메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 118, Issue , 1998, Pages 140-154

The Etymologies in Plato's Cratylus

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 79953463262     PISSN: 00754269     EISSN: 20414099     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.2307/632235     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (59)

References (52)
  • 1
    • 60949130021 scopus 로고
    • The Cratylus
    • Leiden This assumption still underlies the most recent and in many ways the best study of the kind where the etymological section is interpreted as a sustained satire on attitudes, throughout the entire Greek cultural tradition down to Plato's day, to the relation between reality and language
    • This assumption still underlies the most recent and in many ways the best study of the kind, T.M.S. Baxter, The Cratylus. Plato's Critique of Naming (Leiden 1992), where the etymological section is interpreted as a sustained satire on attitudes, throughout the entire Greek cultural tradition down to Plato's day, to the relation between reality and language.
    • (1992) Plato's Critique of Naming
    • Baxter, T.M.S.1
  • 2
    • 79958763945 scopus 로고
    • Paris Probably Baxter's most important forerunner in this tradition of interpretation is which detects in the etymological section an ‘encyclopedic’ of flux-based theories in cosmology, theology and ethics
    • Probably Baxter's most important forerunner in this tradition of interpretation is V. Goldschmidt, Essai sur le “Cratyle” (Paris 1940), which detects in the etymological section an ‘encyclopedic’ of flux-based theories in cosmology, theology and ethics.
    • (1940) Essai sur le “Cratyle”
    • Goldschmidt, V.1
  • 3
    • 85022929810 scopus 로고
    • 1st ed., London 1865; 3rd ed. ch. 29. Grote's admirable arguments deserve to be read by everyone interested in the interpretation of this dialogue
    • G. Grote, Plato and the Other Companions ofSokrates (1st ed., London 1865; 3rd ed., 1875) 2, ch. 29. Grote's admirable arguments deserve to be read by everyone interested in the interpretation of this dialogue.
    • (1875) Plato and the Other Companions ofSokrates , vol.2
    • Grote, G.1
  • 4
    • 60949898660 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Socrates agonistes: the case of the Cratylus etymologies
    • forthcoming) also regards the etymologies as exegetically serious; her conclusions, if very different from mine, are complementary rather than antithetical
    • Rachel Barney, ‘Socrates agonistes: the case of the Cratylus etymologies’, OSAP 16 (1998, forthcoming) also regards the etymologies as exegetically serious; her conclusions, if very different from mine, are complementary rather than antithetical.
    • (1998) OSAP , vol.16
    • Barney, R.1
  • 5
    • 65849375231 scopus 로고
    • The serious philosophical content of certain etymologies is recognised by Heidelberg
    • The serious philosophical content of certain etymologies is recognised by K. Gaiser, Name und Sache in Platons Kratylos (Heidelberg 1974)
    • (1974) Name und Sache in Platons Kratylos
    • Gaiser, K.1
  • 6
    • 79251550524 scopus 로고
    • Le etimologie del nome di Apollo nel “Cratilo”
    • F. Montrasio, ‘Le etimologie del nome di Apollo nel “Cratilo”’, Rivista di storia della filosofia 43 (1988) 227–59
    • (1988) Rivista di storia della filosofia , vol.43 , pp. 227-259
    • Montrasio, F.1
  • 7
    • 67651142225 scopus 로고
    • L'etimologia del nome Hades nel “Cratilo”. Contributo alio studio della religione in Platone
    • P. Wohlfahrt, ‘L'etimologia del nome Hades nel “Cratilo”. Contributo alio studio della religione in Platone’, Rivista di storia della filosofia 45 (1990) 5–35.
    • (1990) Rivista di storia della filosofia , vol.45 , pp. 5-35
    • Wohlfahrt, P.1
  • 8
    • 0003526552 scopus 로고
    • (Oxford Translating the reading of the new OCT, edited by $ W: $ BTQ: $ Heindorf, Burnet
    • Translating the reading of the new OCT, edited by W.S.M. Nicoll and E.A. Duke, in Platonis Opera vol. 1, ed. (Oxford 1995), $ W: $ BTQ: $ Heindorf, Burnet).
