of making public policy based on computer models that estimate the future effects of climate change)
    • For an extensive discussion of these uncertainties, see Daniel A. Farber, Modeling Climate Change and Its Impacts: Law, Policy, and Science, 86 TEX. L. REV. 1655, 1656-57 (2008) (discussing the difficulties of making public policy based on computer models that estimate the future effects of climate change).
    • (2008) Tex. L. Rev. , vol.86 , pp. 1655
    • Farber, D.A.1
  • 263
    • 38849090083 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stationarity is dead: Whither water management
    • 573
    • See P.C.D. Milly et al., Stationarity is Dead: Whither Water Management, 319 SCIENCE 573, 573 (2008).
    • (2008) Science , vol.319 , pp. 573
    • Milly, P.C.D.1
  • 265
    • 79956132933 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Adaptation of water systems includes a variety of responses. Some responses involve management of water systems through use of longer range predictions to guide water reservoir use. Managing water demand is another option, including increased use of market transfer among users or conservation and efficiency improvements. It is also important to evaluate the risks to water infrastructure posed by more severe floods, which may require investment in existing dams and levees. Additional storage capacity (both surface and groundwater) may also be called for
    • Adaptation of water systems includes a variety of responses. See LEVI D. BREKKE ET AL., U.S. GEOLOGICAL SURVEY, U.S. DEP'T OF THE INTERIOR, CIRCULAR 1331, CLIMATE CHANGE AND WATER RESOURCES MANAGEMENT: A FEDERAL PERSPECTIVE 29-31 (2008). Some responses involve management of water systems through use of longer range predictions to guide water reservoir use. Managing water demand is another option, including increased use of market transfer among users or conservation and efficiency improvements. It is also important to evaluate the risks to water infrastructure posed by more severe floods, which may require investment in existing dams and levees. Additional storage capacity (both surface and groundwater) may also be called for.
    • (2008) U.S. Geological Survey, U.S. Dep't of the Interior, Circular 1331, Climate Change and Water Resources Management: A Federal Perspective , pp. 29-31
    • Brekke, L.D.1
  • 266
    • 79956065423 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Issues of climate adaptation for water projects are explained in, supra note 200, (advocating the use of scenario planning)
    • Issues of climate adaptation for water projects are explained in BREKKE ET AL., supra note 200, at 23-27 (advocating the use of scenario planning).
    • Brekke1
  • 269
    • 79956063831 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra text accompanying notes 135-48
    • See supra text accompanying notes 135-48.
  • 270
    • 79956158687 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Planning for climate change in the Inland empire: Southern California
    • July, 14. Scenario analysis may also help determine what factual issues are critical for deciding between options. This makes it possible to focus climate research on policy-relevant issues. We should not consider the degree of uncertainty to be fixed forever. One role of modeling is to help us identify research priorities that might reduce the range of uncertainties
    • See David G. Groves, Martha Davis, Robert Wilkinson & Robert Lempert, Planning for Climate Change in the Inland Empire: Southern California, WATER RESOURCES IMPACT, July 2008, at 14, 14. Scenario analysis may also help determine what factual issues are critical for deciding between options. This makes it possible to focus climate research on policy-relevant issues. We should not consider the degree of uncertainty to be fixed forever. One role of modeling is to help us identify research priorities that might reduce the range of uncertainties.
    • (2008) Water Resources Impact , pp. 14
    • Groves, D.G.1    Davis, M.2    Wilkinson, R.3    Lempert, R.4
  • 271
    • 79956108018 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ecologic: Nanotechnology, environmental assurance bonding, and symmetric humility
    • For a recent discussion that emphasizes the importance of these uncertainties
    • For a recent discussion that emphasizes the importance of these uncertainties, see Douglas A. Kysar, Ecologic: Nanotechnology, Environmental Assurance Bonding, and Symmetric Humility, 28 UCLA J. ENVTL. L. & POL'Y 201 (2011).
    • (2011) Ucla J. Envtl. L. & Pol'y , vol.28 , pp. 201
    • Kysar, D.A.1
  • 272
    • 79956115660 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nanotechnology and risk
    • For a short overview of the potential regulatory issues, Summer
    • For a short overview of the potential regulatory issues, see J. Clarence (Terry) Davies, Nanotechnology and Risk, RESOURCES, Summer 2009, at 10.
