메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 6, Issue 4, 2000, Pages 391-404

Rules, rights, options, and time

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 79955112409     PISSN: 13523252     EISSN: 14698048     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/s1352325200064028     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (7)

References (23)
  • 2
    • 78149353074 scopus 로고
    • 491 U.S. 397
    • See Texas v. Johnson, 491 U.S. 397 (1989).
    • (1989) Texas v. Johnson
  • 3
    • 85022426491 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Texas v. Johnson note
    • See Adler, Texas v. Johnson note 1.
    • Adler1
  • 4
    • 85022437764 scopus 로고
    • 408 U.S. 92 (1972) (unequal treatment of speakers based on content violates freedom of speech); Church of the Lukumi Babalu Aye, Inc. v. City of Hialeah, 113 S. Ct. 2217 (1993) (unequal treatment of religious group because of religious rituals violates right to free exercise of religion). See generally Larry Alexander, Constitutional Theory and Constitutionally Optional Benefits and Burdens, 11 CONST. COMMENT.
    • See Police Department of the City of Chicago v. Mosley, 408 U.S. 92 (1972) (unequal treatment of speakers based on content violates freedom of speech); Church of the Lukumi Babalu Aye, Inc. v. City of Hialeah, 113 S. Ct. 2217 (1993) (unequal treatment of religious group because of religious rituals violates right to free exercise of religion). See generally Larry Alexander, Constitutional Theory and Constitutionally Optional Benefits and Burdens, 11 CONST. COMMENT. 287, 290-92 (1994).
    • (1994) Police Department of the City of Chicago v. Mosley , vol.287 , pp. 290-292
  • 5
    • 3843112131 scopus 로고
    • 326 U.S. 501
    • See Marsh v. Alabama, 326 U.S. 501 (1946).
    • (1946) Marsh v. Alabama
  • 6
    • 85022421450 scopus 로고
    • 342 U.S.
    • See Rochin v. California, 342 U.S. 165, 172-73 (1952).
    • (1952) Rochin v. California , vol.165 , pp. 172-173
  • 9
    • 85022370237 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • WHOM DOES THE CONSTITUTION COMMAND? note 5, at
    • See Alexander, WHOM DOES THE CONSTITUTION COMMAND? note 5, at 290-92.
    • Alexander1
  • 11
    • 0041830747 scopus 로고
    • 330 U.S. 1 (upholding as constitutional the provision of public transportation to parochial school students).
    • Cf. Everson v. Board of Education, 330 U.S. 1 (1947) (upholding as constitutional the provision of public transportation to parochial school students).
    • (1947) Everson v. Board of Education
  • 13
    • 77950579318 scopus 로고
    • 465 U.S. 668, 687-94 (O'Connor, J., concurring).
    • See, e.g., Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U.S. 668, 687-94 (1984) (O'Connor, J., concurring).
    • (1984) Lynch v. Donnelly
  • 17
    • 85022372268 scopus 로고
    • DEMOCRACY AND DISTRUST note 5, at 296-99, and in Larry A. Alexander, Modern Equal Protection Theories: A Metatheoretical Taxonomy and Critique, 42 OHIO ST. L.J.
    • A similar example is used in Alexander, DEMOCRACY AND DISTRUST note 5, at 296-99, and in Larry A. Alexander, Modern Equal Protection Theories: A Metatheoretical Taxonomy and Critique, 42 OHIO ST. L.J. 3, 24-39 (1981).
    • (1981) A similar example is used in Alexander , vol.3 , pp. 24-39
  • 18
    • 57049184461 scopus 로고
    • 397 U.S. 471 (rejecting the notion that welfare, though constitutionally permissible, is a “fundamental interest” under the Constitution).
    • See Dandridge v. Williams, 397 U.S. 471 (1970) (rejecting the notion that welfare, though constitutionally permissible, is a “fundamental interest” under the Constitution).
    • (1970) Dandridge v. Williams
  • 21
    • 85022349163 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • CAL. CONST. art. 1, § 31. Administrators who select facially nonracial admissions criteria “in order to promote racial diversity” are not avoiding the law but are violating it. They are choosing close proxies for race for racial reasons, and we must assume that if the reasons remain constant over time, the proxies will change if necessary. See Alexander & Cole, U.S. 598 note 25. The real rule is “admit so as to promote racial diversity,” which is forbidden.
    • This analysis also shows the futility of recent attempts to get around such antidiscrimination laws as California's Proposition 209, which prohibits, inter alia, racial discrimination in admissions to public universities. CAL. CONST. art. 1, § 31. Administrators who select facially nonracial admissions criteria “in order to promote racial diversity” are not avoiding the law but are violating it. They are choosing close proxies for race for racial reasons, and we must assume that if the reasons remain constant over time, the proxies will change if necessary. See Alexander & Cole, U.S. 598 note 25. The real rule is “admit so as to promote racial diversity,” which is forbidden.
    • This analysis also shows the futility of recent attempts to get around such antidiscrimination laws as California's Proposition 209, which prohibits, inter alia, racial discrimination in admissions to public universities.
  • 22
    • 85022416890 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The status quo is no more constitutionally privileged than change, given that the status quo may itself be the product of improperly motivated failure to act. And that means that the courts must impose a remedy whenever they find a constitutionally improper rule that renders the entire set of optional rules unconstitutional. However, given that there are perhaps many constitutionally optional alternative sets of rules, which such set should they impose? They cannot evade this problem, because the legislature may not act. And if the legislature does not act, the corpus juris must be judicially altered. But which of the alternative sets of rules should be chosen? (Notice how this problem of remedy is merely the flip side of the problem of standing mentioned in note 25 This analysis also shows the futility of recent attempts to get around such antidiscrimination laws as California's Proposition 209, which prohibits, inter alia, racial discrimination in admissions to public universities.) See also Alexander, This analysis also shows the futility of recent attempts to get around such antidiscrimination laws as California's Proposition 209, which prohibits, inter alia, racial discrimination in admissions to public universities. note 5, at
    • Because legislative purposes can render otherwise constitutionally optional rules unconstitutional, improperly motivated legislative inaction and repeals of rules are as unconstitutional as improperly motivated enactments. The status quo is no more constitutionally privileged than change, given that the status quo may itself be the product of improperly motivated failure to act. And that means that the courts must impose a remedy whenever they find a constitutionally improper rule that renders the entire set of optional rules unconstitutional. However, given that there are perhaps many constitutionally optional alternative sets of rules, which such set should they impose? They cannot evade this problem, because the legislature may not act. And if the legislature does not act, the corpus juris must be judicially altered. But which of the alternative sets of rules should be chosen? (Notice how this problem of remedy is merely the flip side of the problem of standing mentioned in note 25 This analysis also shows the futility of recent attempts to get around such antidiscrimination laws as California's Proposition 209, which prohibits, inter alia, racial discrimination in admissions to public universities.) See also Alexander, This analysis also shows the futility of recent attempts to get around such antidiscrimination laws as California's Proposition 209, which prohibits, inter alia, racial discrimination in admissions to public universities. note 5, at 307-09.
    • Because legislative purposes can render otherwise constitutionally optional rules unconstitutional, improperly motivated legislative inaction and repeals of rules are as unconstitutional as improperly motivated enactments. , pp. 307-309


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.