-
1
-
-
0029317736
-
Should we hold the (Germ) line?
-
at 173. Parens points out that the argument is an instance of a broader style of analogical reasoning sometimes called the argument from precedent
-
E. Parens, "Should We Hold the (Germ) Line?" Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 23 (1995): 173-76, at 173. Parens points out that the argument is an instance of a broader style of analogical reasoning sometimes called the argument from precedent.
-
(1995)
Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics
, vol.23
, pp. 173-176
-
-
Parens, E.1
-
2
-
-
84895590261
-
-
Baltimore, Md.: Johns Hopkins University Press
-
L.P. Knowles and G.E. Kaebnick, eds., Reprogenetics: Law, Policy, and Ethical Issues (Baltimore, Md.: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2007), ix.
-
(2007)
Reprogenetics: Law, Policy, and Ethical Issues
-
-
Knowles, L.P.1
Kaebnick, G.E.2
-
3
-
-
85036699815
-
-
The enthusiasts are divided on the question whether such uses are merely permissible or sometimes also obligatory. For a defense of the first view
-
The enthusiasts are divided on the question whether such uses are merely permissible or sometimes also obligatory. For a defense of the first view
-
-
-
-
6
-
-
0034752787
-
Procreative beneficence: Why we should select the best children
-
J. Savulescu, "Procreative Beneficence: Why We Should Select the Best Children," Bioethics 15 (2001): 413-26.
-
(2001)
Bioethics
, vol.15
, pp. 413-426
-
-
Savulescu, J.1
-
7
-
-
0034195728
-
The moral significance of the therapy-enhancement distinction in human genetics
-
at 368-69
-
D.B. Resnik, "The Moral Significance of the Therapy-Enhancement Distinction in Human Genetics," Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 9 (2000): 365-77, at 368-69.
-
(2000)
Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics
, vol.9
, pp. 365-377
-
-
Resnik, D.B.1
-
9
-
-
85036717529
-
-
Another influential group of authors writes: "If parents modify phenotype in pursuit of their goal of producing the 'best' offspring they can, then why not add to their arsenal of methods whatever genetic interventions may make it easier to accomplish some of those goals?"
-
Another influential group of authors writes: "If parents modify phenotype in pursuit of their goal of producing the 'best' offspring they can, then why not add to their arsenal of methods whatever genetic interventions may make it easier to accomplish some of those goals?"
-
-
-
-
10
-
-
0003708160
-
-
See, (Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press), I hesitate to count these authors among the proponents of what I call the "parents have always done it" argument, however; they seem less wholeheartedly enthusiastic than Robertson, Harris, and Agar about reprogenetic improvement of offspring
-
See A. Buchanan, D.W. Brock, N. Daniels, and D. Wikler, From Chance to Choice: Genetics and Justice (Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press, 2000), 160. I hesitate to count these authors among the proponents of what I call the "parents have always done it" argument, however; they seem less wholeheartedly enthusiastic than Robertson, Harris, and Agar about reprogenetic improvement of offspring.
-
(2000)
From Chance to Choice: Genetics and Justice
, pp. 160
-
-
Buchanan, A.1
Brock, D.W.2
Daniels, N.3
Wikler, D.4
-
14
-
-
85036702498
-
-
This is not just idle speculation. Recent criminological research suggests that self-control is partly genetically determined
-
This is not just idle speculation. Recent criminological research suggests that self-control is partly genetically determined
-
-
-
-
15
-
-
84992837995
-
Genetic and environmental influences on levels of self-control and delinquent peer affiliation: Results from a longitudinal sample of adolescent twins
-
see, Of course, this means neither that a particular genetic combination has been associated with the trait, nor that there are currently methods for detecting or manipulating that combination
-
see K.M. Beaver et al., "Genetic and Environmental Influences on Levels of Self-Control and Delinquent Peer Affiliation: Results from a Longitudinal Sample of Adolescent Twins," Criminal Justice and Behavior 36, no. 1 (2009): 41-60. Of course, this means neither that a particular genetic combination has been associated with the trait, nor that there are currently methods for detecting or manipulating that combination.
-
(2009)
Criminal Justice and Behavior
, vol.36
, Issue.1
, pp. 41-60
-
-
Beaver, K.M.1
-
16
-
-
85036697769
-
-
For a recent review of current possibilities and limitations of these technologies
-
For a recent review of current possibilities and limitations of these technologies
-
-
-
-
17
-
-
79551583161
-
The science of inheritable genetic modification
-
see, ed. J.E.J. Rasko, G.M. O'Sullivan, and R.A. Ankeny (Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press)
-
see J.E.J. Rasko and D.J. Jolly, "The Science of Inheritable Genetic Modification," in The Ethics of Inheritable Genetic Modification: A Dividing Line? ed. J.E.J. Rasko, G.M. O'Sullivan, and R.A. Ankeny (Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press, 2006), 17-33.
-
(2006)
The Ethics of Inheritable Genetic Modification: A Dividing Line?