    • (2009) Resources , pp. 10
    • Davies, J.C.1
  • 278
    • 79956140848 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 47. As of 2004, according to the Royal Society, "very few studies have been published on the potential adverse effects that nanoparticles or nanotubes may have on humans, and only one to our knowledge on environmental effects."
    • Id. at 47. As of 2004, according to the Royal Society, "very few studies have been published on the potential adverse effects that nanoparticles or nanotubes may have on humans, and only one to our knowledge on environmental effects."
    • (2004) The Royal Soc'y & the Royalacad. of Eng'g, Nanoscience and Nanotechnologies: Opportunities and Uncertainties
  • 290
    • 79956089744 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nanotechnology-scientific and regulatory challenges
    • 330
    • David B. Fischer, Nanotechnology-Scientific and Regulatory Challenges, 19 VILL. ENVTL. L.J. 315, 330 (2008).
    • (2008) Vill. Envtl. L.J. , vol.19 , pp. 315
    • Fischer, D.B.1
  • 291
    • 79956114626 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 79, argues that the precautionary principle may correct market incentives to avoid investigating possible environmental and health risks
    • Dana, Contextual Rationality, supra note 79, at 18-29, argues that the precautionary principle may correct market incentives to avoid investigating possible environmental and health risks.
    • Contextual Rationality , pp. 18-29
    • Dana1
  • 292
    • 33751309183 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nanotechnology: The challenge of regulating known unknowns
    • 710
    • Robin Fretwell Wilson, Nanotechnology: The Challenge of Regulating Known Unknowns, 34 J.L. MED. & ETHICS 704, 710 (2006).
    • (2006) J.L. Med. & Ethics , vol.34 , pp. 704
    • Wilson, R.F.1
  • 294
    • 34548760340 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Size matters: Regulating nanotechnology
    • This proposal is made in, 396-404
    • This proposal is made in Albert C. Lin, Size Matters: Regulating Nanotechnology, 31 HARV. ENVTL. L. REV. 349, 396-404 (2007).
    • (2007) Harv. Envtl. L. Rev. , vol.31 , pp. 349
    • Lin, A.C.1
  • 295
    • 79956115148 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 206, presents an alternative bonding proposal that emphasizes the role played by worst case outcomes in establishing bond amounts
    • Kysar, supra note 206, at 208-09, presents an alternative bonding proposal that emphasizes the role played by worst case outcomes in establishing bond amounts.
    • Kysar1
  • 296
    • 79956121529 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra text accompanying notes 126-33
    • See supra text accompanying notes 126-33.
  • 297
    • 79956060732 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Editorial, nano-risks: A big need for a little testing: The EPA must act swiftly to evaluate the possible health risks of nanotechnology
    • The EPA has embraced such a research program, but if past practice is a guide, it could take a decade or more before the work even begins. This is not acceptable, Jan.
    • The EPA has embraced such a research program, but if past practice is a guide, it could take a decade or more before the work even begins. This is not acceptable. See Editorial, Nano-Risks: A Big Need for a Little Testing: The EPA Must Act Swiftly to Evaluate the Possible Health Risks of Nanotechnology, SCI. AM., Jan. 2010, at 28.
    • (2010) Sci. Am. , pp. 28
  • 298
    • 34250215212 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A small matter of regulation: An international review of nanotechnology regulation
    • 36
    • See Diana M. Bowman & Graeme A. Hodge, A Small Matter of Regulation: An International Review of Nanotechnology Regulation, 8 COLUM. SCI. & TECH. L. REV. 1, 36 (2007).
    • (2007) Colum. Sci. & Tech. L. Rev. , vol.8 , pp. 1
    • Bowman, D.M.1    Hodge, G.A.2
  • 299
    • 79956072194 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • FIFRA scientific advisory panel considers nanosilver
    • An EPA advisory panel is now considering whether to recommend that nanosilver products be treated as new pesticides requiring a new pesticide registration, 11143-44
    • An EPA advisory panel is now considering whether to recommend that nanosilver products be treated as new pesticides requiring a new pesticide registration. See Lynn L. Bergeson, FIFRA Scientific Advisory Panel Considers Nanosilver, 39 ENVTL. L. REP. 11143, 11143-44 (2009).
