-
1
-
-
79959767411
-
-
Note
-
The discussion in this essay is restricted to offenses designed to prevent harm to others; that is, within the scope of the harm principle.
-
-
-
-
2
-
-
79959702745
-
-
Indeed, possession of a handgun is prohibited altogether within England and Wales: Firearms (Amendments) Act, UK), chap. 5
-
Indeed, possession of a handgun is prohibited altogether within England and Wales: Firearms (Amendments) Act 1997 (UK), chap. 5.
-
(1997)
-
-
-
3
-
-
84922552640
-
-
We adopt the usage from, New York: Oxford University Press, 160 and, more generally
-
We adopt the usage from D. Husak, Overcriminalization: The Limits of Criminal Law (New York: Oxford University Press, 2007), 160 and, more generally, 159-77.
-
(2007)
Overcriminalization: The Limits of Criminal Law
, pp. 159-177
-
-
Husak, D.1
-
4
-
-
79959724688
-
-
Or, in some jurisdictions
-
Or, in some jurisdictions, "soliciting."
-
Soliciting
-
-
-
5
-
-
2442630116
-
The presumption of innocence brought home? Kebilene deconstructed
-
our own analysis below, we shall use slightly different definitions
-
Cf. P. Roberts, "The Presumption of Innocence Brought Home? Kebilene Deconstructed," Law Quarterly Review 44 (2002): 48, 55-56. In our own analysis below, we shall use slightly different definitions.
-
(2002)
Law Quarterly Review
, vol.44
-
-
Roberts, P.1
-
6
-
-
79959688208
-
-
Theft Act
-
Cf. Theft Act, 1968, s. 25(1): "A person shall be guilty of an offence if, when not at his place of abode, he has with him any article for use in the course of or in connection with any burglary, theft or cheat."
-
(1968)
A Person Shall Be Guilty of An Offence If, When Not At His Place of Abode, He Has With Him Any Article For Use In the Course of Or In Connection With Any Burglary, Theft Or Cheat
, vol.25
, Issue.1
-
-
-
7
-
-
1842618415
-
Extending the harm principle: 'Remote' Harms and fair imputation
-
ed. A. P. Simester and A. T. H. Smith (Oxford, UK: Clarendon
-
A. von Hirsch, "Extending the Harm Principle: 'Remote' Harms and Fair Imputation," in Harm and Culpability, ed. A. P. Simester and A. T. H. Smith (Oxford, UK: Clarendon, 1996), 259.
-
(1996)
Harm and Culpability
, pp. 259
-
-
von Hirsch, A.1
-
8
-
-
33748596887
-
-
See, e.g., Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, chap. 2
-
See, e.g., A. von Hirsch and A. Ashworth, Proportionate Sentencing (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 2005), chap. 2;
-
(2005)
Proportionate Sentencing
-
-
von Hirsch, A.1
Ashworth, A.2
-
9
-
-
33947593896
-
-
3rd ed. (Oxford, UK: Hart, chaps. 1, 16
-
A. P. Simester and G. R. Sullivan, Criminal Law: Doctrine and Theory, 3rd ed. (Oxford, UK: Hart, 2007), chaps. 1, 16.
-
(2007)
Criminal Law: Doctrine and Theory
-
-
Simester, A.P.1
Sullivan, G.R.2
-
10
-
-
58149229138
-
Intoxication is never a defence
-
Admittedly, the conclusion that particular conduct is wrongful may itself be dependent on the actor's mens rea (for elaboration of this familiar point, see, e.g., In such cases, the role of mens rea in establishing wrongfulness is none the less distinct from its role in establishing culpability, although in practice the two will overlap
-
Admittedly, the conclusion that particular conduct is wrongful may itself be dependent on the actor's mens rea (for elaboration of this familiar point, see, e.g., A. P. Simester, "Intoxication is Never a Defence," Criminal Law Review 14 [2009]: 3, 10-11). In such cases, the role of mens rea in establishing wrongfulness is none the less distinct from its role in establishing culpability, although in practice the two will overlap.
-
(2009)
Criminal Law Review
, vol.14
-
-
Simester, A.P.1
-
11
-
-
44549088794
-
-
Cf. Model Penal Code, § 2.02(b) (substantial risk a prerequisite of recklessness or negligence
-
Husak, Overcriminalization, 162. Cf. Model Penal Code, § 2.02(b) (substantial risk a prerequisite of recklessness or negligence).
-
Overcriminalization
, pp. 162
-
-
Husak1
-
13
-
-
79959690814
-
-
Note
-
It is worth observing of the second constraint that many effective substantiveinchoate offenses tend by their nature to advance our interest in harm-prevention indirectly rather than directly, suggesting that Husak's more general principle may need qualification.
-
-
-
-
14
-
-
79959760414
-
-
The standard analysis is outlined in von Hirsch
-
The standard analysis is outlined in von Hirsch, "Extending the Harm Principle," 261-62.