    • (1995) Platonis Opera , vol.1
    • Nicoll, W.S.M.1    Duke, E.A.2
  • 9
    • 85022945505 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ch. 5 is a very useful guide to this background
    • Baxter (n.1) ch. 5 is a very useful guide to this background.
    • , Issue.1
    • Baxter1
  • 10
    • 85022974320 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Tim. 90c
    • Tim , pp. 90c
  • 11
    • 60949831944 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • “Becoming like god” in the Timaeus and Aristotle
    • in T. Calvo and L. Brisson (eds.) see further Sankt Augustin
    • see further, D.N. Sedley, ‘“Becoming like god” in the Timaeus and Aristotle’, in T. Calvo and L. Brisson (eds.), Interpreting the Timaeus-Critias (Sankt Augustin 1997) 327–39.
    • (1997) Interpreting the Timaeus-Critias , pp. 327-339
    • Sedley, D.N.1
  • 12
    • 85022916687 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 369b-c
    • Rep. 369b-c.
    • Rep.
  • 13
    • 0040966665 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge Thus I resist any suggestion that Socrates, departing for once from his project of rhetorical persuasiveness, is here for reasons of his own resorting to an intentionally ridiculous and therefore Unpersuasive device. Cf. especially C.J. Rowe, Plato's Phaedrus (Warminster 1986) 170–2, where the second group of etymologies is ‘deliberately fanciful’ (170) and ‘a kind of reductio ad absurdum’ of the Cratylus thesis that names are a guide to the truth (172)
    • Thus R. Hackforth, Plato's Phaedrus (Cambridge 1952) 59.I resist any suggestion that Socrates, departing for once from his project of rhetorical persuasiveness, is here for reasons of his own resorting to an intentionally ridiculous and therefore Unpersuasive device. Cf. especially C.J. Rowe, Plato's Phaedrus (Warminster 1986) 170–2, where the second group of etymologies is ‘deliberately fanciful’ (170) and ‘a kind of reductio ad absurdum’ of the Cratylus thesis that names are a guide to the truth (172).
    • (1952) Plato's Phaedrus , pp. 59
    • Hackforth, R.1
  • 14
    • 80054493462 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For acceptance of the Cratylus etymologies as at least exegetically serious, see e.g. 375C-D
    • For acceptance of the Cratylus etymologies as at least exegetically serious, see e.g. Plut. De hide et Osiride 375C-D
    • De hide et Osiride
    • Plut1
  • 15
    • 85022962015 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • De comp
    • 3 Usener-Radermacher; Proclus Schol. In Crat. passim
    • Dionysius Hal. De comp. verborum 62.18–63.3 Usener-Radermacher; Proclus Schol. In Crat. passim
    • verborum , vol.62 , pp. 18-63
    • Hal, D.1
  • 16
    • 85022964410 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf 30. Perhaps the most revealing acceptance of etymology is that of Sextus Empiricus, Adversus grammaticos (= Adversus mathematicos 1) 241–7
    • cf. Alcinous, Did. 159.44–160.30. Perhaps the most revealing acceptance of etymology is that of Sextus Empiricus, Adversus grammaticos (= Adversus mathematicos 1) 241–7.
    • Did. , vol.159 , pp. 44-160
    • Alcinous1
  • 17
    • 85022910907 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hermogenes was an intimate enough member of the Socratic circle to be present at Socrates' death
    • Note too that he is familiar with the theory of Forms {Crat. 389–90)
    • Hermogenes was an intimate enough member of the Socratic circle to be present at Socrates' death, Phd. 59b. Note too that he is familiar with the theory of Forms {Crat. 389–90).
    • Phd , pp. 59b
  • 18
    • 85022945725 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Respectively EN 1103a 17–18, 1132a 30–2, 1152b 7, DA 429a 2–4
    • Respectively Phys. 197b 29–30, EN 1103a 17–18, 1132a 30–2, 1152b 7, DA 429a 2–4.