    • (2009) Envtl. L. Rep. , vol.39 , pp. 11143
    • Bergeson, L.L.1
  • 301
    • 30744477460 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In brief, D.C. circuit rejects EPA's proposed standards and extends timeline for yucca mountain nuclear waste repository
    • 743
    • Beko Reblitz-Richardson, In Brief, D.C. Circuit Rejects EPA's Proposed Standards and Extends Timeline for Yucca Mountain Nuclear Waste Repository, 32 ECOLOGY L.Q. 743, 743 (2005).
    • (2005) Ecology L.Q. , vol.32 , pp. 743
    • Reblitz-Richardson, B.1
  • 302
    • 27144508494 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note, yucca mountain and reversing the irreversible: The need for monitored retrievable storage in a permanent repository
    • 826
    • David P. Ross, Note, Yucca Mountain and Reversing the Irreversible: The Need for Monitored Retrievable Storage in a Permanent Repository, 25 VT. L. REV. 815, 826 (2001).
    • (2001) Vt. L. Rev. , vol.25 , pp. 815
    • Ross, D.P.1
  • 303
    • 27144508494 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note, yucca mountain and reversing the irreversible: The need for monitored retrievable storage in a permanent repository
    • Id., (citing COMM. ON TECHNICAL BASES FOR YUCCAMOUNTAIN STANDARDS, NAT'L RESEARCH COUNCIL, TECHNICAL BASES FOR YUCCAMOUNTAIN STANDARDS 85, 96 (1995))
    • Id. at 829 (citing COMM. ON TECHNICAL BASES FOR YUCCAMOUNTAIN STANDARDS, NAT'L RESEARCH COUNCIL, TECHNICAL BASES FOR YUCCAMOUNTAIN STANDARDS 85, 96 (1995)).
    • (2001) Vt. L. Rev. , vol.25 , pp. 829
    • Ross, D.P.1
  • 304
    • 79956143655 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 232
    • Ross, supra note 232, at 838.
    • Ross1
  • 305
    • 79956140374 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 42 U.S.C. § 10133(a) (2006)
    • See 42 U.S.C. § 10133(a) (2006)
  • 306
    • 79956115147 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 42 U.S.C. § 10172(a)(1)-(2) (2006)
    • 42 U.S.C. § 10172(a)(1)-(2) (2006).
  • 307
    • 79956135861 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some of the major decisions include Nevada v. U.S. Dep't of Energy, (9th Cir.)
    • Some of the major decisions include Nevada v. U.S. Dep't of Energy, 133 F.3d 1201 (9th Cir. 1998)
    • (1998) F.3d , vol.133 , pp. 1201
  • 308
    • 79956079295 scopus 로고
    • Cnty. of Esmeralda v. U.S. Dep't of Energy, (9th Cir.)
    • Cnty. of Esmeralda v. U.S. Dep't of Energy, 925 F.2d 1216 (9th Cir. 1991)
    • (1991) F.2d , vol.925 , pp. 1216
  • 309
    • 77956796904 scopus 로고
    • Nevada v. Watkins, (9th Cir.)
    • Nevada v. Watkins, 914 F.2d 1545 (9th Cir. 1990)
    • (1990) F.2d , vol.914 , pp. 1545
  • 310
    • 79956063403 scopus 로고
    • Nevada v. Herrington, (9th Cir.)
    • Nevada v. Herrington, 777 F.2d 529 (9th Cir. 1985)
    • (1985) F.2d , vol.777 , pp. 529
  • 311
    • 79956100647 scopus 로고
    • Nevada v. Burford, (D. Nev.)
    • Nevada v. Burford, 708 F. Supp. 289 (D. Nev. 1989).
    • (1989) F. Supp. , vol.708 , pp. 289
  • 312
    • 79956131169 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The current outlook for the nuclear power industry in the United States
    • (Lutz Mez, Mycle Schneider & Steve Thomas eds.)
    • John L. Jurewitz, The Current Outlook for the Nuclear Power Industry in the United States, in INTERNATIONAL PERSPECTIVES OF ENERGY POLICY AND THE ROLE OF NUCLEAR POWER 203, 206-07 (Lutz Mez, Mycle Schneider & Steve Thomas eds., 2009).
    • (2009) International Perspectives of Energy Policy and the Role of Nuclear Power , vol.203 , pp. 206-207
    • Jurewitz, J.L.1
  • 313
    • 68949170460 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Future dim for nuclear waste repository
    • Mar. 6
    • Matthew L. Wald, Future Dim for Nuclear Waste Repository, N.Y. TIMES, Mar. 6, 2009, at A15.