-
Extending the Harm Principle
, pp. 261-262
-
-
-
16
-
-
0003439620
-
-
The proposal has some pedigree: see, New York: Oxford University Press
-
The proposal has some pedigree: see J. Feinberg, Harm to Others (New York: Oxford University Press, 1984), 109-114;
-
(1984)
Harm to Others
, pp. 109-114
-
-
Feinberg, J.1
-
17
-
-
4143152965
-
The nature and justifiability of nonconsummate offenses
-
D. Husak, "The Nature and Justifiability of Nonconsummate Offenses," Arizona Law Review 37 (1995):151;
-
(1995)
Arizona Law Review
, vol.37
, pp. 151
-
-
Husak, D.1
-
20
-
-
75749144380
-
Why distinguish intention from foresight?
-
For development of this line of thought, see, Simester and Smith
-
For development of this line of thought, see A. P. Simester, "Why Distinguish Intention From Foresight?" in Simester and Smith, Harm and Culpability, 71.
-
Harm and Culpability
, pp. 71
-
-
Simester, A.P.1
-
21
-
-
79959747236
-
Directly
-
We omit here Husak's additional criterion, which is intended to exclude consequences brought about by intervening wrongdoers. The work done by that criterion in excluding autonomous intervening actors is adequately reflected within more sophisticated legal tests of causation
-
We omit here Husak's additional criterion, "directly" (Overcriminalization, 162), which is intended to exclude consequences brought about by intervening wrongdoers. The work done by that criterion in excluding autonomous intervening actors is adequately reflected within more sophisticated legal tests of causation:
-
Overcriminalization
, pp. 162
-
-
-
22
-
-
33947593896
-
-
see, sec. 4.2(iii). Indeed, better reflected, since not all wrongdoers are autonomous, and not all autonomous interveners are wrongdoers
-
see Simester and Sullivan, Criminal Law: Doctrine and Theory, sec. 4.2(iii). Indeed, better reflected, since not all wrongdoers are autonomous, and not all autonomous interveners are wrongdoers.
-
Criminal Law: Doctrine and Theory
-
-
Simester1
Sullivan2
-
23
-
-
34548797897
-
The Mental Element in Complicity
-
This is part of the idea behind joint enterprise liability: see
-
This is part of the idea behind joint enterprise liability: see A. P. Simester, "The Mental Element in Complicity," Law Quarterly Review 122 (2006): 578, 598-600.
-
(2006)
Law Quarterly Review
, vol.122
-
-
Simester, A.P.1
-
24
-
-
79959736453
-
-
Note
-
That is, a principle that makes specific allowance for remote-harm offenses, thus going beyond the standard harms analysis.
-
-
-
-
27
-
-
0003529325
-
-
See, e.g., Oxford, UK: Clarendon
-
See, e.g., J. Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford, UK: Clarendon, 1980), 284;
-
(1980)
Natural Law and Natural Rights
, pp. 284
-
-
Finnis, J.1
-
29
-
-
79959753984
-
-
Note
-
See further the discussion of endangerment offenses, below.
-
-
-
-
30
-
-
34547707593
-
Culpability and mistake of law
-
For discussion of this constraint, see, ed. S. Shute, J. Gardner, and J. Horder (New York: Oxford University Press
-
For discussion of this constraint, see D. Husak and A. von Hirsch, "Culpability and Mistake of Law," in Action and Value in Criminal Law, ed. S. Shute, J. Gardner, and J. Horder (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993), 157.
-
(1993)
Action and Value in Criminal Law
, pp. 157
-
-
Husak, D.1
von Hirsch, A.2
-
32
-
-
84919663917
-
Criminalizing endangerment
-
R. A. Duff and S. P. Green (New York: Oxford University Press, sec. 2. Our usage of "endangerment" differs from Duff's, in that it includes hostile "attacks" on an interest or value
-
Cf. R. A. Duff, "Criminalizing Endangerment," in Defining Crimes: Essays on the Special Part of the Criminal Law, ed. R. A. Duff and S. P. Green (New York: Oxford University Press, 2005), 43, sec. 2. Our usage of "endangerment" differs from Duff's, in that it includes hostile "attacks" on an interest or value.
-
(2005)
Defining Crimes: Essays On the Special Part of the Criminal Law
, pp. 43
-
-
Duff, R.A.1
-
33
-
-
79959754842
-
-
Note
-
Although not the only reason: for example, evidential uncertainty about an actor's intentions is typically greater at the point of preliminary conduct, which is likely to be ambiguous in character.
-
-
-
-
34
-
-
79959710803
-
-
Note
-
Interestingly, Husak has moved his own position on this issue, now favoring a rebuttable presumption against overinclusive prohibitions rather than an outright ban
-
-
-
-
36
-
-
0346860472
-
Reasonable risk creation and overinclusive legislation
-
compare his
-
compare his ";";Reasonable Risk Creation and Overinclusive Legislation," Buffalo Criminal Law Review 1 (1998): 599.