    • Phys. , vol.197b , pp. 29-30
  • 19
    • 85022962280 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • GA 736a 18–21
    • GA , vol.736a , pp. 18-21
  • 20
    • 79954128323 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 18-b 1. In the former he follows the (fairly obvious) derivation from $ at Crat. 406c, but differs from the explanation offered there that the name reflects the goddess's birth from the sea
    • DC 1.9, 279a 18-b 1. In the former he follows the (fairly obvious) derivation from $ at Crat. 406c, but differs from the explanation offered there that the name reflects the goddess's birth from the sea.
    • DC , vol.1 , Issue.9 , pp. 279a
  • 21
    • 80052739572 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 38-b 14. Plato himself has a similar cataclysm theory in his late dialogues—at Timaeus 22b-23c, Critias 109d-110c, and Laws 677a-679e—but the latter two passages explicitly deny that any knowledge is preserved from one civilisation to the next beyond a bare record of some names of great dynasts
    • Metaphysics 12.1074a 38-b 14. Plato himself has a similar cataclysm theory in his late dialogues—at Timaeus 22b-23c, Critias 109d-110c, and Laws 677a-679e—but the latter two passages explicitly deny that any knowledge is preserved from one civilisation to the next beyond a bare record of some names of great dynasts.
    • Metaphysics , vol.12 , pp. 1074a
  • 22
    • 62749083401 scopus 로고
    • Paris Thus contrary to the more favoured but linguistically strained interpretation that the ancients alone know whether it is true or not; at Tim. 40d-e, in a case where the ancients' word cannot be checked, Timaeus insists that it must simply be accepted as true.) In fact Socrates even set out to check the word of a divine authority, the Delphic oracle, despite an extreme reluctance to believe that it could be wrong (Apol. 21b-c)
    • (Thus L. Brisson, Platon, Phedre (Paris 1989), contrary to the more favoured but linguistically strained interpretation that the ancients alone know whether it is true or not; at Tim. 40d-e, in a case where the ancients' word cannot be checked, Timaeus insists that it must simply be accepted as true.) In fact Socrates even set out to check the word of a divine authority, the Delphic oracle, despite an extreme reluctance to believe that it could be wrong (Apol. 21b-c).
    • (1989) Platon, Phedre
    • Brisson, L.1
  • 23
    • 85022926024 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. also where the association of $ with $, the ‘dispensation of (or ‘by’) intelligence’, is meant to invoke law's mythical origin in the age of Cronos as a divine benefaction to mankind, and therefore implicitly the original meaning of the word. Similarly, at Laws 654a the suggested derivation of the word $ from $ is attributed to the gods who first instituted dance
    • Cf. also Laws 714a, 957c, where the association of $ with $, the ‘dispensation of (or ‘by’) intelligence’, is meant to invoke law's mythical origin in the age of Cronos as a divine benefaction to mankind, and therefore implicitly the original meaning of the word. Similarly, at Laws 654a the suggested derivation of the word $ from $ is attributed to the gods who first instituted dance.
    • Laws , vol.714a , pp. 957c
  • 24
    • 85022920955 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Charm. 173e-174a
    • Charm , pp. 173e-174a
  • 25
    • 85022935884 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ion 531b
    • Ion , pp. 531b
  • 26
    • 85022951950 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lack 196d, 199a
    • Lack , vol.196d , pp. 199a
  • 27
    • 85022954483 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf
    • cf. Tht. 179a
    • Tht. , pp. 179a
  • 28
    • 85022917793 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rep. 389d
    • Rep. , pp. 389d
  • 29
    • 85022939300 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Laws 828b.
    • Laws , pp. 828b
  • 30
    • 85022944016 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 44a-b Many scholars, following the lead of Lambinus, have thought that Socrates' interpretation of the dream was itself based, if not on an etymology, at any rate on a linguistic decoding—that of $
    • PI. Crito 44a-b. Many scholars, following the lead of Lambinus, have thought that Socrates' interpretation of the dream was itself based, if not on an etymology, at any rate on a linguistic decoding—that of $.