    • (2009) N.Y. Times
    • Wald, M.L.1
  • 314
    • 79956120996 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Yucca mountain; energy department presses for license as if nothing's changed
    • Apr. 4
    • Alexandra Berzon, Yucca Mountain; Energy Department Presses for License as if Nothing's Changed, LAS VEGAS SUN, Apr. 4, 2009, at 1
    • (2009) Las Vegas Sun , pp. 1
    • Berzon, A.1
  • 315
    • 79956088126 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Yucca haunts admin's lagging efforts on nuclear waste study panel
    • Jan. 11
    • Katherine Ling, Yucca Haunts Admin's Lagging Efforts on Nuclear Waste Study Panel, N.Y. TIMES, Jan. 11, 2010, http://www.nytimes.com/gwire/2010/01/11/ 11greenwire-yucca-haunts-admins-lagging-efforts-on-nuclear-24943.html.
    • (2010) N.Y. Times
    • Ling, K.1
  • 316
    • 79956085233 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • McCain: Time for yucca plan B
    • Apr. 1, (quoting John McCain)
    • Steve Tetreault & Keith Rogers, McCain: Time for Yucca Plan B, LAS VEGAS REV.-J., Apr. 1, 2009, at 1B (quoting John McCain).
    • (2009) Las Vegas Rev.-J.
    • Tetreault, S.1    Rogers, K.2
  • 317
    • 79956079296 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 237
    • Jurewitz, supra note 237, at 207.
    • Jurewitz1
  • 318
    • 79956099012 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 239
    • See Ling, supra note 239.
    • Ling1
  • 319
    • 79956120454 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 232
    • Ross, supra note 232, at 815.
    • Ross1
  • 320
    • 79956078374 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id. at 821.
    • Ross1
  • 321
  • 322
    • 79956100103 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id. at 834.
    • Ross1
  • 323
    • 79956158686 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra text accompanying notes 31-35
    • See supra text accompanying notes 31-35.
  • 324
    • 79956139330 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 232
    • Ross, supra note 232, at 838.
    • Ross1
  • 325
    • 79956084161 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It may seem superficially plausible to exclude such remote risks, but some of the unlikely events could have such significant consequences that they are worth considering
    • It may seem superficially plausible to exclude such remote risks, but some of the unlikely events could have such significant consequences that they are worth considering.
  • 326
    • 79956107477 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Suppose that there are ten different risks, each of which is likely to materialize once in fifty thousand years. We would then expect one of these risks to materialize about once every five thousand years, yet the government would not consider them in the analysis. Thus, excluding all events with a less than 1/10,000 probability does not guarantee the safety of the facility for even ten thousand years
    • Suppose that there are ten different risks, each of which is likely to materialize once in fifty thousand years. We would then expect one of these risks to materialize about once every five thousand years, yet the government would not consider them in the analysis. Thus, excluding all events with a less than 1/10,000 probability does not guarantee the safety of the facility for even ten thousand years.
  • 327
    • 79956131702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra text accompanying notes 102-09
    • See supra text accompanying notes 102-09.
  • 328
    • 84959354952 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nuclear Energy Inst., Inc. v. Envtl. Prot. Agency, 1273 (D.C. Cir.)
    • Nuclear Energy Inst., Inc. v. Envtl. Prot. Agency, 373 F.3d 1251, 1273 (D.C. Cir. 2004).
    • (2004) F.3d , vol.373 , pp. 1251
  • 329
    • 79956074699 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As the court explained: With respect to the length of the compliance period, NAS found "no scientific basis for limiting the time period of the individual-risk standard to 10,000 years or any other value." According to the Academy, "compliance assessment is feasible for most physical and geologic aspects of repository performance on the time scale of the long-term stability of the fundamental geologic regime-a time scale that is on the order of 106 [one million] years at Yucca Mountain." NAS also explained that humans may not face peak radiation risks until tens to hundreds of thousands of
    • As the court explained: With respect to the length of the compliance period, NAS found "no scientific basis for limiting the time period of the individual-risk standard to 10,000 years or any other value." According to the Academy, "compliance assessment is feasible for most physical and geologic aspects of repository performance on the time scale of the long-term stability of the fundamental geologic regime-a time scale that is on the order of 106 [one million] years at Yucca Mountain." NAS also explained that humans may not face peak radiation risks until tens to hundreds of thousands of years after disposal, "or even farther into the future." Id. at 1267 (citations omitted).