, pp. 17-33
-
-
Rasko, J.E.J.1
Jolly, D.J.2
-
19
-
-
85036717131
-
-
That is, discussions of reprogenetic technologies tend to proceed from what Agar calls a "pragmatic optimism" about such technologies
-
That is, discussions of reprogenetic technologies tend to proceed from what Agar calls a "pragmatic optimism" about such technologies
-
-
-
-
21
-
-
85036717650
-
-
Such considerations also clearly advise against clinical research aimed at developing many imagined reprogenetic interventions
-
Such considerations also clearly advise against clinical research aimed at developing many imagined reprogenetic interventions
-
-
-
-
22
-
-
85195774756
-
Can anyone really be talking about ethically modifying human nature?
-
see, ed. J. Savulescu and N. Bostrom (Oxford, U.K.: Oxford University Press), at 38-41
-
see N. Daniels, "Can Anyone Really Be Talking About Ethically Modifying Human Nature?" in Human Enhancement, ed. J. Savulescu and N. Bostrom (Oxford, U.K.: Oxford University Press, 2009), 25-42, at 38-41.
-
(2009)
Human Enhancement
, pp. 25-42
-
-
Daniels, N.1
-
23
-
-
85036719828
-
-
note
-
This is why Aristotle characterizes each virtue as a mean between two vicious extremes, but regarding where that mean is to be found, only says that this is to be determined "by that principle by which the man of practical wisdom would determine it."
-
-
-
-
24
-
-
0003986649
-
-
See, trans. W.D. Ross (Oxford, U.K.: Oxford University Press)
-
See Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, trans. W.D. Ross (Oxford, U.K.: Oxford University Press, 1980), 1107a.
-
(1980)
Nicomachean Ethics
-
-
Aristotle1
-
25
-
-
85036717415
-
-
The nature of techne is most extensively laid out in the Metaphysics
-
The nature of techne is most extensively laid out in the Metaphysics.
-
-
-
-
26
-
-
0004158981
-
-
See, trans. H. Tredennick (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press)
-
See Aristotle, Metaphysics, trans. H. Tredennick (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1980), 980a-982b.
-
(1980)
Metaphysics
-
-
Aristotle1
-
27
-
-
84891872690
-
-
2nd ed. (London, U.K.: Continuum)
-
H-G. Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2nd ed. (London, U.K.: Continuum, 1989), 319
-
(1989)
Truth and Method
, pp. 319
-
-
Gadamer, H.-G.1
-
29
-
-
0001825304
-
To follow a rule ⋯
-
For an excellent discussion of this issue, see, ed. R. Shusterman (Oxford, U.K.: Blackwell), Taylor notes that Wittgenstein's point implies a need for something like Aristotelian phronesis
-
For an excellent discussion of this issue, see C. Taylor, "To Follow a Rule mellip; ," in Bourdieu: A Critical Reader, ed. R. Shusterman (Oxford, U.K.: Blackwell, 1999), 29-44. Taylor notes that Wittgenstein's point implies a need for something like Aristotelian phronesis
-
(1999)
Bourdieu: A Critical Reader
, pp. 29-44
-
-
Taylor, C.1
-
30
-
-
85036701328
-
-
Ibid., 41
-
Ibid., 41.
-
-
-
-
31
-
-
0002453266
-
Practical principles and practical judgment
-
O. O'Neill, "Practical Principles and Practical Judgment," Hastings Center Report 31, no. 4 (2001): 15-23.
-
(2001)
Hastings Center Report
, vol.31
, Issue.4
, pp. 15-23
-
-
O'Neill, O.1
-
33
-
-
85036713186
-
-
Ibid., 385-91
-
Ibid., 385-91.
-
-
-
-
36
-
-
33846127121
-
Liberal eugenics and human nature: Against habermas
-
E. Fenton, "Liberal Eugenics and Human Nature: Against Habermas," Hastings Center Report 36, no. 6 (2006): 35-42.
-
(2006)
Hastings Center Report
, vol.36
, Issue.6
, pp. 35-42
-
-
Fenton, E.1
-
38
-
-
85036720902
-
-
Ibid., 63
-
Ibid., 63.
-
-
-
-
39
-
-
85036722954
-
-
Bernard G. Prusak has provided readers of this journal with an excellent explication and unusually charitable appraisal of Habermas's argument, noting its unavoidably tentative character
-
Bernard G. Prusak has provided readers of this journal with an excellent explication and unusually charitable appraisal of Habermas's argument, noting its unavoidably tentative character.
-
-
-
-
40
-
-
28644449049
-
Rethinking 'liberal eugenics': Reflections and questions on habermas and bioethics
-
See
-
See B.G. Prusak, "Rethinking 'Liberal Eugenics': Reflections and Questions on Habermas and Bioethics," Hastings Center Report 35, no. 6 (2005): 31-42.
-
(2005)
Hastings Center Report
, vol.35
, Issue.6
, pp. 31-42
-
-
Prusak, B.G.1
-
41
-
-
65549094583
-
The parental investment factor and the child's right to an open future
-
D.S. Davis, "The Parental Investment Factor and the Child's Right to an Open Future," Hastings Center Report 39, no. 2 (2009): 24-27.
-
(2009)
Hastings Center Report
, vol.39
, Issue.2
, pp. 24-27
-
-
Davis, D.S.1
-
42
-
-
85036693128
-
-
note
-
Habermas is right to emphasize the child's response to the intervention and the parents' intentions, regardless of whether he is right about the profound effects that the response may have on the child's self-determination.
-
-
-
|