    • PI. Crito
  • 31
    • 85022969732 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf
    • Cf. Apol 22b-c
    • Apol , pp. 22b-c
  • 32
    • 85022925348 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ion 534c-d
    • Ion , pp. 534c-d
  • 33
    • 85022954951 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Meno 99c.
    • Meno , pp. 99c
  • 34
    • 77955102019 scopus 로고
    • For a full list of occurrences, see Leiden
    • For a full list of occurrences, see A.S. Riginos, Platonica (Leiden 1976) 35–8.
    • (1976) Platonica , pp. 35-38
    • Riginos, A.S.1
  • 35
    • 77953938503 scopus 로고
    • The name of Plato
    • J. Notopoulos, ‘The name of Plato’, CP 34 (1939) 135–45.
    • (1939) CP , vol.34 , pp. 135-145
    • Notopoulos, J.1
  • 37
    • 85022955004 scopus 로고
    • M.J. Osborne and S.G. Byrne (Oxford
    • ‘Attica’, ed. M.J. Osborne and S.G. Byrne (Oxford 1994).
    • (1994) Attica
  • 38
    • 85022909087 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • E.g. no one ascribes Aristotle's name—’ $ = ‘best goal’?—to his pioneering work in teleology. Nor, when (exceptionally) Pythagoras' name was etymologized did any name-change story result
    • E.g. no one ascribes Aristotle's name—’ $ = ‘best goal’?—to his pioneering work in teleology. Nor, when (exceptionally) Pythagoras' name was etymologized (Diog. Laert. 8.21), did any name-change story result.
    • Diog. Laert. , vol.8 , pp. 21
  • 39
    • 85022941454 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fr.
    • Fr. 5A FHS&G.
    • FHS&G , vol.5A
  • 40
    • 85022958425 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • At the mechanical naming of a child after an ancestor is judged liable to be incorrect. This may have been one ground for rejecting ‘Aristocles’. Another may have been that any name with the ‘-cles’ termination, signifying a kind of ‘fame’, must fail to convey the subject's essence. Contrast the ‘crat-’ element in two names of which Cratylus does approve, Socrates and Cratylus, ‘power’ being an intrinsic property (I owe this last point to C.D.C. Reeve's draft introduction to his forthcoming translation of the Cratylus
    • At Crat. 397a-b, the mechanical naming of a child after an ancestor is judged liable to be incorrect. This may have been one ground for rejecting ‘Aristocles’. Another may have been that any name with the ‘-cles’ termination, signifying a kind of ‘fame’, must fail to convey the subject's essence. Contrast the ‘crat-’ element in two names of which Cratylus does approve, Socrates and Cratylus, ‘power’ being an intrinsic property (I owe this last point to C.D.C. Reeve's draft introduction to his forthcoming translation of the Cratylus).
    • Crat. , pp. 397a-b
  • 41
    • 79958934492 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See esp. R. Barney (n.2) for a convincing interpretation of Socrates' etymological performance as an ‘agonistic display’. Cf. also Paris
    • See esp. R. Barney (n.2) for a convincing interpretation of Socrates' etymological performance as an ‘agonistic display’. Cf. also C. Dalimier, Platon, Cratyle (Paris 1998) 16–17.
    • (1998) Platon, Cratyle , pp. 16-17
    • Dalimier, C.1
  • 42
    • 80054543070 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Was Euthyphro the author of the Derveni Papyrus?
    • in A. Laks and G.W. Most (eds.) The Derveni commentator, like Euthyphro, combines being a mantis with being a purveyor of etymologies. Cf. Oxford
    • The Derveni commentator, like Euthyphro, combines being a mantis with being a purveyor of etymologies. Cf. C.H. Kahn, ‘Was Euthyphro the author of the Derveni Papyrus?’, in A. Laks and G.W. Most (eds.), Studies on the Derveni Papyrus (Oxford 1997) 55–63.