  • 330
    • 79956152223 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. (quoting Public Health and Environmental Radiation Protection Standards for Yucca Mountain, NV, 66 Fed. Reg. 32,074, 32,094 (June 13, 2001) (codified at 40 C.F.R. pt. 197))
    • Id. at 1275 (quoting Public Health and Environmental Radiation Protection Standards for Yucca Mountain, NV, 66 Fed. Reg. 32,074, 32,094 (June 13, 2001) (codified at 40 C.F.R. pt. 197)).
    • (2004) F.3d , vol.373 , pp. 1275
  • 331
    • 79956078926 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Why the French like nuclear energy
    • The problem of nuclear waste disposal has proved intractable even in France, despite that country's general enthusiasm for nuclear power, (last visited Dec. 21)
    • The problem of nuclear waste disposal has proved intractable even in France, despite that country's general enthusiasm for nuclear power. See Jon Palfreman, Why the French Like Nuclear Energy, FRONTLINE, http://www.pbs.org/ wgbh/pages/frontline/shows/reaction/readings/french.html (last visited Dec. 21, 2010).
    • (2010) Frontline
    • Palfreman, J.1
  • 332
    • 79956150652 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Regulatory trust
    • 625-26
    • Rebecca M. Bratspies, Regulatory Trust, 51 ARIZ. L. REV. 575, 625-26 (2009).
    • (2009) Ariz. L. Rev. , vol.51 , pp. 575
    • Bratspies, R.M.1
  • 334
    • 49249135403 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The perils of a half-built bridge: Risk perception, shifting majorities, and the nuclear power debate
    • 61
    • Amanda Leiter, The Perils of a Half-Built Bridge: Risk Perception, Shifting Majorities, and the Nuclear Power Debate, 35 ECOLOGY L.Q. 31, 61 (2008).
    • (2008) Ecology L.Q. , vol.35 , pp. 31
    • Leiter, A.1
  • 335
    • 49249135403 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The perils of a half-built bridge: Risk perception, shifting majorities, and the nuclear power debate
    • Id. Notably, even in France, where the public widely supports nuclear power: "When it came time to develop a waste facility, however, people balked. There were widespread demonstrations and even riots. And the problem has yet to be solved."
    • Id. at 63. Notably, even in France, where the public widely supports nuclear power: "When it came time to develop a waste facility, however, people balked. There were widespread demonstrations and even riots. And the problem has yet to be solved."
    • (2008) Ecology L.Q. , vol.35 , pp. 63
    • Leiter, A.1
  • 336
    • 49249135403 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The perils of a half-built bridge: Risk perception, shifting majorities, and the nuclear power debate
    • Id.
    • Id. at 67.
    • (2008) Ecology L.Q. , vol.35 , pp. 67
    • Leiter, A.1
  • 337
    • 79956076262 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Balancing risks: Nuclear energy & climate change
    • Robert H. Socolow & Alexander Glaser, Balancing Risks: Nuclear Energy & Climate Change, DÆDALUS, Fall 2009, at 31, 36 (2009).
    • (2009) Dædalus, Fall 2009 , vol.31 , pp. 36
    • Socolow, R.H.1    Glaser, A.2
  • 338
    • 79956088702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The case for using nuclear power in this setting is made in Geoffrey Rothwell and Rob Graber, The Role of Nuclear Power in Climate Change Mitigation, in GENERATING ELECTRICITY IN A CARBONCONSTRAINED WORLD 175 (Fereidoon P. Sioshansi ed., 2010). Rothwell and Graber have some concerns about the economics of rapidly ramping up nuclear power but see it as a significant potential component of mitigation strategy: "[N]uclear power is the only central-station, GHG-free alternative that could replace global ever-growing, ever-polluting coal-fired capacity. If utilities and nations are prepared to significantly increase their investment in nuclear power plant construction, nuclear power is capable of making an important contribution to GHG reduction and climate stabilization." Id. at 205
    • The case for using nuclear power in this setting is made in Geoffrey Rothwell and Rob Graber, The Role of Nuclear Power in Climate Change Mitigation, in GENERATING ELECTRICITY IN A CARBONCONSTRAINED WORLD 175 (Fereidoon P. Sioshansi ed., 2010). Rothwell and Graber have some concerns about the economics of rapidly ramping up nuclear power but see it as a significant potential component of mitigation strategy: "[N]uclear power is the only central-station, GHG-free alternative that could replace global ever-growing, ever-polluting coal-fired capacity. If utilities and nations are prepared to significantly increase their investment in nuclear power plant construction, nuclear power is capable of making an important contribution to GHG reduction and climate stabilization." Id. at 205.