-
(1998)
Buffalo Criminal Law Review
, vol.1
, pp. 599
-
-
-
37
-
-
79959699211
-
-
Note
-
We assume here that the abstract-endangerment offense being considered is the least overinclusive formulation available. To this extent, we agree with Husak that offenses should be no more extensive than is necessary to achieve their (justified) objectives.
-
-
-
-
39
-
-
79959750910
-
-
Thus abstract endangerment formulations can also advance rule-of-law values see Simester and Sullivan, sec. 2.3
-
Thus abstract endangerment formulations can also advance rule-of-law values see Simester and Sullivan, Criminal Law: Doctrine and Theory, sec. 2.3.
-
Criminal Law: Doctrine and Theory
-
-
-
40
-
-
79959699662
-
-
Note
-
Selecting exceptions on the basis of identified qualifications helps circumvent the objection that they are ad hoc or a matter of self-identification*the obverse case, in effect, of restrictions imposed on those holding a provisional licence.
-
-
-
-
41
-
-
79959771622
-
-
Note
-
We are grateful for discussions with Nils Jareborg that prompted this line of thought.
-
-
-
-
42
-
-
79959708062
-
-
Note
-
Such a prohibition would be an instance of conjunctive harm, discussed below.
-
-
-
-
43
-
-
79959757245
-
-
the section on, above
-
Cf. the section on "Husak's Constraints" above.
-
Husak's Constraints
-
-
-
44
-
-
79959734091
-
-
Note
-
Completed attempts might also require intervening actors; but in such cases the interventions are typically not autonomous and free (as when D lays a trap, but V must still walk into it). Even if some completed attempts still require autonomous interventions, that possibility can generally be neglected since the remaining completedattempt cases are likely to justify criminalization on probabilistic, endangermentbased grounds.
-
-
-
-
45
-
-
79959691998
-
-
Note
-
By contrast with complicity liability, where S's liability lies partly in P's hands:
-
-
-
-
47
-
-
79959750910
-
-
A fair labelling concern: see Simester and Sullivan, sec. 2.4
-
A fair labelling concern: see Simester and Sullivan, Criminal Law: Doctrine and Theory, sec. 2.4.
-
Criminal Law: Doctrine and Theory
-
-
-
49
-
-
79959739204
-
Criminalizing endangerment
-
Duff
-
Duff, "Criminalizing Endangerment," in Duff and Green, Defining Crimes, 43, 64;
-
Duff and Green, Defining Crimes
, vol.43
, pp. 64
-
-
-
51
-
-
79959748973
-
-
Note
-
Perhaps the most obvious example is the incomplete attempt, in which S's act of σ-ing is performed in order to facilitate, or as part of, S's own act of φ-ing. As we shall see, however, such a close connection is not always required.
-
-
-
-
52
-
-
79959690347
-
-
R. v. Brown, 1 AC 212
-
R. v. Brown [1994] 1 AC 212, 246.
-
(1994)
, pp. 246
-
-
-
53
-
-
79959759494
-
-
Note
-
Although Saturday Night Specials may lie closer to that status than do many other weapons.
-
-
-
-
54
-
-
79959741789
-
-
Note
-
Once in place, handgun laws may themselves help to shape differences in cultural traditions. However, though this may be a legitimate bootstrap consideration, it cannot be relied upon to justify the initial proscription.
-
-
-
-
55
-
-
79959714045
-
-
Note
-
This is not to deny that there may be further reasons why S should be treated differently, and we note this possibility in the discussion of mediating considerations below.
-
-
-
-
57
-
-
79959693352
-
-
Note
-
Note that this earlier paper treats these considerations differently, analyzing them as an imputation issue. We now think the problem is not one of responsibility but rather of freedom, in that burdens of compliance may interfere too greatly with S's freedom of choice.
-
-
-
-
58
-
-
79959715432
-
-
Note
-
This argument is distinct from a ruleof-law claim about greater notice: that the specialist is better able to inform himself of the specific rules applicable to this activity. The notice problem could, for non-specialists, be overcome by taking measures to publicize the rule, etc.
-
-
-
-
59
-
-
79959734090
-
-
Husak requires only that "statutes are designed to prohibit a nontrivial harm or evil" and defines "consummate" offenses as those in which "each act-token of an acttype proscribed. produces a harm or evil, In this essay, we have preferred the term "constitutive" to "consummate," principally in order to preserve the distinction outlined here in the text
-
Husak requires only that "statutes are designed to prohibit a nontrivial harm or evil" and defines "consummate" offenses as those in which "each act-token of an acttype proscribed. produces a harm or evil" (Husak, Overcriminalization, 66, 160). In this essay, we have preferred the term "constitutive" to "consummate," principally in order to preserve the distinction outlined here in the text.
-
Overcriminalization
, vol.66
, pp. 160
-
-
Husak1
-
60
-
-
79959766527
-
Criminalizing Endangerment
-
Duff, sec. 2
-
Duff, "Criminalizing Endangerment," in Duff and Green, Defining Crimes, 43, sec. 2.
-
Duff and Green, Defining Crimes
, vol.43
-
-
|