    • (1997) Studies on the Derveni Papyrus , pp. 55-63
    • Kahn, C.H.1
  • 43
    • 85022948510 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the acceptability of multiple etymologies, cf. See 406b 5–6 for the principle applied to Artemis, and the multiple etymology of Apollo at 404e-406a. The same principle will explain why Cronos is allowed two etymologies (396b, 402b). Sometimes one decoding may commend itself as superior to another (399d-400b, 404b), but it is only when the two decodings of a word contradict each other that one must necessarily be rejected, as in the case of epistēmē, p. 151 below)
    • On the acceptability of multiple etymologies, cf. Dalimier (n. 29) 43–44. See 406b 5–6 for the principle applied to Artemis, and the multiple etymology of Apollo at 404e-406a. The same principle will explain why Cronos is allowed two etymologies (396b, 402b). Sometimes one decoding may commend itself as superior to another (399d-400b, 404b), but it is only when the two decodings of a word contradict each other that one must necessarily be rejected, as in the case of epistēmē, p. 151 below).
    • Dalimier , Issue.29 , pp. 43-44
  • 45
    • 79954300330 scopus 로고
    • Plato's Cratylus: the order of the etymologies
    • In the table which follows, square brackets indicate subordinate or digressive etymologies, round brackets indicate words which are listed but not etymologised (at least here). I have found no comparably full analysis in the modern literature, although does discern some natural philosophical sequences amounting to a ‘double dialectical progression from complex to simple, from thing to thought to name’
    • In the table which follows, square brackets indicate subordinate or digressive etymologies, round brackets indicate words which are listed but not etymologised (at least here). I have found no comparably full analysis in the modern literature, although R. Brumbaugh, ‘Plato's Cratylus: the order of the etymologies’, Review of Metaphysics 11 (1957–1958) 502–10 does discern some natural philosophical sequences amounting to a ‘double dialectical progression from complex to simple, from thing to thought to name’.
    • (1957) Review of Metaphysics , vol.11 , pp. 502-510
    • Brumbaugh, R.1
  • 46
    • 85022962107 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Xenocrates frr. 264–6 Isnardi Parente = fr. 53 Heinze: a verbatim quotation from Xenocrates' Life of Plato preserved by Simpl
    • Xenocrates frr. 264–6 Isnardi Parente = fr. 53 Heinze: a verbatim quotation from Xenocrates' Life of Plato preserved by Simpl. In Ar. Phys. 1165.33 ff
    • Ar. Phys. , vol.1165 , pp. 33 ff
  • 47
    • 85022944551 scopus 로고
    • Isnardi Parente
    • In Ar. De caelo 12.22 ff., 87.23 ff. For a survey of modern dismissals, see Naples
    • In Ar. De caelo 12.22 ff., 87.23 ff. For a survey of modern dismissals, see Isnardi Parente (Senocrate-Ermodoro, frammenti, Naples 1981) 433–5.
    • (1981) Senocrate-Ermodoro, frammenti , pp. 433-435
  • 48
    • 85022911008 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at is: $
    • The new list, at 437a-c, is: $.
    • The new list , pp. 437a-c
  • 49
    • 84889784630 scopus 로고
    • $ in Plato's Cratylus
    • in L. Ayres (ed.) This is well argued by New Brunswick and London
    • This is well argued by David Robinson, ‘$ in Plato's Cratylus’, in L. Ayres (ed.), The Passionate Intellect (New Brunswick and London 1995) 57–66.
    • (1995) The Passionate Intellect , pp. 57-66
    • Robinson, D.1
  • 50
    • 85022926024 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For the association of Cronos with nous, see also n.17 above on
    • For the association of Cronos with nous, see also n.17 above on Laws 714a, 957c.
    • Laws , vol.714a , pp. 957c
  • 51
    • 85022935202 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • fully argued by
    • fully argued by Wohlfahrt (n.2).
    • , Issue.2
    • Wohlfahrt1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.