  • 339
    • 77955631040 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For discussion of the prospects of nuclear power expansion as a response to climate change, (stating that nuclear power is "Green," and that new reactor designs are "even more [green]"); Harold A. Feiveson, A Skeptic's View of Nuclear Energy, DÆDALUS, FALL 2009, at 60, 68 (discussing nuclear energy prospects and expressing "a strong cautionary note to the confident projections of an inevitable nuclear renaissance"); John W. Rowe, Nuclear Power in a Carbon-Constrained World, DÆDALUS, Fall 2009, at 81, 89 (arguing that, considering global warming and projected future energy demands, "[n]uclear power is inescapably part of the answer to addressing climate change")
    • For discussion of the prospects of nuclear power expansion as a response to climate change, see STEWART BRAND, WHOLE EARTH DISCIPLINE: AN ECOPRAGMATIST MANIFESTO 75-76 (2009) (stating that nuclear power is "Green," and that new reactor designs are "even more [green]"); Harold A. Feiveson, A Skeptic's View of Nuclear Energy, DÆDALUS, FALL 2009, at 60, 68 (discussing nuclear energy prospects and expressing "a strong cautionary note to the confident projections of an inevitable nuclear renaissance"); John W. Rowe, Nuclear Power in a Carbon-Constrained World, DÆDALUS, Fall 2009, at 81, 89 (arguing that, considering global warming and projected future energy demands, "[n]uclear power is inescapably part of the answer to addressing climate change").
    • (2009) Whole Earth Discipline: An Ecopragmatist Manifesto , pp. 75-76
    • Brand, S.1
  • 340
    • 0142138790 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • From here to eternity: Environmental law and future generations
    • Whether we do so depends largely on whether we apply discounting to harms far in the future. Over long time periods, the results of changes in discount rates are enormous. As Cass Sunstein has explained, "[i]f a human life is valued at $8 million, and if an agency chooses a 10% discount rate, a life saved 100 years from now is worth only $581." Cass R. Sunstein, Cost-Benefit Default Principles, 99 MICH. L. REV. 1651, 1711 (2001). Imagine how little a life saved in 10,000 years is worth on this basis. Discounting is particularly controversial in the multigenerational context. For a review of the debate
    • Whether we do so depends largely on whether we apply discounting to harms far in the future. Over long time periods, the results of changes in discount rates are enormous. As Cass Sunstein has explained, "[i]f a human life is valued at $8 million, and if an agency chooses a 10% discount rate, a life saved 100 years from now is worth only $581." Cass R. Sunstein, Cost-Benefit Default Principles, 99 MICH. L. REV. 1651, 1711 (2001). Imagine how little a life saved in 10,000 years is worth on this basis. Discounting is particularly controversial in the multigenerational context. For a review of the debate, see Daniel A. Farber, From Here to Eternity: Environmental Law and Future Generations, 2003 U. ILL. L. REV. 289.
    • U. Ill. L. Rev. , vol.2003 , pp. 289
    • Farber, D.A.1
  • 346
    • 77950467763 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Regulation by deal: The government's response to the financial crisis
    • 471-512
    • Steven M. Davidoff & David Zaring, Regulation by Deal: The Government's Response to the Financial Crisis, 61 ADMIN. L. REV. 463, 471-512 (2009).
    • (2009) Admin. L. Rev. , vol.61 , pp. 463
    • Davidoff, S.M.1    Zaring, D.2
  • 349
    • 79956062853 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • According to Posner: To understand how the difficulty of determining the riskiness of the new financial instruments contributed to the financial crisis, it is helpful to recall a distinction, made long ago by the economist Frank Knight, between two types of risk. One, which he called "risk," is a risk to which a probability can be assigned, and is the kind that insurance companies insure against because they can calculate a premium that will cover the risk. The other, called "uncertainty," is a risk that cannot be quantified. Anyone who insures such a risk is gambling; anyone who rates it (AAA, BB, etc.) is guessing. supra note 264, at
    • According to Posner: To understand how the difficulty of determining the riskiness of the new financial instruments contributed to the financial crisis, it is helpful to recall a distinction, made long ago by the economist Frank Knight, between two types of risk. One, which he called "risk," is a risk to which a probability can be assigned, and is the kind that insurance companies insure against because they can calculate a premium that will cover the risk. The other, called "uncertainty," is a risk that cannot be quantified. Anyone who insures such a risk is gambling; anyone who rates it (AAA, BB, etc.) is guessing. POSNER, supra note 264, at 60.
    • Posner1
  • 350
  • 351
  • 352
  • 354
    • 79956105355 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra text accompanying notes 102-09, 116-21
    • See supra text accompanying notes 102-09, 116-21
  • 356
    • 79956119289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 264
    • POSNER, supra note 264, at 62.
    • Posner1
  • 357
    • 79851505119 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note, a crack in the façade and the whole building came tumbling down: A critical examination of the central banks' response to the subprime mortgage loan crisis and global financial market turmoil
    • 215, ("The subprime market constituted only $600 billion of the $3 trillion mortgage business, yet the spillover has affected hedge funds, private equity, investment banks, commercial paper, and the stock market.")
    • See Kara M. Westercamp, Note, A Crack in the Façade and the Whole Building Came Tumbling Down: A Critical Examination of the Central Banks' Response to the Subprime Mortgage Loan Crisis and Global Financial Market Turmoil, 18 TRANSNAT'L L. & CONTEMP. PROBS. 197, 215 (2009) ("The subprime market constituted only $600 billion of the $3 trillion mortgage business, yet the spillover has affected hedge funds, private equity, investment banks, commercial paper, and the stock market.").
    • (2009) Transnat'l L. & Contemp. Probs. , vol.18 , pp. 197
    • Westercamp, K.M.1
  • 365
    • 67650429623 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. ("[T]he sharp parallel increase in the economy-wide VaR [value at risk] and the bank-wide VaR suggests a break with the past feedback patterns, indicating that macro-financial linkages are now tighter, potentially complicating the policy response to the financial sector problems.")
    • Id. at 98 ("[T]he sharp parallel increase in the economy-wide VaR [value at risk] and the bank-wide VaR suggests a break with the past feedback patterns, indicating that macro-financial linkages are now tighter, potentially complicating the policy response to the financial sector problems.").
    • (2009) Int'l Monetary Fund, Global Financial Stability Report: Responding to the Financial Crisis and Measuring Systemic Risk , pp. 98
  • 367
    • 0042383698 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Uncertainty and overconfidence in time series forecasts: Application to the standard & poor's 500 stock index
    • 193
    • Danielle A. Gordon & Daniel M. Kammen, Uncertainty and Overconfidence in Time Series Forecasts: Application to the Standard & Poor's 500 Stock Index, 6 APPLIED FIN. ECON. 189, 193 (1996).
    • (1996) Applied Fin. Econ. , vol.6 , pp. 189
    • Gordon, D.A.1    Kammen, D.M.2
  • 368
    • 0002812609 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A multifractal walk down wall street
    • Feb., 71
    • See Benoit B. Mandelbrot, A Multifractal Walk Down Wall Street, SCI. AM., Feb. 1999, at 70, 71
    • (1999) Sci. Am. , pp. 70
    • Mandelbrot, B.B.1
  • 369
    • 79956110477 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 272, (describing studies and observations of fat tails and fractals)
    • see also FOX, supra note 272, at 133-34 (describing studies and observations of fat tails and fractals).
    • Fox1
  • 370
    • 0001178567 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the complexities of complex economic dynamics
    • For a discussion of chaos and complexity theory and possible applications to economics, The present discussion does not rely on complexity theory except as a heuristic explanation for certain probability distributions; it is the distribution rather than the explanation that is most relevant
    • For a discussion of chaos and complexity theory and possible applications to economics, see J. Barkley Rosser Jr., On the Complexities of Complex Economic Dynamics, 13 J. ECON. PERSP. 169 (1999). The present discussion does not rely on complexity theory except as a heuristic explanation for certain probability distributions; it is the distribution rather than the explanation that is most relevant.
    • (1999) J. Econ. Persp. , vol.13 , pp. 169
    • Rosser Jr., J.B.1
  • 371
    • 79956081416 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 283
    • Gordon & Kammen, supra note 283, at 193.
    • Gordon1    Kammen2
  • 372
    • 79956062854 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 119, 1078
    • Barberis & Thaler, supra note 119, at 1075, 1078.
    • Barberis1    Thaler2
  • 373
    • 79956110980 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 272
    • See FOX, supra note 272, at 133-35.
    • Fox1
  • 376
    • 79956117677 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 3
    • See BOOKSTABER, supra note 3, at 144-45.
    • Bookstaber1
  • 377
    • 79956077309 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 264
    • POSNER, supra note 264, at xii.
    • Posner1
  • 378
    • 79956063828 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id. at 259-60.
    • Posner1
  • 379
  • 381
    • 79956090226 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a discussion of reform efforts aimed at the subprime market that triggered the crisis, supra note 288
    • For a discussion of reform efforts aimed at the subprime market that triggered the crisis, see SHILLER, supra note 288, at 107-69.
    • Shiller1
  • 382
    • 77957874054 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (reviewing responses to the financial crisis and various reform proposals)
    • See generally HAL S. SCOTT, THE GLOBAL FINANCIAL CRISIS (2009) (reviewing responses to the financial crisis and various reform proposals).
    • (2009) The Global Financial Crisis
    • Scott, H.S.1
  • 383
    • 69249125735 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Code, crash, and open source: The outsourcing of financial regulation to risk models and the global financial crisis
    • Back testing "involves modelers making several hypothetical jumps back in time, inputting historical data that were available at those respective times, and then comparing the predictions of the model with how losses actually unfolded."
    • See Erik F. Gerding, Code, Crash, and Open Source: The Outsourcing of Financial Regulation to Risk Models and the Global Financial Crisis, 84 WASH. L. REV. 127 (2009). Back testing "involves modelers making several hypothetical jumps back in time, inputting historical data that were available at those respective times, and then comparing the predictions of the model with how losses actually unfolded."
    • (2009) Wash. L. Rev. , vol.84 , pp. 127
    • Gerding, E.F.1
  • 384
    • 69249125735 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Code, crash, and open source: The outsourcing of financial regulation to risk models and the global financial crisis
    • Id.
    • Id. at 143.
    • (2009) Wash. L. Rev. , vol.84 , pp. 143
    • Gerding, E.F.1
  • 385
    • 79956151693 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Efforts at stress-testing banks after the financial meltdown are discussed in, supra note 271
    • Efforts at stress-testing banks after the financial meltdown are discussed in Talley & Walden, supra note 271.
    • Talley1    Walden2
  • 386
    • 79956109593 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Other applications exist beyond those discussed in this article. For instance, the question of whether to remove a child from a possibly abusive parent involves great uncertainties about the potentially severe harm to the child from remaining with the parent as well as the psychological harm of removing the parent. Counterterrorism is another obvious application, as are measures to prepare for catastrophic events such as Hurricane Katrina
    • Other applications exist beyond those discussed in this article. For instance, the question of whether to remove a child from a possibly abusive parent involves great uncertainties about the potentially severe harm to the child from remaining with the parent as well as the psychological harm of removing the parent. Counterterrorism is another obvious application, as are measures to prepare for catastrophic events such as Hurricane Katrina.
  • 387
    • 79956120995 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra section I.B.3
    • See supra section I.B.3.
  • 388
    • 79956090228 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra section II.B.2
    • See supra section II.B.2.
  • 389
    • 79956130645 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra section III.C
    • See supra section III.C.
  • 390
    • 79956125912 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra section III.D
    • See supra section III.D.
  • 391
    • 34047227637 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Feb. 12) (transcript available at, "[A]s we know, there are known knowns; there are things we know we know. We also know there are known unknowns; that is to say we know there are some things we do not know. But there are also unknown unknowns-the ones we don't know we don't know. And if one looks throughout the history of our country and other free countries, it is the latter category that tend to be the difficult ones.")
    • Donald Rumsfeld, Sec'y, Dep't of Def., DoD News Briefing (Feb. 12, 2002) (transcript available at http://www.defense.gov/transcripts/transcript.aspx? transcriptid=2636) ("[A]s we know, there are known knowns; there are things we know we know. We also know there are known unknowns; that is to say we know there are some things we do not know. But there are also unknown unknowns-the ones we don't know we don't know. And if one looks throughout the history of our country and other free countries, it is the latter category that tend to be the difficult ones.").
    • (2002) Sec'y, Dep't of Def., DoD News Briefing
    • Rumsfeld, D.1
  • 392
    • 79956158151 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra text accompanying notes 247-50
    • See supra text accompanying notes 247-50.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.